(navigation image)
Home American Libraries | Canadian Libraries | Universal Library | Community Texts | Project Gutenberg | Children's Library | Biodiversity Heritage Library | Additional Collections
Search: Advanced Search
Anonymous User (login or join us)
Upload
See other formats

Full text of "Theory Of Games And Economic Behavior"

^ 

CO DO 

[<OU_1 66986 ^ 



Osmania University Library 

Call No. "7 ^ ' ' " "* Accession No. G? 3 *> 

Author 

Title 



This book should be returned on or before the date 
last marked below. 



THEORY OF GAMES 
AND ECONOMIC BEHAVIOR 



THEORY OF 

GAMES 

AND ECONOMIC 
BEHAVIOR 



By JOHN VON NEUMANN, and 
OSKAR MORGENSTERN 



PRINCETON 
PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS 

1953 



Copyright 1944, by Princeton University Press 

PRINTED IN THE UNITED STATES OP AMERICA 

Second printing (SECOND EDITION), 1947 

Third printing, 1948 

Fourth printing, 1950 

Fifth printing (THIRD EDITION), 1953 

Sixth printing, 1955 



LONDON: GEOFFREY CUMBERLEGE OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS 



PREFACE TO FIRST EDITION 

This book contains an exposition and various applications of a mathe- 
matical theory of games. The theory has been developed by one of us 
since 1928 and is now published for the first time in its entirety. The 
applications are of two kinds: On the one hand to games in the proper sense, 
on the other hand to economic and sociological problems which, as we hope 
to show, are best approached from this direction. 

The applications which we shall make to games serve at least as much 
to corroborate the theory as to investigate these games. The nature of this 
reciprocal relationship will become clear as the investigation proceeds. 
Our major interest is, of course, in the economic and sociological direction. 
Here we can approach only the simplest questions. However, these ques- 
tions are of a fundamental character. Furthermore, our aim is primarily 
to show that there is a rigorous approach to these subjects, involving, as 
they do, questions of parallel or opposite interest, perfect or imperfect infor- 
mation, free rational decision or chance influences. 

JOHN VON NEUMANN 
OSKAR MORGENSTERN. 

PRINCETON, N. J. 
January, 1943. 



PREFACE TO SECOND EDITION 

The second edition differs from the first in some minor respects only. 
We have carried out as complete an elimination of misprints as possible, and 
wish to thank several readers who have helped us in that respect. We have 
added an Appendix containing an axiomatic derivation of numerical utility. 
This subject was discussed in considerable detail, but in the main qualita- 
tively, in Section 3. A publication of this proof in a periodical was promised 
in the first edition, but we found it more convenient to add it as an Appendix. 
Various Appendices on applications to the theory of location of industries 
and on questions of the four and five person games were also planned, but 
had to be abandoned because of the pressure of other work. 

Since publication of the first edition several papers dealing with the 
subject matter of this book have appeared. 

The attention of the mathematically interested reader may be drawn 
to the following: A. Wald developed a new theory of the foundations of 
statistical estimation which is closely related to, and draws on, the theory of 



vi PREFACE TO SECOND EDITION 

the zero-sum two-person game (" Statistical Decision Functions Which 
Minimize the Maximum Risk," Annals of Mathematics, Vol. 46 (1945) 
pp. 265-280). He also extended the main theorem of the zero-sum two- 
person games (cf. 17.6.) to certain continuous-infinite-cases, (" Generalization 
of a Theorem by von Neumann Concerning Zero-Sum Two-Person Games," 
Annals of Mathematics, Vol. 46 (1945), pp. 281-286.) A new, very simple 
and elementary proof of this theorem (which covers also the more general 
theorem referred to in footnote 1 on page 154) was given by L. H. Loomis, 
("On a Theorem of von Neumann," Proc. Nat. Acad., Vol. 32 (1946) pp. 213- 
215). Further, interesting results concerning the role of pure and of mixed 
strategies in the zero-sum two-person game were obtained by /. Kaplanski, 
("A Contribution to von Neumann's Theory of Games," Annals of Mathe- 
matics, Vol. 46 (1945), pp. 474-479). We also intend to come back to vari- 
ous mathematical aspects of this problem. The group theoretical problem 
mentioned in footnote 1 on page 258 was solved by C. Chevalley. 

The economically interested reader may find an easier approach to the 
problems of this book in the expositions of L. Hururicz, ("The Theory of 
Economic Behavior," American Economic Review, Vol. 35 (1945), pp. 909- 
925) and of J. Marschak ("Neumann's and Morgenstern's New Approach 
to Static Economics," Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 54, (1946), 
pp. 97-115). 

JOHN VON NEUMANN 

OSKAR MORGENSTERN 
PRINCETON, N. J. 
September, 1946. 



PREFACE TO THIRD EDITION 

The Third Edition differs from the Second Edition only in the elimination 
of such further misprints as have come to our attention in the meantime, 
and we wish to thank several readers who have helped us in that respect. 

Since the publication of the Second Edition, the literature on this subject 
has increased very considerably. A complete bibliography at this writing 
includes several hundred titles. We are therefore not attempting to give 
one here. We will only list the following books on this subject: 

(1) H. W. Kuhn and A. W. Tucker (eds.), " Contributions to the Theory 
of Games, I," Annals of Mathematics Studies, No. 24, Princeton (1950), 
containing fifteen articles by thirteen authors. 

(2) H. W. Kuhn and A. W. Tucker (eds.), " Contributions to the Theory 
of Games, II," Annals of Mathematics Studies, No. 28, Princeton (1953), 
containing twenty-one articles by twenty-two authors. 

(3) J '. McDonald, Strategy in Poker, Business and War, New York 
(1950). 

(4) J. C. C. McKinsey, Introduction to the Theory of Games, New 
York (1952). 

(5) A. Wald, Statistical Decision Functions, New York (1950). 

(6) J. Williams, The Compleat Strategyst, Being a Primer on the Theory 
of Games of Strategy, New York (1953). 

Bibliographies on the subject are found in all of the above books except 
(6). Extensive work in this field has been done during the last years by the 
staff of the RAND Corporation, Santa Monica, California. A bibliography 
of this work can be found in the RAND publication RM-950. 

In the theory of n-person games, there have been some further develop- 
ments in the direction of " non-cooperative" games. In this respect, 
particularly the work of J. F. Nash, " Non-cooperative Games," Annals of 
Mathematics, Vol. 54, (1951), pp. 286-295, must be mentioned. Further 
references to this work are found in (1), (2), and (4). 

Of various developments in economics we mention in particular "linear 
programming" and the " assignment problem" which also appear to be 
increasingly connected with the theory of games. The reader will find 
indications of this $gain in (1), (2), and (4). 

The theory of utility suggested in Section 1.3., and in the Appendix to the 
Second Edition has undergone considerable development theoretically, as 
well as experimentally, and in various discussions. In this connection, the 
reader may consult in particular the following: 

M. Friedman and L. J. Savage, "The Utility Analysis of Choices Involv- 
ing Risk," Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 56, (1948), pp. 279-304. 

vii 



viii PREFACE TO THIRD EDITION 

J. Marschak, "Rational Behavior, Uncertain Prospects, and Measurable 
Utility/' Econometrica, Vol. 18, (1950), pp. 111-141. 

F. Mosteller and P. Nogee, " An Experimental Measurement of Utility," 
Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 59, (1951), pp. 371-404. 

M. Friedman and L. J. Savage, "The Expected- Utility Hypothesis and 
the Measurability of Utility," Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 60, 
(1952), pp. 463-474. 

See also the Symposium on Cardinal Utilities in Econometrica, Vol. 20, 
(1952): 

H. Wold, "Ordinal Preferences or Cardinal Utility?" 
A. S. Manne, "The Strong Independence Assumption Gasoline 
Blends and Probability Mixtures." 

P. A. Samuelson, "Probability, Utility, and the Independence Axiom." 
E. Malinvaud, "Note on von Neumann-Morgenstem's Strong Inde- 
pendence Axiom." 

In connection with the methodological critique exercised by some of the 
contributors to the last-mentioned symposium, we would like to mention 
that we applied the axiomatic method in the customary way with the cus- 
tomary precautions. Thus the strict, axiomatic treatment of the concept 
of utility (in Section 3.6. and in the Appendix) is complemented by an 
heuristic preparation (in Sections 3.1.-3.5.). The latter's function is to 
convey to the reader the viewpoints to evaluate and to circumscribe the 
validity of the subsequent axiomatic procedure. In particular our dis- 
cussion and selection of "natural operations" in those sections covers what 
seems to us the relevant substrate of the Samuelson-Malinvaud "inde- 
pendence axiom." 

JOHN VON NEUMANN 
OSKAR MORGENSTERN 
PRINCETON, N. J. 
January, 1953. 



TECHNICAL NOTE 

The nature of the problems investigated and the techniques employed 
in this book necessitate a procedure which in many instances is thoroughly 
mathematical. The mathematical devices used are elementary in the sense 
that no advanced algebra, or calculus, etc., occurs. (With two, rather unim- 
portant, exceptions: Part of the discussion of an example in 19.7. et sequ. and 
a remark in A.3.3. make use of some simple integrals.) Concepts originating 
in set theory, linear geometry and group theory play an important role, but 
they are invariably taken from the early chapters of those disciplines and are 
moreover analyzed and explained in special expository sections. Neverthe- 
less the book is not truly elementary because the mathematical deductions 
are frequently intricate and the logical possibilities are extensively exploited. 

Thus no specific knowledge of any particular body of advanced mathe- 
matics is required. However, the reader who wants to acquaint himself 
more thoroughly with the subject expounded here, will have to familiarize 
himself with the mathematical way of reasoning definitely beyond its 
routine, primitive phases. The character of the procedures will be mostly 
that of mathematical logics, set theory and functional analysis. 

We have attempted to present the subject in such a form that a reader 
who is moderately versed in mathematics can acquire the necessary practice 
in the course of this study. We hope that we have not entirely failed in 
this endeavour. 

In accordance with this, the presentation is not what it would be in a 
strictly mathematical treatise. All definitions and deductions are con- 
siderably broader than they would be there. Besides, purely verbal dis- 
cussions and analyses take up a considerable amount of space. We have 
in particular tried to give, whenever possible, a parallel verbal exposition 
for every major mathematical deduction. It is hoped that this procedure 
will elucidate in unmathematical language what the mathematical technique 
signifies and will also show where it achieves more than can be done 
without it. 

In this, as well as in our methodological stand, we are trying to follow 
the best examples of theoretical physics. 

The reader who is not specifically interested in mathematics should at 
first omit those sections of the book which in his judgment are too mathe- 
matical. We prefer not to give a definite list of them, since this judgment 
must necessarily be subjective. However, those sections marked with an 
asterisk in the table of contents are most likely to occur to the average reader 
in this connection. At any rate he will find that these omissions will little 
interfere with the comprehension of the early parts, although the logical 



TECHNICAL NOTE 

chain may in the rigorous sense have suffered an interruption. As he 
proceeds the omissions will gradually assume a more serious character and 
the lacunae in the deduction will become more and more significant. The 
reader is then advised to start again from the beginning since the greater 
familiarity acquired is likely to facilitate a better understanding. 

ACKNOWLEDGMENT 

The authors wish to express their thanks to Princeton University and to 
the Institute for Advanced Study for their generous help which rendered 
this publication possible. 

They are also greatly indebted to the Princeton University Press which 
has made every effort to publish this book in spite of wartime difficulties. 
The publisher has shown at all times the greatest understanding for the 
authors' wishes. 



CONTENTS 

PREFACE v 

TECHNICAL NOTE ix 

ACKNOWLEDGMENT x 

CHAPTER I 
FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

1. THE MATHEMATICAL METHOD IN ECONOMICS 1 

1.1. Introductory remarks 1 

1.2. Difficulties of the application of the mathematical method 2 

1.3. Necessary limitations of the objectives 6 

1.4. Concluding remarks 7 

2. QUALITATIVE DISCUSSION OF THE PROBLEM OF RATIONAL BEHAV- 
IOR 8 

2.1. The problem of rational behavior 8 

2.2. "Robinson Crusoe" economy and social exchange economy 9 

2.3. The number of variables and the number of participants 12 

2.4. The case of many participants: Free competition 13 

2.5. The "Lausanne" theory 15 

3. THE NOTION OF UTILITY 15 

3.1. Preferences and utilities 15 

3.2. Principles of measurement: Preliminaries 16 

3.3. Probability and numerical utilities 17 

3.4. Principles of measurement: Detailed discussion 20 

3.5. Conceptual structure of the axiomatic treatment of numerical 
utilities 24 

3.6. The axioms and their interpretation 26 

3.7. General remarks concerning the axioms 28 

3.8. The role of the concept of marginal utility 29 

4. STRUCTURE OF THE THEORY: SOLUTIONS AND STANDARDS OF 
BEHAVIOR 31 

4.1. The simplest concept of a solution for one participant 31 

4.2. Extension to all participants 33 

4.3. The solution as a set of imputations 34 

4.4. The intransitive notion of "superiority" or "domination" 37 

4.5. The precise definition of a solution 39 

4.6. Interpretation of our definition in terms of "standards of behavior" 40 

4.7. Games and social organizations 43 

4.8. Concluding remarks 43 

CHAPTER II 
GENERAL FORMAL DESCRIPTION OF GAMES OF STRATEGY 

5. INTRODUCTION 46 

5.1. Shift of emphasis from economics to games 46 

5.2. General principles of classification and of procedure 46 



CONTENTS 

6. THE SIMPLIFIED CONCEPT OF A GAME 48 

6.1. Explanation of the termini technici 48 

6.2. The elements of the game 49 

6.3. Information and preliminary 51 

6.4. Preliminarity, transitivity, and signaling 51 

7. THE COMPLETE CONCEPT OF A GAME 55 

7.1. Variability of the characteristics of each move 55 

7.2. The general description 57 

8. SETS AND PARTITIONS 60 

8.1. Desirability of a set-theoretical description of a game 60 

8.2. Sets, their properties, and their graphical representation 61 

8.3. Partitions, their properties, and their graphical representation 63 

8.4. Logistic interpretation of sets and partitions 66 

*9. THE SET-THEORETICAL DESCRIPTION OF A GAME 67 

*9.1. The partitions which describe a game 67 

*9.2. Discussion of these partitions and their properties 7 1 

*10. AXIOMATIC FORMULATION 73 

*10.1. The axioms and their interpretations 73 

*10.2. Logistic discussion of the axioms 76 

*10.3. General remarks concerning the axioms 76 

*10.4. Graphical representation 77 

11. STRATEGIES AND THE FINAL SIMPLIFICATION OF THE DESCRIPTION 

OF A GAME 79 

11.1. The concept of a strategy and its formalization 79 

11.2. The final simplification of the description of a game 81 

11.3. The role of strategies in the simplified form of a game 84 

11.4. The meaning of the zero-sum restriction 84 

CHAPTER III 
ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

12. PRELIMINARY SURVEY 85 

12.1. General viewpoints 85 

12.2. The one-person game 85 

12.3. Chance and probability 87 

12.4. The next objective 87 

13. FUNCTIONAL CALCULUS 88 

13.1. Basic definitions 88 

13.2. The operations Max and Min 89 

13.3. Commutativity questions 91 

13.4. The mixed case. Saddle points 93 

13.5. Proofs of the main facts 95 

14. STRICTLY DETERMINED GAMES 98 

14 1. Formulation of the problem 98 

14.2. The minorant and the majorant games 100 

14.3. Discussion of the auxiliary games 101 



CONTENTS 

14.4. Conclusions 105 

14.5. Analysis of strict determinateness 106 

14.6. The interchange of players. Symmetry 109 

14.7. Non strictly determined games 110 

14.8. Program of a detailed analysis of strict determinateness 111 

*15. GAMES WITH PERFECT INFORMATION 112 

* 1 5 . 1 . Statement of purpose. Induction 112 

*15.2. The exact condition (First step) 114 

*15.3. The exact condition (Entire induction) 116 

*15.4. Exact discussion of the inductive step 117 

*15.5. Exact discussion of the inductive step (Continuation) 120 

*15.6. The result in the case of perfect information 123 

*15.7. Application to Chess 124 

*15.8. The alternative, verbal discussion 126 

16. LINEARITY AND CONVEXITY 128 

16.1. Geometrical background 1 28 

16.2. Vector operations 129 

16.3. The theorem of the supporting hyperplanes 134 

16.4. The theorem of the alternative for matrices 138 

17. MIXED STRATEGIES. THE SOLUTION FOR ALL GAMES 143 

17.1. Discussion of two elementary examples 143 

17.2. Generalization of this viewpoint 145 

17.3. Justification of the procedure as applied to an individual play 146 

17.4. The minorant and the majorant games. (For mixed strategies) 149 

17.5. General strict determinateness 150 

17.6. Proof of the main theorem 153 

17.7. Comparison of the treatment by pure and by mixed strategies 155 

17.8. Analysis of general strict determinateness 158 

17.9. Further characteristics of good strategies 160 

17.10. Mistakes and their consequences. Permanent optimality 162 

17.11. The interchange of players. Symmetry 165 

CHAPTER IV 
ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 

18. SOME ELEMENTARY GAMES 169 

18.1. The simplest games 169 

18.2. Detailed quantitative discussion of these games 170 

18.3. Qualitative characterizations 173 

18.4. Discussion of some specific games. (Generalized forms of Matching 
Pennies) 175 

18.5. Discussion of some slightly more complicated games 178 

18.6. Chance and imperfect information 182 

18.7. Interpretation of this result 185 

*19. POKER AND BLUFFING 186 

*19.1. Description of Poker 186 

*19.2. Bluffing 188 

*19.3. Description of Poker (Continued) 189 

*19.4. Exact formulation of the rules 190 



CONTENTS 

*19.5. Description of the strategy 191 

*19.6. Statement of the problem 195 

*19.7. Passage from the discrete to the continuous problem 196 

*19.8. Mathematical determination of the solution 199 

*19.9. Detailed analysis of the solution 202 

*19.10. Interpretation of the solution 204 

*19.11. More general forms of Poker 207 

19.12. Discrete hands 208 

*19.13. m possible bids 209 

*19.14. Alternate bidding 211 

*19.15. Mathematical description of all solutions 216 

* 19. 16. Interpretation of the solutions. Conclusions 218 

CHAPTER V 
ZERO-SUM THREE-PERSON GAMES 

20. PRELIMINARY SURVEY 220 

20.1. General viewpoints 220 

20.2. Coalitions 221 

21. THE SIMPLE MAJORITY GAME OF THREE PERSONS 222 

21.1. Definition of the game 222 

21.2. Analysis of the game: Necessity of "understandings" 223 

21.3. Analysis of the game: Coalitions. The role of symmetry 224 

22. FURTHER EXAMPLES 225 

22.1. Unsymmetric distributions. Necessity of compensations 225 

22.2. Coalitions of different strength. Discussion 227 

22.3. An inequality. Formulae 229 

23. THE GENERAL CASE 231 

23.1. Detailed discussion. Inessential and essential games 231 

23.2. Complete formulae 232 

24. DISCUSSION OF AN OBJECTION 233 

24.1. The case of perfect information and its significance 233 

24.2. Detailed discussion. Necessity of compensations between three or 
more players 235 

CHAPTER VI 

FORMULATION OF THE GENERAL THEORY: 
ZERO-SUM n-PERSON GAMES 

25. THE CHARACTERISTIC FUNCTION 238 

25.1. Motivation and definition 238 

25.2. Discussion of the concept 240 

25.3. Fundamental properties 24 1 

25.4. Immediate mathematical consequences 242 

26. CONSTRUCTION OF A GAME WITH A GIVEN CHARACTERISTIC 
FUNCTION 243 

26.1. The construction 243 

26.2. Summary 245 



CONTENTS 

27. STRATEGIC EQUIVALENCE. INESSENTIAL AND ESSENTIAL GAMES 245 

27.1. Strategic equivalence. The reduced form 245 

27.2. Inequalities. The quantity y 248 

27.3. Inessentiality and essentiality 249 

27.4. Various criteria. Non additive utilities 250 

27.5. The inequalities in the essential case 252 

27.6. Vector operations on characteristic functions 253 

28. GROUPS, SYMMETRY AND FAIRNESS 255 

28.1. Permutations, their groups and their effect on a game 255 

28.2. Symmetry and fairness 258 

29. RECONSIDERATION OF THE ZERO-SUM THREE-PERSON GAME 260 

29.1. Qualitative discussion 260 

29.2. Quantitative discussion 262 

30. THE EXACT FORM OP THE GENERAL DEFINITIONS 263 

30.1. The definitions 263 

30.2. Discussion and recapitulation 265 
*30.3. The concept of saturation 266 

30.4. Three immediate objectives 271 

31. FIRST CONSEQUENCES 272 

31.1. Convexity, flatness, and some criteria for domination 272 

31.2. The system of all imputations. One element solutions 277 

31.3. The isomorphism which corresponds to strategic equivalence 281 

32. DETERMINATION OF ALL SOLUTIONS OF THE ESSENTIAL ZERO-SUM 
THREE-PERSON GAME 282 

32.1. Formulation of the mathematical problem. The graphical method 282 

32.2. Determination of all solutions 285 

33. CONCLUSIONS 288 

33.1. The multiplicity of solutions. Discrimination and its meaning 288 

33.2. Statics and dynamics 290 

CHAPTER VII 
ZERO-SUM FOUR-PERSON GAMES 

34. PRELIMINARY SURVEY 291 

34.1. General viewpoints 291 

34.2. Formalism of the essential zero sum four person games 291 

34.3. Permutations of the players 294 

35. DISCUSSION OF SOME SPECIAL POINTS IN THE CUBE Q 295 

35.1. The corner /. (and V., VI., VII.) 295 

35.2. The corner VIII. (and //., ///., 7F.,). The three person game and 

a "Dummy" 299 

35.3. Some remarks concerning the interior of Q 302 

36. DISCUSSION OP THE MAIN DIAGONALS 304 

36.1. The part adjacent to the corner VIII.' Heuristic discussion 304 

36.2. The part adjacent to the corner VIII. : Exact discussion 307 
*36.3. Other parts of the main diagonals 312 



CONTENTS 

37. THE CENTER AND ITS ENVIRONS 313 

37.1. First orientation about the conditions around the center 313 

37.2. The two alternatives and the role of symmetry 315 

37.3. The first alternative at the center 316 

37.4. The second alternative at the center 317 

37.5. Comparison of the two central solutions 318 

37.6. Unsymmetrical central solutions 319 

J8. A FAMILY OP SOLUTIONS FOR A NEIGHBORHOOD OP THE CENTER 321 
*38.1. Transformation of the solution belonging to the first alternative at 

the center 321 

*38.2. Exact discussion 322 

*38.3. Interpretation of the solutions 327 

CHAPTER VIII 

SOME REMARKS CONCERNING n ^ 5 PARTICIPANTS 
39. THE NUMBER OF PARAMETERS IN VARIOUS CLASSES OF GAMES 330 

39.1. The situation for n - 3, 4 330 

39.2. The situation for all n ^ 3 330 

10. THE SYMMETRIC FIVE PERSON GAME 332 

40.1. Formalism of the symmetric five person game 332 

40.2. The two extreme cases 332 

40.3. Connection between the symmetric five person game and the 1, 2, 3- 
symmetric four person game 334 

CHAPTER IX 
COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

11. COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION 339 

41.1. Search for n-person games for which all solutions can be determined 339 

41.2. The first type. Composition and decomposition 340 

41.3. Exact definitions 341 

41.4. Analysis of decomposability 343 

41.5. Desirability of a modification 345 

12. MODIFICATION OF THE THEORY 345 

42.1. No complete abandonment of the zero sum restriction 345 

42.2. Strategic equivalence. Constant sum games 346 

42.3. The characteristic function in the new theory 348 

42.4. Imputations, domination, solutions in the new theory 350 

42.5. Essentiality, inessentiality and decomposability in the new theory 351 

13. THE DECOMPOSITION PARTITION 353 

43.1. Splitting sets. Constituents 353 

43.2. Properties of the system of all splitting sets 353 

43.3. Characterization of the system of all splitting sets. The decomposi- 
tion partition 354 

43.4. Properties of the decomposition partition 357 

14. DECOMPOSABLE GAMES. FURTHER EXTENSION OF THE THEORY 358 

44.1. Solutions of a (decomposable) game and solutions of its constituents 358 

44.2. Composition and decomposition of imputations and of sets of impu- 
tations 359 



CONTENTS 

44.3. Composition and decomposition of solutions. The main possibilities 

and surmises 361 

44.4. Extension of the theory. Outside sources 363 

44.5. The excess 364 

44.6. Limitations of the excess. The non-isolated character of a game in 

the new setup 366 

44.7. Discussion of the new setup. E(e Q ) t F(e ) 367 

45. LIMITATIONS OF THE EXCESS. STRUCTURE OF THE EXTENDED 
THEORY 368 

45.1. The lower limit of the excess 368 

45.2. The upper limit of the excess. Detached and fully detached imputa- 
tions 369 

45.3. Discussion of the two limits, |r|i, |r| 2 . Their ratio 372 

45.4. Detached imputations and various solutions. The theorem con- 
necting E(e ), F(e ) 375 

45.5. Proof of the theorem 376 

45.6. Summary and conclusions 380 

46. DETERMINATION OF ALL SOLUTIONS OF A DECOMPOSABLE GAME 381 

46.1. Elementary properties of decompositions 381 

46.2. Decomposition and its relation to the solutions: First results con- 
cerning F( ) 384 

46.3. Continuation 386 

46.4. Continuation 388 

46.5. The complete result in F(e ) 390 

46.6. The complete result in E(e ) 393 

46.7. Graphical representation of a part of the result 394 

46.8. Interpretation: The normal zone. Heredity of various properties 396 

46.9. Dummies 397 

46.10. Imbedding of a game 398 

46.11. Significance of the normal zone 401 

46.12. First occurrence of the phenomenon of transfer: n - 6 402 

47. THE ESSENTIAL THREE-PERSON GAME IN THE NEW THEORY 403 

47.1. Need for this discussion 403 

47.2. Preparatory considerations 403 

47.3. The six cases of the discussion. Cases (I)-(III) 406 

47.4. Case (IV) : First part 407 

47.5. Case (IV): Second part 409 

47.6. Case (V) 413 

47.7. Case (VI) 415 

47.8. Interpretation of the result: The curves (one dimensional parts) in 

the solution 416 

47.9. Continuation: The areas (two dimensional parts) in the solution 418 

CHAPTER X 
SIMPLE GAMES 

48. WINNING AND LOSING COALITIONS AND GAMES WHERE THEY 
OCCUR 420 

48.1. The second type of 41.1. Decision by coalitions 420 

48.2. Winning and Losing Coalitions 421 



CONTENTS 

49. CHARACTERIZATION OP THE SIMPLE GAMES 423 

49.1. General concepts of winning and losing coalitions 423 

'49.2. The special role of one element sets 425 

49.3. Characterization of the systems TF, L of actual games 426 

49.4. Exact definition of simplicity 428 

49.5. Some elementary properties of simplicity 428 

49.6. Simple games and their W, L. The Minimal winning coalitions: W m 429 

49.7. The solutions of simple g^mes 430 

50. THE MAJORITY GAMES AND THE MAIN SOLUTION 431 

50.1. Examples of simple games: The majority games 431 

50.2. Homogeneity 433 

50.3. A more direct use of the concept of imputation in forming solutions 435 

50.4. Discussion of this direct approach 436 

50.5. Connections with the general theory. Exact formulation 438 

50.6. Reformulation of the result 440 

50.7. Interpretation of the result 442 

50.8. Connection with the Homogeneous Majority game. 443 

51. METHODS FOR THE ENUMERATION OF ALL SIMPLE GAMES 445 

51.1. Preliminary Remarks 445 

51.2. The saturation method: Enumeration by means of W 446 

51.3. Reasons for passing from W to W m . Difficulties of using W m 448 

51.4. Changed Approach: Enumeration by means of W m 450 

51.5. Simplicity and decomposition 452 

51.6. Inessentiality, Simplicity and Composition. Treatment of the excess 454 

51.7. A criterium of decomposability in terms of W m 455 

52. THE SIMPLE GAMES FOR SMALL n 457 

52.1. Program, n = 1, 2 play no role. Disposal of n = 3 457 

52.2. Procedure for n ^ 4: The two element sets and their role in classify- 
ing the W m 458 

52.3. Decomposability of cases C*, C n _ 2 , C n _i 459 

52.4. The simple games other than [1, , 1, n 2]* (with dummies): 
The Cases C k , k 0, 1, , n - 3 461 

52.5. Disposal of n = 4, 5 462 

53. THE NEW POSSIBILITIES OF SIMPLE GAMES FOR n ^ 6 463 

53.1. The Regularities observed for n ^ 6 463 

53.2. The six main counter examples (for n * 6, 7) 464 

54. DETERMINATION OF ALL SOLUTIONS IN SUITABLE GAMES 470 

54.1. Reasons to consider other solutions than the main solution in simple 
games 470 

54.2. Enumeration of those games for which all solutions are known 471 

54.3. Reasons to consider the simple game [1, , 1, n 2] A 472 

*55. THE SIMPLE GAME [1, , 1, n - 2] h 473 

*55.1. Preliminary Remarks 473 

*55.2. Domination. The chief player. Cases (I) and (II) 473 

*55.3. Disposal of Case (I) 475 

*55.4. Case (II): Determination of Y 478 

*55.5. Case (II): Determination of V 481 

*55.6. Case (II): a and S* 484 



CONTENTS 

*55.7. Case (II') and (II"). Disposal of Case (IF) 485 

*55.8^ Case (II"): a and V. Domination 487 

*55.9. Case (II"): Determination of V 488 

*55.10. Disposal of Case (II") 494 

*55.11. Reformulation of the complete result 497 

*55.12. Interpretation of the result 499 

CHAPTER XI 
GENERAL NON-ZERO-SUM GAMES 

56. EXTENSION OF THE THEORY 504 

56.1. Formulation of the problem 504 

56.2. The fictitious player. The zero sum extension r 505 

56.3. Questions concerning the character of r 506 

56.4. Limitations of the use of r 508 

56.5. The two possible procedures 510 

56.6. The discriminatory solutions 511 

56.7. Alternative possibilities 512 

56.8. The new setup . 514 

56.9. Reconsideration of the case when T is a zero sum game 516 

56.10. Analysis of the concept of domination 520 

56.11. Rigorous discussion 523 

56.12. The new definition of a solution 526 

57. THE CHARACTERISTIC FUNCTION AND RELATED TOPICS 527 

57.1. The characteristic function: The extended and the restricted form 527 

57.2. Fundamental properties 528 

57.3. Determination of all characteristic functions 530 

57.4. Removable sets of players 533 

57.5. Strategic equivalence. Zero-sum and constant-sum games 535 

58. INTERPRETATION OF THE CHARACTERISTIC FUNCTION 538 

58.1. Analysis of the definition 538 

58.2. The desire to make a gain vs. that to inflict a loss 539 

58.3. Discussion 541 

59. GENERAL CONSIDERATIONS 542 

59.1. Discussion of the program 542 

59.2. The reduced forms. The inequalities 543 

59.3. Various topics 546 

60. THE SOLUTIONS OF ALL GENERAL GAMES WITH n ^ 3 548 

60.1. The case n - 1 548 

60.2. The case n - 2 549 

60.3. The case n = 3 550 

60.4. Comparison with the zero sum games 554 

61. ECONOMIC INTERPRETATION OF THE RESULTS FOR n = 1, 2 555 

61.1. The case n - 1 555 

61.2. The case n = 2. The two person market 555 

61.3. Discussion of the two person market and its characteristic function 557 

61.4. Justification of the standpoint of 58 559 

61.5. Divisible goods. The "marginal pairs" 560 

61.6. The price. Discussion 562 



CONTENTS 

62. ECONOMIC INTERPRETATION OF THE RESULTS FOR n = 3: SPECIAL 
CASE 564 

62.1. The case n = 3, special case. The three person market 564 

62.2. Preliminary discussion 566 

62.3. The solutions: First subcase 566 

62.4. The solutions: General form 569 

62.5. Algebraical form of the result 570 

62.6. Discussion 571 

63. ECONOMIC INTERPRETATION OF THE RESULTS FOR n = 3: GENERAL 
CASE 573 

63.1. Divisible goods 573 

63.2. Analysis of the inequalities 575 

63.3. Preliminary discussion 577 

63.4. The solutions 577 

63.5. Algebraical form of the result 580 

63.6. Discussion 581 

64. THE GENERAL MARKET 583 

64.1. Formulation of the problem 583 

64.2. Some special properties. Monopoly and monopsony 584 

CHAPTER XII 

EXTENSION OF THE CONCEPTS OF DOMINATION 
AND SOLUTION 

65. THE EXTENSION. SPECIAL CASES 587 

65.1. Formulation of the problem 587 

65.2. General remarks 588 

65.3. Orderings, transitivity, acyclicity 589 

65.4. The solutions: For a symmetric relation. For a complete ordering 591 

65.5. The solutions: For a partial ordering 592 

65.6. Acyclicity and strict acyclicity 594 

65.7. The solutions: For an acyclic relation 597 

65.8. Uniqueness 'of solutions, acyclicity and strict acyclicity 600 

65.9. Application to games: Discreteness and continuity 602 

66. GENERALIZATION OF THE CONCEPT OF UTILITY 603 

66.1. The generalization. The two phases of the theoretical treatment 603 

66.2. Discussion of the first phase 604 

66.3. Discussion of the second phase 606 

66.4. Desirability of unifying the two phases 607 

67. DISCUSSION OF AN EXAMPLE 608 

67.1. Description of the example 608 

67.2. The solution and its interpretation 611 

67.3. Generalization: Different discrete utility scales 614 

67.4. Conclusions concerning bargaining 616 

APPENDIX: THE AXIOMATIC TREATMENT OF UTILITY 617 

INDEX OF FIGURES 633 

INDEX OF NAMES 634 

INDEX OF SUBJECTS 635 



CHAPTER I 
FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

1. The Mathematical Method in Economics 
1.1. Introductory Remarks 

1.1.1. The purpose of this book is to present a discussion of some funda- 
mental questions of economic theory which require a treatment different 
from that which they have found thus far in the literature. The analysis 
is concerned with some basic problems arising from a study of economic 
behavior which have been the center of attention of economists for a long 
time. They have their origin in the attempts to find an exact description 
of the endeavor of the individual to obtain a maximum of utility, or, in the 
case of the entrepreneur, a maximum of profit. It is well known what 
considerable and in fact unsurmounted difficulties this task involves 
given even a limited number of typical situations, as, for example, in the 
case of the exchange of goods, direct or indirect, between two or more 
persons, of bilateral monopoly, of duopoly, of oligopoly, and of free compe- 
tition. It will be made clear that the structure of these problems, familiar 
to every student of economics, is in many respects quite different from the 
way in which they are conceived at the present time. It will appear, 
furthermore, that their exact positing and subsequent solution can only be 
achieved with the aid of mathematical methods which diverge considerably 
from the techniques applied by older or by contemporary mathematical 
economists. 

1.1.2. Our considerations will lead to the application of the mathematical 
theory of "games of strategy " developed by one of us in several successive 
stages in 1928 and 1940-1941. 1 After the presentation of this theory, its 
application to economic problems in the sense indicated above will be 
undertaken. It will appear that it provides a new approach to a number of 
economic questions as yet unsettled. 

We shall first have to find in which way this theory of games can be 
brought into relationship with economic theory, and what their common 
elements are. This can be done best by stating briefly the nature of some 
fundamental economic problems so that the common elements will be 
seen clearly. It will then become apparent that there is not only nothing 
artificial in establishing this relationship but that on the contrary this 

1 The first phases of this- work were published: J. von Neumann, "Zur Theorie der 
Gesellschaftsspiele," Math. Annalen, vol. 100 (1928), pp. 295-320. The subsequent 
completion of the theory, as well as the more detailed elaboration of the considerations 
of loc. cit. above, are published here for the first time. 

1 



2 FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

theory of games of strategy is the proper instrument with which to develop 
a theory of economic behavior. 

One would misunderstand the intent of our discussions by interpreting 
them as merely pointing out an analogy between these two spheres. We 
hope to establish satisfactorily, after developing a few plausible schematiza- 
tions, that the typical problems of economic behavior become strictly 
identical with the mathematical notions of suitable games of strategy. 

1.2. Difficulties of the Application of the Mathematical Method 

1.2.1. It may be opportune to begin with some remarks concerning the 
nature of economic theory and to discuss briefly the question of the role 
which mathematics may take in its development. 

First let us be aware that there exists at present no universal system of 
economic theory and that, if one should ever be developed, it will very 
probably not be during our lifetime. The reason for this is simply that 
economics is far too difficult a science to permit its construction rapidly, 
especially in view of the very limited knowledge and imperfect description 
of the facts with which economists are dealing. Only those wlio fail to 
appreciate this condition are likely to attempt the construction of universal 
systems. Even in sciences which are far more advanced than economics, 
like physics, there is no universal system available at present. 

To continue the simile with physics: It happens occasionally that a 
particular physical theory appears to provide the basis for a universal 
system, but in all instances up to the present time this appearance has not 
lasted more than a decade at best. The everyday work of the research 
physicist is certainly not involved with such high aims, but rather is con- 
cerned with special problems which are " mature." There would probably 
be no progress at all in physics if a serious attempt were made to enforce 
that super-standard. The physicist works on individual problems, some 
of great practical significance, others of less. Unifications of fields which 
were formerly divided and far apart may alternate with this type of work. 
However, such fortunate occurrences are rare and happen only after each 
field has been thoroughly explored. Considering the fact that economics 
is much more difficult, much less understood, and undoubtedly in a much 
earlier stage of its evolution as a science than physics, one should clearly not 
expect more than a development of the above type in economics either. 

Second we have to notice that the differences in scientific questions 
make it necessary to employ varying methods which may afterwards have 
to be discarded if better ones offer themselves. This has a double implica- 
tion: In some branches of economics the most fruitful work may be that of 
careful, patient description; indeed this may be by far the largest domain 
for the present and for some time to come. In others it may be possible 
to develop already a theory in a strict manner, and for that purpose the 
use of mathematics may be required. 



THE MATHEMATICAL METHOD IN ECONOMICS 3 

Mathematics has actually been used in economic theory, perhaps even 
in an exaggerated manner. In any case its use has not been highly suc- 
cessful. This is contrary to what one observes in other sciences: There 
mathematics has been applied with great success, and most sciences could 
hardly get along without it. Yet the explanation for this phenomenon is 
fairly simple. 

1.2.2. It is not that there exists any fundamental reason why mathe- 
matics should not be used in economics. The arguments often heard that 
because of the human element, of the psychological factors etc., or because 
there is allegedly no measurement of important factors, mathematics 
will find no application, can all be dismissed as utterly mistaken. Almost 
all these objections have been made, or might have been made, many 
centuries ago in fields where mathematics is now the chief instrument of 
analysis. This " might have been" is meant in the following sense: Let 
us try to imagine ourselves in the period which preceded the mathematical 
or almost mathematical phase of the development in physics, that is the 
16th century, or in chemistry and biology, that is the 18th century. 
Taking for granted the skeptical attitude of those who object to mathe- 
matical economics in principle, the outlook in the physical and biological 
sciences at these early periods can hardly have been better than that in 
economics mutatis mutandis at present. 

As to the lack of measurement of the most important factors, the 
example of the theory of heat is most instructive ; before the development of 
the mathematical theory the possibilities of quantitative measurements 
were less favorable there than they are now in economics. The precise 
measurements of the quantity and quality of heat (energy and temperature) 
were the outcome and not the antecedents of the mathematical theory. 
This ought to be contrasted with the fact that the quantitative and exact 
notions of prices, money and the rate of interest were already developed 
centuries ago. 

A further group of objections against quantitative measurements in 
economics, centers around the lack of indefinite divisibility of economic 
quantities. This is supposedly incompatible with the use of the infini- 
tesimal calculus and hence ( !) of mathematics. It is hard to see how such 
objections can be maintained in view of the atomic theories in physics and 
chemistry, the theory of quanta in electrodynamics, etc., and the notorious 
and continued success of mathematical analysis within these disciplines. 

At this point it is appropriate to mention another familiar argument of 
economic literature which may be revived as an objection against the 
mathematical procedure. 

1.2.3. In order to elucidate the conceptions which we are applying to 
economics, we have given and may give again some illustrations from 
physics. There are many social scientists who object to the drawing of 
such parallels on various grounds, among which is generally found the 
assertion that economic theory cannot be modeled after physics since it is a 



4 FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

science of social, of human phenomena, has to take psychology into account, 
etc. Such statements are at least premature. It is without doubt reason- 
able to discover what has led to progress in other sciences, and to investigate 
whether the application of the same principles may not lead to progress 
in economics also. Should the need for the application of different principles 
arise, it could be revealed only in the course of the actual development 
of economic theory. This would itself constitute a major revolution. 
But since most assuredly we have not yet reached such a state and it is 
by no means certain that there ever will be need for entirely different 
scientific principles it would be very unwise to consider anything else 
than the pursuit of our problems in the manner which has resulted in the 
establishment of physical science. 

1.2.4* The reason why mathematics has not been more successful in 
economics must, consequently, be found elsewhere. The lack of real 
success is largely due to a combination of unfavorable circumstances, some 
of which can be removed gradually. To begin with, the economic problems 
were not formulated clearly and are often stated in such vague terms as to 
make mathematical treatment a priori appear hopeless because it is quite 
uncertain what the problems really are. There is no point in using exact 
methods where there is no clarity in the concepts and issues to which they 
are to be applied. Consequently the initial task is to clarify the knowledge 
of the matter by further careful descriptive work. But even in those 
parts of economics where the descriptive problem has been handled more 
satisfactorily, mathematical tools have seldom been used appropriately. 
They were either inadequately handled, as in the attempts to determine a 
general economic equilibrium by the mere counting of numbers of equations 
and unknowns, or they led to mere translations from a literary form of 
expression into symbols, without any subsequent mathematical analysis. 

Next, the empirical background of economic science is definitely inade- 
quate. Our knowledge of the relevant facts of economics is incomparably 
smaller than that commanded in physics at the time when the mathe- 
matization of that subject was achieved. Indeed, the decisive break which 
came in physics in the seventeenth century, specifically in the field of 
mechanics, was possible only because of previous developments in astron- 
omy. It was backed by several millennia of systematic, scientific, astro- 
nomical observation, culminating in an observer of unparalleled caliber, 
Tycho de Brahe. Nothing of this sort has occurred in economic science. It 
would have been absurd in physics to expect Kepler and Newton without 
Tycho, and there is no reason to hope for an easier development in 
economics. 

These obvious comments should not be construed, of course, as a 
disparagement of statistical-economic research which holds the real promise 
of progress in the proper direction. 

It is due to the combination of the above mentioned circumstances 
that mathematical economics has not achieved very much. The underlying 



THE MATHEMATICAL METHOD IN ECONOMICS 5 

vagueness and ignorance has not been dispelled by the inadequate and 
inappropriate use of a powerful instrument that is very difficult to 
handle. 

In the light of these remarks we may describe our own position as follows: 
The aim of this book lies not in the direction of empirical research. The 
advancement of that side of economic science, on anything like the scale 
which was recognized above as necessary, is clearly a task of vast propor- 
tions. It may be hoped that as a result of the improvements of scientific 
technique and of experience gained in other fields, the development of 
descriptive economics will not take as much time as the comparison with 
astronomy would suggest. But in any case the task seems to transcend 
the limits of any individually planned program. 

We shall attempt to utilize only some commonplace experience concern- 
ing human behavior which lends itself to mathematical treatment and 
which is of economic importance. 

We believe that the possibility of a mathematical treatment of these 
phenomena refutes the "fundamental' 1 objections referred to in 1.2.2. 

It will be seen, however, that this process of mathematization is not 
at all obvious. Indeed, the objections mentioned above may have their 
roots partly in the rather obvious difficulties of any direct mathematical 
approach. We shall find it necessary to draw upon techniques of mathe- 
matics which have not been used heretofore in mathematical economics, and 
it is quite possible that further study may result in the future in the creation 
of new mathematical disciplines. 

To conclude, we may also observe that part of the feeling of dissatisfac- 
tion with the mathematical treatment of economic theory derives largely 
from the fact that frequently one is offered not proofs but mere assertions 
which are really no better than the same assertions given in literary form. 
Very frequently the proofs are lacking because a mathematical treatment 
has been attempted of fields which are so vast and so complicated that for 
a long time to come until much more empirical knowledge is acquired 
there is hardly any reason at all to expect progress more mathematico. 
The fact that these fields have been attacked in this way as for example 
the theory of economic fluctuations, the time structure of production, etc. 
indicates how much the attendant difficulties are being underestimated. 
They are enormous and we are now in no way equipped for them. 

1.2.6. We have referred to the nature and the possibilities of those 
changes in mathematical technique in fact, in mathematics itself which 
a successful application of mathematics to a new subject may produce. 
It is important to visualize these in their proper perspective. 

It must not be forgotten that these changes may be very considerable. 
The decisive phase of the application of mathematics to physics Newton's 
creation of a rational discipline of mechanics brought about, and can 
hardly be separated from, the discovery of the infinitesimal calculus. 
(There are several other examples, but none stronger than this.) 



6 FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

The importance of the social phenomena, the wealth and multiplicity 
of theii manifestations, and the complexity of their structure, aie at least 
equal to those in physics. It is therefore to be expected or feared that 
mathematical discoveries of a stature comparable to that of calculus will 
be needed in ordei to produce decisive success in this field. (Incidentally, 
it is in this spirit that our present efforts must be discounted.) A fortiori 
it is unlikely that a mere repetition of the tricks which served us so well in 
physics will do for the social phenomena too. The probability is very slim 
indeed, since it will be shown that we encounter in our discussions some 
mathematical problems which are quite different from those which occur in 
physical science. 

These observations should be remembered in connection with the current 
overemphasis on the use of calculus, differential equations, etc., as the 
main tools of mathematical economics. 

1.3. Necessary Limitations of the Objectives 

1.3.1. We have to return, therefore, to the position indicated earlier: 
It is necessary to begin with those problems which are described clearly, 
even if they should not be as important from any other point of view. It 
should be added, moreover, that a treatment of these manageable problems 
may lead to results which are already fairly well known, but the exact 
proofs may nevertheless be lacking. Before they have been given the 
respective theory simply does not exist as a scientific theory. The move- 
ments of the planets were known long before their courses had been calcu- 
lated and explained by Newton's theory, and the same applies in many 
smaller and less dramatic instances. And similarly in economic theory, 
certain results say the indeterminateness of bilateral monopoly may be 
known already. Yet it is of interest to derive them again from an exact 
theory. The same could and should be said concerning practically all 
established economic theorems. 

1.3.2. It might be added finally that we do not propose to raise the 
question of the practical significance of the problems treated. This falls 
in line with what was said above about the selection of fields for theory. 
The situation is not different here from that in other sciences. There too 
the most important questions from a practical point of view may have been 
completely out of reach during long and fruitful periods of their develop- 
ment. This is certainly still the case in economics, where it is of utmost 
importance to know how to stabilize employment, how to increase the 
national income, or how to distribute it adequately. Nobody can really 
answer these questions, and we need not concern ourselves with the pre- 
tension that there can be scientific answers at present. 

The great progress in every science came when, in the study of problems 
which were modest as compared with ultimate aims, methods were devel- 
oped which could be extended further and furthei. The free fall is a very 
trivial physical phenomenon, but it was the study of this exceedingly simple 



THE MATHEMATICAL METHOD IN ECONOMICS 7 

fact and its comparison with the astronomical material, which brought forth 
mechanics. 

It seems to us that the same standard of modesty should be applied in 
economics. It is futile to try to explain and " systematically 1 ' at that 
everything economic. The sound procedure is to obtain first utmost 
precision and mastery in a limited field, and then to proceed to another, some- 
what wider one, and so on. This would also do away with the unhealthy 
practice of applying so-called theories to economic or social reform where 
they are in no way useful. 

We believe that it is necessary to know as much as possible about the 
behavior of the individual and about the simplest forms of exchange. This 
standpoint was actually adopted with remarkable success by the founders 
of the marginal utility school, but nevertheless it is not generally accepted. 
Economists frequently point to much larger, more " burning " questions, and 
brush everything aside which prevents them from making statements 
about these. The experience of more advanced sciences, for example 
physics, indicates that this impatience merely delays progress, including 
that of the treatment of the " burning " questions. There is no reason to 
assume the existence of shortcuts. 

1.4. Concluding Remarks 

1.4. It is essential to realize that economists can expect no easier fate 
than that which befell scientists in other disciplines. It seems reasonable 
to expect that they will have to take up first problems contained in the very 
simplest facts of economic life and try to establish theories which explain 
them and which really conform to rigorous scientific standards. We can 
have enough confidence that from then on the science of economics will 
grow further, gradually comprising matters of more vital impoitance than 
those with which one has to begin. 1 

The field covered in this book is very limited, and we approach it in 
this sense of modesty. We do not worry at all if the results of oui study 
conform with views gained recently or held for a long time, for what is 
important is the gradual development of a theory, based on a careful 
analysis of the ordinary everyday interpretation of economic facts. This 
preliminary stage is necessarily heuristic, i.e. the phase of transition from 
unmathematical plausibility considerations to the formal procedure of 
mathematics. The theory finally obtained must be mathematically rigor- 
ous and conceptually general. Its first applications are necessarily to 
elementary problems where the result has never been in doubt and no 
theory is actually required. At this early stage the application selves to 
corroborate the theory. The next stage develops when the theory is applied 

1 The beginning is actually of a certain significance, because the forms of exchange 
between a few individuals are the same as those observed on some of the most important 
markets of modern industry, or in the case of barter exchange between states in inter- 
national trade. 



8 FORlVgJLATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

to somewhat more complicated situations in which it may already lead to a 
certain extent beyond the obvious and the familiar. Here theory and 
application corroborate each other mutually. Beyond this lies the field of 
real success: genuine prediction by theory. It is well known that all 
mathematized sciences have gone through these successive phases of 
evolution. 

2. Qualitative Discussion of the Problem of Rational Behavior 

2.1. The Problem of Rational Behavior 

2.1.1. The subject matter of economic theory is the very complicated 
mechanism of prices and production, and of the gaining and spending of 
incomes. In the course of the development of economics it has been 
found, and it is now well-nigh universally agreed, that an approach to this 
vast problem is gained by the analysis of the behavior of the individuals 
which constitute the economic community. This analysis has been pushed 
fairly far in many respects, and while there still exists much disagreement 
the significance of the approach cannot be doubted, no matter how great 
its difficulties may be. The obstacles are indeed considerable, even if the 
investigation should at first be limited to conditions of economics statics, as 
they well must be. One of the chief difficulties lies in properly describing 
the assumptions which have to be made about the motives of the individual. 
This problem has been stated traditionally by assuming that the consumer 
desires to obtain a maximum of utility or satisfaction and the entrepreneur 
a maximum of profits. 

The conceptual and practical difficulties of the notion of utility, and 
particularly of the attempts to describe it as a number, are well known and 
their treatment is not among the primary objectives of this work. We shall 
nevertheless be forced to discuss them in some instances, in particular in 
3.3. and 3.5. Let it be said at once that the standpoint of the present book 
on this very important and very interesting question will be mainly oppor- 
tunistic. We wish to concentrate on one problem which is not that of 
the measurement of utilities and of preferences and we shall therefore 
attempt to simplify all other characteristics as far as reasonably possible. 
We shall therefore assume that the aim of all participants in the economic 
system, consumers as well as entrepreneurs, is money, or equivalently a 
single monetary commodity. This is supposed to be unrestrictedly divisible 
and substitutable, freely transferable and identical, even in the quantitative 
sense, with whatever " satisfaction" or " utility" is desired by each par- 
ticipant. (For the quantitative character of utility, cf. 3.3. quoted above.) 

It is sometimes claimed in economic literature that discussions of the 
notions of utility and preference are altogether unnecessary, since these are 
purely verbal definitions with no empirically observable consequences, i.e., 
entirely tautological. It does not seem to us that these notions are quali- 
tatively inferior to certain well established and indispensable notions in 



THE PROBLEM OF RATIONAL BEHAVIOR 9 

physics, like force, mass, charge, etc. That is, while they are in their 
immediate form merely definitions, they become subject to empirical control 
through the theories which are built upon them and in no other way. 
Thus the notion of utility is raised above the status of a tautology by such 
economic theories as make use of it and the results of which can be compared 
with experience or at least with common sense. 

2.1.2. The individual who attempts to obtain these respective maxima 
is also said to act "rationally." But it may safely be stated that there 
exists, at present, no satisfactory treatment of the question of rational 
behavior. There may, for example, exist several ways by which to reach 
the optimum position; they may depend upon the knowledge and under- 
standing which the individual has and upon the paths of action open to 
him. A study of all these questions in qualitative terms will not exhaust 
them, because they imply, as must be evident, quantitative relationships. 
It would, therefore, be necessary to formulate them in quantitative terms 
so that all the elements of the qualitative description are taken into con- 
sideration. This is an exceedingly difficult task, and we can safely say 
that it has not been accomplished in the extensive literature about the 
topic. The chief reason for this lies, no doubt, in the failure to develop 
and apply suitable mathematical methods to the problem; this would 
have revealed that the maximum problem which is supposed to correspond 
to the notion of rationality is not at all formulated in an unambiguous way. 
Indeed, a more exhaustive analysis (to be given in 4.S.-4.5.) reveals that 
the significant relationships are much more complicated than the popular 
and the " philosophical" use of the word " rational" indicates. 

A valuable qualitative preliminary description of the behavior of the 
individual is offered by the Austrian School, particularly in analyzing the 
economy of the isolated " Robinson Crusoe." We may have occasion to 
note also some considerations of Bohm-Bawerk concerning the exchange 
between two or more persons. The more recent exposition of the theory of 
the individual's choices in the form of indifference curve analysis builds up 
on the very same facts or alleged facts but uses a method which is often held 
to be superior in many ways. Concerning this we refer to the discussions in 
2.1.1. and 3.3. 

We hope, however, to obtain a real understanding of the problem of 
exchange by studying it from an altogether different angle; this is, from the 
perspective of a "game of strategy." Our approach will become clear 
presently, especially after some ideas which have been advanced, say by 
Bohm-Bawerk whose views may be considered only as a prototype of this 
theory are given correct quantitative formulation. 

2.2. "Robinson Crusoe" Economy and Social Exchange Economy 

2.2.1. Let us look more closely at the type of economy which is repre- 
sented by the "Robinson Crusoe" model, that is an economy of an isolated 
single person or otherwise organized under a single will. This economy is 



10 FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

confronted with certain quantities of commodities and a number of wants 
which they may satisfy. The problem is to obtain a maximum satisfaction. 
This is considering in particular our above assumption of the numerical 
character of utility indeed an ordinary maximum problem, its difficulty 
depending appaiently on the number of variables and on the nature of the 
function to be maximized; but this is more of a practical difficulty than a 
theoretical one. 1 If one abstracts from continuous production and from 
the fact that consumption too stretches over time (and often uses durable 
consumers' goods), one obtains the simplest possible model. It was 
thought possible to use it as the very basis for economic theory, but this 
attempt notably a feature of the Austrian version was often contested. 
The chief objection against using this very simplified model of an isolated 
individual for the theory of a social exchange economy is that it does not 
represent an individual exposed to the manifold social influences. Hence, 
it is said to analyze an individual who might behave quite differently if his 
choices were made in a social world where he would be exposed to factors 
of imitation, advertising, custom, and so on. These factors certainly make 
a great difference, but it is to be questioned whether they change the formal 
properties of the process of maximizing. Indeed the latter has never been 
implied, and since we are concerned with this problem alone, we can leave 
the above social considerations out of account. 

Some other differences between " Crusoe " and a participant in a social 
exchange economy will not concern us either. Such is the non-existence of 
money as a means of exchange in the first case where there is only a standard 
of calculation, for which purpose any commodity can serve. This difficulty 
indeed has been ploughed under by our assuming in 2.1.2. a quantitative 
and even monetary notion of utility. We emphasize again: Our interest 
lies in the fact that even after all these drastic simplifications Crusoe is 
confronted with a formal problem quite different from the one a participant 
in a social economy faces. 

2.2.2. Crusoe is given certain physical data (wants and commodities) 
and his task is to combine and apply them in such a fashion as to obtain 
a maximum resulting satisfaction. There can be no doubt that he controls 
exclusively all the variables upon which this result depends say the 
allotting of resources, the determination of the uses of the same commodity 
for different wants, etc. 2 

Thus Crusoe faces an ordinary maximum problem, the difficulties of 
which are of a purely technical and not conceptual nature, as pointed out. 

2.2.3. Consider now a participant in a social exchange economy. His 
problem has, of course, many elements in common with a maximum prob- 

1 It is not important for the following to determine whether its theory is complete in 
all its aspects. 

2 Sometimes uncontrollable factors also intervene, e.g. the weather in agriculture. 
These however are purely statistical phenomena. Consequently they can be eliminated 
by the known procedures of the calculus of probabilities: i.e., by determining the prob- 
abilities of the various alternatives and by introduction of the notion of " mathematical 
expectation." Cf . however the influence on the notion of utility, discussed in 3.3. 



THE PROBLEM OF RATIONAL BEHAVIOR 11 

lem. But it also contains some, very essential, elements of an entirely 
different nature. He too tries to obtain an optimum result. But in order 
to achieve this, he must enter into relations of exchange with others. If 
two or more persons exchange goods with each other, then the result for 
each one will depend in general not merely upon his own actions but on 
those of the others as well. Thus each participant attempts to maximize 
a function (his above-mentioned "result") of which he does not control all 
variables. This is certainly no maximum problem, but a peculiar and dis-~ 
concerting mixture of several conflicting maximum problems. Every parti- 
cipant is guided by another principle and neither determines all variables 
which affect his interest. 

This kind of problem is nowhere dealt with in classical mathematics. 
We emphasize at the risk of being pedantic that this is no conditional maxi- 
mum problem, no problem of the calculus of variations, of functional 
analysis, etc. It arises in full clarity, even in the most " elementary" 
situations, e.g., when all variables can assume only a finite number of values. 

A particularly striking expression of the popular misunderstanding 
about this pseudo-maximum problem is the famous statement according to 
which the purpose of social effort is the "greatest possible good for the 
greatest possible number. " A guiding principle cannot be formulated 
by the requirement of maximizing two (or more) functions at once. 

Such a principle, taken literally, is self-contradictory, (in general one 
function will have no maximum where the other function has one.) It is 
no better than saying, e.g., that a firm should obtain maximum prices 
at maximum turnover, or a maximum revenue at minimum outlay. If 
some order of importance of these principles or some weighted average is 
meant, this should be stated. However, in the situation of the participants 
in a social economy nothing of that sort is intended, but all maxima are 
desired at once by various participants. 

One would be mistaken to believe that it can be obviated, like the 
difficulty in the Crusoe case mentioned in footnote 2 on p. 10, by a mere 
recourse to the devices of the theory of probability. Every participant can 
determine the variables which describe his own actions but not those of the 
others. Nevertheless those "alien " variables cannot, from his point of view, 
be described by statistical assumptions. This is because the others are 
guided, just as he himself, by rational principles whatever that may mean 
and no modus procedendi can be correct which does not attempt to under- 
stand those principles and the interactions of the conflicting interests of all 
participants. 

Sometimes some of these interests run more 01 less parallel then we 
are nearer to a simple maximum problem. But they can just as well be 
opposed. The general theory must cover all these possibilities, all inter- 
mediary stages, and all their combinations. 

2.2.4. The difference between Crusoe's perspective and that of a par- 
ticipant in a social economy can also be illustrated in this way: Apart from 



12 FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

those variables which his will controls, Crusoe is given a number of data 
which are "dead"; they are the unalterable physical background of the 
situation. (Even when they are apparently variable, cf. footnote 2 on 
p. 10, they are really governed by fixed statistical laws.) Not a single 
datum with which he has to deal reflects another person's will or intention 
of an economic kind based on motives of the same nature as his own. A 
participant in a social exchange economy, on the other hand, faces data 
of this last type as well : they are the product of other participants' actions 
and volitions (like prices). His actions will be influenced by his expectation 
of these, and they in turn reflect the other participants' expectation of his 
actions. 

Thus the study of the Crusoe economy and the use of the methods 
applicable to it, is of much more limited value to economic theory than 
has been assumed heretofore even by the most radical critics. The grounds 
for this limitation lie not in the field of those social relationships which 
we have mentioned before although we do not question their significance 
but rather they arise from the conceptual differences between the original 
(Crusoe's) maximum problem and the more complex problem sketched above. 

We hope that the reader will be convinced by the above that we face 
here and now a really conceptual and not merely technical difficulty. 
And it is this problem which the theory of " games of strategy" is mainly 
devised to meet. 

2.3. The Number of Variables and the Number of Participants 

2.3.1. The formal set-up which we used in the preceding paragraphs to 
indicate the events in a social exchange economy made use of a number of 
" variables" which described the actions of the participants in this economy. 
Thus every participant is allotted a set of variables, "his" variables, which 
together completely describe his actions, i.e. express precisely the manifes- 
tations of his will. We call these sets the partial sets of variables. The 
partial sets of all participants constitute together the set of all variables, to 
be called the total set. So the total number of variables is determined first 
by the number of participants, i.e. of partial sets, and second by the number 
of variables in every partial set. 

From a purely mathematical point of view there would be nothing 
objectionable in treating all the variables of any one partial set as a single 
variable, "the" variable of the participant corresponding to this partial 
set. Indeed, this is a procedure which we are going to use frequently in 
our mathematical discussions; it makes absolutely no difference con- 
ceptually, and it simplifies notations considerably. 

For the moment, however, we propose to distinguish from each other the 
variables within each partial set. The economic models to which one is 
naturally led suggest that procedure; thus it is desirable to describe for 
every participant the quantity of every particular good he wishes to acquire 
by a separate variable, etc. 



THE PROBLEM OF RATIONAL BEHAVIOR 13 

2.3.2. Now we must emphasize that any increase of the number of 
variables inside a participant's partial set may complicate our problem 
technically, but only technically. Thus in a Crusoe economy where 
there exists only one participant and only one partial set which then coin- 
cides with the total set this may make the necessary determination of a 
maximum technically more difficult, but it will not alter the "pure maxi- 
mum " character of the problem. If, on the other hand, the number of 
participants i.e., of the partial sets of variables is increased, something 
of a very different nature happens. To use a terminology which will turn 
out to be significant, that of games, this amounts to an increase in the 
number of players in the game. However, to take the simplest cases, a 
three-person game is very fundamentally different from a two-person game, 
a four-person game from a three-person game, etc. The combinatorial 
complications of the problem which is, as we saw, no maximum problem 
at all increase tremendously with every increase in the number of players, 
as our subsequent discussions will amply show. 

We have gone into this matter in such detail particularly because in 
most models of economics a peculiar mixture of these two phenomena occurs. 
Whenever the number of players, i.e. of participants in a social economy, 
increases, the complexity of the economic system usually increases too; 
e.g. the number of commodities and services exchanged, processes of 
production used, etc. Thus the number of variables in every participant's 
partial set is likely to increase. But the number of participants, i.e. of 
partial sets, has increased too. Thus both of the sources which we discussed 
contribute pari passu to the total increase in the number of variables. It is 
essential to visualize each source in its proper role. 

2.4. The Case of Many Participants : Free Competition 

2.4.1. In elaborating the contrast between a Crusoe economy and a 
social exchange economy in 2.2.2.-2.2.4., we emphasized those features 
of the latter which become more prominent when the number of participants 
while greater than 1 is of moderate size. The fact that every partici- 
pant is influenced by the anticipated reactions of the others to his own 
measures, and that this is true for each of the participants, is most strikingly 
the crux of the matter (as far as the sellers are concerned) in the classical 
problems of duopoly, oligopoly, etc. When the number of participants 
becomes really great, some hope emerges that the influence of every par- 
ticular participant will become negligible, and that the above difficulties 
may recede and a more conventional theory become possible. These 
are, of course, the classical conditions of "free competition." Indeed, this 
was the starting point of much of what is best in economic theory. Com- 
pared with this case of great numbers free competition the cases of small 
numbers on the side of the sellers monopoly, duopoly, oligopoly were 
even considered to be exceptions and abnormities. (Even in these cases 
the number of participants is still very large in view of the competition 



14 FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

among the buyers. The cases involving really small numbers are those of 
bilateral monopoly, of exchange between a monopoly and an oligopoly, or 
two oligopolies, etc.) 

2.4.2. In all fairness to the traditional point of view this much ought 
to be said: It is a well known phenomenon in many branches of the exact 
and physical sciences that very great numbers are often easier to handle 
than those of medium size. An almost exact theory of a gas, containing 
about 10 26 freely moving particles, is incomparably easier than that of the 
solar system, made up of 9 major bodies; and still more than that of a mul- 
tiple star of three or four objects of about the same size. This is, of course, 
due to the excellent possibility of applying the laws of statistics and prob- 
abilities in the first case. 

This analogy, however, is far from perfect for our problem. The theory 
of mechanics for 2, 3, 4, bodies is well known, and in its general 
theoretical (as distinguished from its special and computational) form is the 
foundation of the statistical theory for great numbers. For the social 
exchange economy i.e. for the equivalent " games of strategy " the theory 
of 2, 3, 4, participants was heretofore lacking. It is this need that 
our previous discussions were designed to establish and that our subsequent 
investigations will endeavor to satisfy. In other words, only after the 
theory for moderate numbers of participants has been satisfactorily devel- 
oped will it be possible to decide whether extremely great numbers of par- 
ticipants simplify the situation. Let us say it again: We share the hope 
chiefly because of the above-mentioned analogy in other fields! that such 
simplifications will indeed occur. The current assertions concerning free 
competition appear to be very valuable surmises and inspiring anticipations 
of results. But they are not results and it is scientifically unsound to treat 
them as such as long as the conditions which we mentioned above are not 
satisfied. 

There exists in the literature a considerable amount of theoretical dis- 
cussion purporting to show that the zones of indeterminateness (of rates of 
exchange) which undoubtedly exist when the number of participants is 
small narrow and disappear as the number increases. This then would 
provide a continuous transition into the ideal case of free competition for 
a very great number of participants where all solutions would be sharply 
and uniquely determined. While it is to be hoped that this indeed turns out 
to be the case in sufficient generality, one cannot concede that anything 
like this contention has been established conclusively thus far. There is 
no getting away from it: The problem must be formulated, solved and 
understood for small numbers of participants before anything can be proved 
about the changes of its character in any limiting case of large numbers, 
such as free competition. 

2.4.3. A really fundamental reopening of this subject is the more 
desirable because it is neither certain nor probable that a mere increase in 
the number of participants will always lead in fine to the conditions of 



THE NOTION OF UTILITY 15 

free competition. The classical definitions of free competition all involve 
further postulates besides the greatness of that number. E.g., it is clear 
that if certain great groups of participants will for any reason whatsoever 
act together, then the great number of participants may not become 
effective; the decisive exchanges may take place directly between large 
" coalitions, " l few in number, and not between individuals, many in number, 
acting independently. Our subsequent discussion of " games of strategy" 
will show that the role and size of " coalitions " is decisive throughout the 
entire subject. Consequently the above difficulty though not new still 
remains the crucial problem. Any satisfactory theory of the " limiting 
transition " from small numbers of participants to large numbers will have 
to explain under what circumstances such big coalitions will or will not be 
formed i.e. when the large numbers of participants will become effective 
and lead to a more or less free competition. Which of these alternatives is 
likely to arise will depend on the physical data of the situation. Answering 
this question is, we think, the real challenge to any theory of free competition. 

2.5. The "Lausanne" Theory 

2.6. This section should not be concluded without a reference to the 
equilibrium theory of the Lausanne School and also of various other systems 
which take into consideration " individual planning " and interlocking 
individual plans. All these systems pay attention to the interdependence 
of the participants in a social economy. This, however, is invariably done 
under far-reaching restrictions. Sometimes free competition is assumed, 
after the introduction of which the participants face fixed conditions and 
act like a number of Robinson Crusoes solely bent on maximizing their 
individual satisfactions, which under these conditions are again independent. 
In other cases other restricting devices are used, all of which amount to 
excluding the free play of " coalitions " formed by any or all types of par- 
ticipants. There are frequently definite, but sometimes hidden, assump- 
tions concerning the ways in which their partly parallel and partly opposite 
interests will influence the participants, and cause them to cooperate or not, 
as the case may be. We hope we have shown that such a procedure amounts 
to a petitio principii at least on the plane on which we should like to put 
the discussion. It avoids the real difficulty and deals with a verbal problem, 
which is not the empirically given one. Of course we do not wish to ques- 
tion the significance of these investigations but they do not answer our 
queries. 

3. The Notion of Utility 

3.1. Preferences and Utilities 

3.1.1. We have stated already in 2.1.1. in what way we wish to describe 
the fundamental concept of individual preferences by the use of a rather 

1 Such as trade unions, consumers' cooperatives, industrial cartels, and conceivably 
some organizations more in the political sphere. 



16 FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

far-reaching notion of utility. Many economists will feel that we are 
assuming far too much (cf . the enumeration of the properties we postulated 
in 2.1.1.), and that our standpoint is a retrogression from the more cautious 
modern technique of " indifference curves." 

Before attempting any specific discussion let us state as a general 
excuse that our procedure at worst is only the application of a classical 
preliminary device of scientific analysis: To divide the difficulties, i.e. to 
concentrate on one (the subject proper of the investigation in hand), and 
to reduce all others as far as reasonably possible, by simplifying and schema- 
tizing assumptions. We should also add that this high handed treatment 
of preferences and utilities is employed in the main body of our discussion, 
but we shall incidentally investigate to a certain extent the changes which an 
avoidance of the assumptions in question would cause in our theory (cf. 66., 
67.). 

We feel, however, that one part of our assumptions at least that of 
treating utilities as numerically measurable quantities is not quite as 
radical as is often assumed in the literature. We shall attempt to prove 
this particular point in the paragraphs which follow. It is hoped that the 
reader will forgive us for discussing only incidentally in a condensed form 
a subject of so great a conceptual importance as that of utility. It seems 
however that even a few remarks may be helpful, because the question 
of the measurability of utilities is similar in character to corresponding 
questions in the physical sciences. 

3.1.2. Historically, utility was fiist conceived as quantitatively measur- 
able, i.e. as a number. Valid objections can be and have been made against 
this view in its original, naive form. It is clear that every measurement 
or rather every claim of measurability must ultimately be based on some 
immediate sensation, which possibly cannot and certainly need not be 
analyzed any further. 1 In the case of utility the immediate sensation of 
preference of one object or aggregate of objects as against another 
provides this basis. But this permits us only to say when for one person 
one utility is greater than another. It is not in itself a basis for numerical 
comparison of utilities for one person nor of any comparison between 
different persons. Since there is no intuitively significant way to add two 
iUtilities for the same person, the assumption that utilities are of non- 
Jnumerical character even seems plausible. The modern method of indiffer- 
ence curve analysis is a mathematical procedure to describe this situation. 

3.2. Principles of Measurement : Preliminaries 

3.2.1. All this is strongly reminiscent of the conditions existant at the 
beginning of the theory of heat: that too was based on the intuitively clear 
concept of one body feeling warmer than another, yet there was no immedi- 
ate way to express significantly by how much, or how many times, or in 
what sense. 

1 Such as the sensations of light, heat, muscular effort, etc., in the corresponding 
branches of physics. 



THE NOTION OF UTILITY 17 

This comparison with heat also shows how little one can forecast a priori 
what the ultimate shape of such a theory will be. The above crude indica- 
tions do not disclose at all what, as we now know, subsequently happened. 
It turned out that heat permits quantitative description not by one numbei 
but by two: the quantity of heat and temperature. The former is rather 
directly numerical because it turned out to be additive and also in an 
unexpected way connected with mechanical energy which was numerical 
anyhow. The latter is also numerical, but in a much more subtle way; 
it is not additive in any immediate sense, but a rigid numerical scale for it 
emerged from the study of the concordant behavior of ideal gases, and the 
role of absolute temperature in connection with the entropy theorem. 

3.2.2. The historical development of the theory of heat indicates that 
one must be extremely careful in making negative assertions about any 
concept with the claim to finality. Even if utilities look very unnumerical 
today, the history of the experience in the theory of heat may repeat itself, 
and nobody can foretell with what ramifications and variations. 1 And it 
should certainly not discourage theoretical explanations of the formal 
possibilities of a numerical utility. 

3.3. Probability and Numerical Utilities 

3.3.1. We can go even one step beyond the above double negations 
which were only cautions against premature assertions of the impossibility 
of a numerical utility. It can be shown that under the conditions on which 
the indifference curve analysis is based very little extra effort is needed to 
reach a numerical utility. 

It has been pointed out repeatedly that a numerical utility is dependent 
upon the possibility of comparing differences in utilities. This may seem 
and indeed is a more far-reaching assumption than that of a mere ability 
to state preferences. But it will seem that the alternatives to which eco- 
nomic preferences must be applied are such as to obliterate this distinction. 

3.3.2. ILet us for the moment accept the picture of an individual whose 
system ol preferences is all-embracmg^md-eemplete, i^e^who^for any two 
objects or rather for any two imagined events, possesses a clear intuition of 
preference. 

More precisely we expect him, for any two alternative events which are 
put before him as possibilities, to be able to tell which of the two he prefers. 

It is a very natural extension of this picture to permit such an individual 
to compare not only events, but even combinations of events with stated 
probabilities. 2 

By a combination of two events we mean this: Let the two events be 
denoted by B and C and use, for the sake of simplicity, the probability 

1 A good example of the wide variety of formal possibilities is given by the entirely 
different development of the theory of light, colors, and wave lengths. All these notions 
too became numerical, but in an entirely different way. 

2 Indeed this is necessary if he is engaged in economic activities which are explicitly 
dependent on probability. Of. the example of agriculture in footnote 2 on p. 10. 



18 FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

50%-50%. Then the " combination" is the prospect of seeing B occur 
with a probability of 50% and (if B does not occur) C with the (remaining) 
probability of 50%. We stress that the two alternatives are mutually 
exclusive, so that no possibility of complementarity and the like exists. 
Also, that an absolute certainty of the occurrence of either B or C exists. 

To restate our position. We expect the individual under consideration 
to possess a clear intuition whether he prefers the event A to the 50-50 
combination of B or C, or conversely. It is clear that if he prefers A to B 
and also to C, then he will prefer it to the above combination as well; 
similarly, if he prefers B as well as C to A, then he will prefei the combination 
too. But if he should prefer A to, say B, but at the same time C to A, then 
any assertion about his preference of A against the combination contains 
fundamentally new information. Specifically: If he now prefers A to the 
50-50 combination of B and C, this provides a plausible base for the numer- 
ical estimate that his preference of A over B is in excess of his preference of 
C over A. 1 - 2 

If this standpoint is accepted, then there is a criterion with which to 
compare the preference of C over A with the preference of A over B. It is 
well known that thereby utilities or rather differences of utilities become 
numerically measurable. 

That the possibility of comparison between A, B, and C only to this 
extent is already sufficient for a numerical measurement of " distances " 
was first observed in economics by Pareto. Exactly the same argument 
has been made, however, by Euclid for the position of points on a line in 
fact it is the very basis of his classical derivation of numerical distances. 

The introduction of numerical measures can be achieved even more 
directly if use is made of all possible probabilities. Indeed: Consider 
three events, C, A, B, for which the order of the individual's preferences 
is the one stated. Let a be a real number between and 1, such that A 
is exactly equally desirable with the combined event consisting of a chance 
of probability 1 a for B and the remaining chance of probability a. for C. 
Then we suggest the use of a as a numerical estimate for the ratio of the 
preference of A over B to that of C over B. 8 An exact and exhaustive 

1 To give a simple example: Assume that an individual prefers the consumption of a 
glass of tea to that of a cup of coffee, and the cup of coffee to a glass of milk. If we now 
want to know whether the last preference i.e., difference in utilities exceeds the former, 
it suffices to place him in a situation where he must decide this: Does he prefer a cup of 
coffee to a glass the content of which will be determined by a 50 %-50 % chance device as 
tea or milk. 

1 Observe that we have only postulated an individual intuition which permits decision 
as to which of two "events" is preferable. But we have not directly postulated any 
intuitive estimate of the relative sizes of two preferences i.e. in the subsequent termi- 
nology, of two differences of utilities. 

This is important, since the former information ought to be obtainable in a reproduci- 
ble way by mere "questioning." 

1 This offers a good opportunity for another illustrative example. The above tech- 
nique permits a direct determination of the ratio q of the utility of possessing 1 unit of a 
certain good to the utility of possessing 2 units of the same good. The individual must 



THE NOTION OF UTILITY 19 

elaboration of these ideas requires the use of the axiomatic method. A sim- 
ple treatment on this basis is indeed possible. We shall discuss it in 
3.5-3.7. 

3.3.3. To avoid misunderstandings let us state that the " events" 
which were used above as the substratum of preferences are conceived as 
future events so as to make all logically possible alternatives equally 
admissible. However, it would be an unnecessary complication, as far 
as our present objectives are concerned, to get entangled with the problems 
of the preferences between events in different periods of the future. 1 It 
seems, however, that such difficulties can be obviated by locating all 
"events" in which we are interested at one and the same, standardized, 
moment, preferably in the immediate future. 

The above considerations are so vitally dependent upon the numerical 
concept of probability that a few words concerning the latter may be 
appropriate. 

Probability has often been visualized as a subjective concept more 
or less in the nature of an estimation. Since we propose to use it in con- 
structing an individual, numerical estimation of utility, the above view of 
probability would not serve our purpose. The simplest procedure is, there- 
fore, to insist upon the alternative, perfectly well founded interpretation of 
probability as frequency in long runs. This gives directly the necessary 
numerical foothold. 2 

3.3.4. This procedure for a numerical measurement of the utilities of the 
individual depends, of course, upon the hypothesis of completeness in the 
system of individual preferences. 8 It is conceivable and may even in a 
way be more realistic to allow for cases where the individual is neither 
able to state which of two alternatives he prefers nor that they are equally 
desirable. In this case the treatment by indifference curves becomes 
impracticable too. 4 

How real this possibility is, both for individuals and for organizations, 
seems to be an extremely interesting question, but it is a question of fact. 
It certainly deserves further study. We shall reconsider it briefly in 3.7.2. 

At any rate we hope we have shown that the treatment by indifference 
curves implies either too much or too little: if the preferences of the indi- 

be given the choice of obtaining 1 unit with certainty or of playing the chance to get two 
units with the probability <*, or nothing with the probability 1 a. If he prefers the 
former, then a < 5; if he prefers the latter, then a > g; if he cannot state a preference 
either way, then a = q. 

1 It is well known that this presents very interesting, but as yet extremely obscure, 
connections with the theory of saving and interest, etc. 

2 If one objects to the frequency interpretation of probability then the two concepts 
(probability and preference) can be axiomatized together. This too leads to a satis- 
factory numerical concept of utility which will be discussed on another occasion. 

8 We have not obtained any basis for a comparison, quantitatively or qualitatively, 
of the utilities of different individuals. 

4 These problems belong systematically in the mathematical theory of ordered sets. 
The above question in particular amounts to asking whether events, with respect to 
preference, form a completely or a partially ordered set. Cf. 65,3. 



20 FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

vidual are not all comparable, then the indifference curves do not exist. 1 
If the individual's preferences are all comparable, then we can even obtain a 
(uniquely defined) numeiical utility which renders the indifference curves 
superfluous. 

All this becomes, of course, pointless for the entrepreneur who can 
calculate in terms of (monetary) costs and profits. 

3.3.5. The objection could be raised that it is not necessary to go into 
all these intricate details concerning the measurability of utility, since 
evidently the common individual, whose behavior one wants to describe, 
does not measure his utilities exactly but rather conducts his economic 
activities in a sphere of considerable haziness. The same is true, of course, 
for much of his conduct regarding light, heat, muscular effort, etc. But in 
order to build a science of physics these phenomena had to be measured. 
And subsequently the individual has come to use the results of such measure- 
ments directly or indirectly even in his everyday life. The same may 
obtain in economics at a future date. Once a fuller understanding of 
economic behavior has been achieved with the aid of a theory which makes 
use of this instrument, the life of the individual might be materially affected. 
It is, therefore, not an unnecessary digression to study these problems. 

3.4. Principles of Measurement : Detailed Discussion 

3.4.1. The reader may feel, on the basis of the foregoing, that we 
obtained a numerical scale of utility only by begging the principle, i.e. by 
really postulating the existence of such a scale. We have argued in 3.3.2. 
that if an individual prefers A to the 50-50 combination of B and C (while 
preferring C to A and A to JB), this provides a plausible basis for the numer- 
ical estimate that this preference of A over B exceeds that of C over A. 
Are we not postulating here or taking it for granted that one preference 
may exceed another, i.e. that such statements convey a meaning? Such 
a view would be a complete misunderstanding of our procedure. 

3.4.2. We are not postulating or assuming anything of the kind. We 
have assumed only one thing and for this there is good empirical evidence 
namely that imagined events can be combined with probabilities. And 
therefore the same must be assumed for the utilities attached to them, 
whatever they may be. Or to put it in more mathematical language: 

There frequently appear in science quantities which are a priori not 
mathematical, but attached to certain aspects of the physical world. 
Occasionally these quantities can be grouped together in domains within 
which certain natural, physically defined operations are possible. Thus 
the physically defined quantity of "mass" permits the operation of addition. 
The physico-geometrically defined quantity of "distance" 2 permits the same 

1 Points on the same indifference curve must be identified and are therefore no 
instances of incomparability. 

f Let us, for the sake of the argument, view geometry as a physical discipline, a 
sufficiently tenable viewpoint. By "geometry" we mean equally for the sake of the 
argument Euclidean geometry. 



THE NOTION OF UTILITY 21 

operation. On the other hand, the physico-geometrically defined quantity 
of " position" does not permit this operation, 1 but it permits the operation 
of forming the " center of gravity" of two positions. 2 Again other physico- 
geometrical concepts, usually styled " vectorial" like velocity and accelera- 
tion permit the operation of " addition." 

3.4.3. In all these cases where such a " natural" operation is given a 
name which is reminiscent of a mathematical operation like the instances 
of " addition" above one must carefully avoid misunderstandings. This 
nomenclature is not intended as a claim that the two operations with the 
same name are identical, this is manifestly not the case; it only expresses 
the opinion that they possess similar traits, and the hope that some cor- 
respondence between them will ultimately be established. This of course 
when feasible at all is done by finding a mathematical model for the 
physical domain in question, within which those quantities are defined by 
numbers, so that in the model the mathematical operation describes the 
synonymous " natural" operation. 

To return to our examples: " energy" and "mass" became numbers in 
the pertinent mathematical models, "natural" addition becoming ordinary 
addition. "Position" as well as the vectorial quantities became triplets 3 of 
numbers, called coordinates or components respectively. The "natural" 
concept of "center of gravity" of two positions {#1, x%, x 3 ) and \x' ly x' 2 , z'a}/ 
with the "masses" a, 1 a (cf. footnote 2 above), becomes 

{ax, + (1 - a)x(, ax, + (1 - a)*J, ax, + (1 - <*X). 5 

The "natural" operation of "addition" of vectors {zi, x 2 , x*\ and [x(, z, x' z \ 
becomes {xi + x[, x 2 + x 2 , x* + ZgJ. 6 

What was said above about "natural" and mathematical operations 
applies equally to natural and mathematical relations. The various con- 
cepts of "greater" which occur in physics greater energy, force, heat, 
velocity, etc. are good examples. 

These "natural" relations are the best base upon which to construct 
mathematical models and to correlate the physical domain with them. 7 ' 8 

1 We are thinking of a "homogeneous" Euclidean space, in which no origin or frame of 
reference is preferred above any other. 

2 With respect to two given masses a, occupying those positions. It may be con- 
venient to normalize so that the total mass is the unit, i.e. ** 1 *. 

3 We are thinking of three-dimensional Euclidean space. 

4 We are now describing them by their three numerical coordinates. 

8 This is usually denoted by a (xi,z 2 ,z 8 1 + (1 - a)js|, xj, *',) Cf. (16:A:c) in 16.2.1. 
8 This is usually denoted by (xi, x*, x s \ -f (z'i, zj, xj|. Cf. the beginning of 16.2.1. 

7 Not the only one. Temperature is a good counter-example. The "natural" rela- 
tion of "greater," would not have sufficed to establish the present day mathematical 
model, i.e. the absolute temperature scale. The devices actually used were different. 
Cf. 3.2.1. 

8 We do not want to give the misleading impression of attempting here a complete 
picture of the formation of mathematical models, i.e. of physical theories. It should be 
remembered that this is a very varied process with many unexpected phases. An impor- 
tant one is, e.g., the disentanglement of concepts: i.e. splitting up something which at 



22 FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

3.4.4. Here a further remark must be made. Assume that a satisfactory 
mathematical model for a physical domain in the above sense has been 
found, and that the physical quantities under consideration have been 
correlated with numbers. In this case it is not true necessarily that the 
description (of the mathematical model) provides for a unique way of 
correlating the physical quantities to numbers; i.e., it may specify an entire 
family of such correlations the mathematical name is mappings any 
one of which can be used for the purposes of the theory. Passage from one 
of these correlations to another amounts to a transformation of the numerical 
data describing the physical quantities. We then say that in this theory 
the physical quantities in question are described by numbers up to that 
system of transformations. The mathematical name of such transformation 
systems is groups. 1 

Examples of such situations are numerous. Thus the geometrical con- 
cept of distance is a number, up to multiplication by (positive) constant 
factors. 2 The situation concerning the physical quantity of mass is the 
same. The physical concept of energy is a number up to any linear trans- 
formation, i.e. addition of any constant and multiplication by any (posi- 
tive) constant. 8 The concept of position is defined up to an inhomogeneous 
orthogonal linear transformation. 4 - B The vectorial concepts are defined 
up to homogeneous tiansformations of the same kind. 5 ' 6 

3.4.6. It is even conceivable that a physical quantity is a number up to 
any monotone transformation. This is the case for quantities for which 
only a "natural" relation " greater " exists and nothing else. E.g. this 
was the case for temperature as long as only the concept of " warmer " was 
known; 7 it applies to the Mohs' scale of hardness of minerals; it applies to 



superficial inspection seems to be one physical entity into several mathematical notions. 
Thus the "disentanglement" of force and energy, of quantity of heat and temperature, 
were decisive in their respective fields. 

It is quite unforeseeable how many such differentiations still lie ahead in economic 
theory. 

1 We shall encounter groups in another context in 28.1.1, where references to the 
literature are also found. 

* I.e. there is nothing in Euclidean geometry to fix a unit of distance. 

3 I.e. there is nothing in mechanics to fix a zero or a unit of energy. Cf . with footnote 2 
above. Distance has a natural zero, the distance of any point from itself. 

4 I.e. |*i, x, X|| are to be replaced by {xi*, x a *, x 9 *\ where 



-f OU.TI 4- 013X3 + 61, 
*i* - 0*1X1 -f 022X1 -f 023X3 -f 62, 
^i* - 031X1 -f as2X S + 033X3 + &3, 



the a</, bi being constants, and the matrix (a,/) what is known as orthogonal. 

I.e. there is nothing in geometry to fix either origin or the frame of reference when 
positions are concerned; and nothing to fix the frame of reference when vectors are 
concerned. 

f I.e. the bi in footnote 4 above. Sometimes a wider concept of matrices is 
permissible, all those with determinants ^ 0. We need not discuss these matters here. 

' But no quantitatively reproducible method of thermometry . 



THE NOTION OF UTILITY 23 

the notion of utility when this is based on the conventional idea of prefer- 
ence. In these cases one may be tempted to take the view that the quantity 
in question is not numerical at all, considering how arbitrary the description 
by numbers is. It seems to be preferable, however, to refrain from such 
qualitative statements and to state instead objectively up to what system 
of transformations the numerical description is determined. The case 
when the system consists of all monotone transformations is, of course, a 
rather extreme one; various graduations at the other end of the scale are 
the transformation systems mentioned above: inhomogeneous or homo- 
geneous orthogonal linear transformations in space, linear transformations 
of one numerical variable, multiplication of that variable by a constant. 1 
In fine, the case even occurs where the numerical description is absolutely 
rigorous, i.e. where no transformations at all need be tolerated. 2 

3.4.6. Given a physical quantity, the system of transformations up to 
which it is described by numbers may vary in time, i.e. with the stage of 
development of the subject. Thus temperature was originally a number 
only up to any monotone transformation. 8 With the development of 
thermometry particularly of the concordant ideal gas thermometry the 
transformations were restricted to the linear ones, i.e. only the absolute 
zero and the absolute unit were missing. Subsequent developments of 
thermodynamics even fixed the absolute zero so that the transformation 
system in thermodynamics consists only of the multiplication by constants. 
Examples could be multiplied but there seems to be no need to go into this 
subject further. 

For utility the situation seems to be of a similar nature. One may 
take the attitude that the only "natural" datum in this domain is the 
relation "greater," i.e. the concept of preference. In this case utilities are 
numerical up to a monotone transformation. This is, indeed, the generally 
accepted standpoint in economic literature, best expressed in the technique 
of indifference curves. 

To narrow the system of transformations it would be necessary to dis- 
cover further "natural" operations or relations in the domain of utility. 
Thus it was pointed out by Pareto 4 that an equality relation for utility 
differences would suffice; in our terminology it would reduce the transfor- 
mation system to the linear transformations. 6 However, since it does not 

1 One could also imagine intermediate cases of greater transformation systems than 
these but not containing all monotone transformations. Various forms of the theory of 
relativity give rather technical examples of this. 

2 In the usual language this would hold for physical quantities where an absolute zero 
as well as an absolute unit can be defined. This is, e.g., the case for the absolute value 
(not the vector!) of velocity in such physical theories as those in which light velocity 
plays a normative role: Maxwellian electrodynamics, special relativity. 

8 As long as only the concept of " warmer" i.e. a "natural" relation "greater" was 
known. We discussed this in extenao previously. 

4 V. Pareto, Manuel d'Economie Politique, Paris, 1907, p. 264. 

'This is exactly what Euclid did for position on a line. The utility concept of 
" preference " corresponds to the relation of " lying to the right of " there, and the (desired) 
relation of the equality of utility differences to the geometrical congruence of intervals. 



24 FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

seem that this relation is really a "natural" one i.e. one which can be 
interpreted by reproducible observations the suggestion does not achieve 
the purpose. 

3.6. Conceptual Structure of the Axiomatic Treatment of Numerical Utilities 

3.6.1. The failure of one particular device need not exclude the possibility 
of achieving the same end by another device. Our contention is that the 
domain of utility contains a "natural" operation which narrows the system 
of transformations to precisely the same extent as the other device would 
have done. This is the combination of two utilities with two given alterna- 
tive probabilities a, 1 a, (0 < a < 1) as described in 3.3.2. The 
process is so similar to the formation of centers of gravity mentioned in 
3.4.3. that it may be advantageous to use the same terminology. Thus 
we have for utilities u, v the "natural" relation u > v (read: u is preferable 
to v), and the "natural" operation an + (1 a)v, (0 < a < 1), (read: 
center of gravity of u, v with the respective weights a, 1 a; or: combina- 
tion of u, v with the alternative probabilities ,! ). If the existence 
and reproducible observability of these concepts is conceded, then our 
way is clear: We must find a correspondence between utilities and numbers 
which carries the relation u > v and the operation au + (1 a)v for 
utilities into the synonymous concepts for numbers. 

Denote the correspondence by 

u -> p = v(w), 

u being the utility and v(u) the number which the correspondence attaches 
to it. Our requirements are then: 

(3:l:a) u > v implies v(u) > v(v), 

(3:l:b) v(au + (1 - a)v) = av(u) + (1 - a)v(y). 1 

If two such correspondences 

(3:2:a) u-+p = v(u), 

(3:2:b) u - p' = v'(u), 

should exist, then they set up a correspondence between numbers 
(3:3) p+ P ', 

for which we may also write 
(3:4) P ' 



Since (3:2:a), (3:2:b) fulfill (3:1 :a), (3:1 :b), the correspondence (3:3), i.e. 
the function 0(p) in (3:4) must leave the relation p > cr 2 and the operation 

^Observe that in in each case the left-hand side has the "natural" concepts for 
utilities, and the right-hand side the conventional ones for numbers. 
1 Now these are applied to numbers p, o-l 



THE NOTION OF UTILITY 25 

ap + (1 )<r unaffected (cf footnote 1 on p. 24). I.e. 

(3:5:a) p > <r implies <f>(p) > <(<r), 

(3:5:b) <t>(ap + (1 - a)r) = a*(p) + (1 - a)0(<r). 

Hence </>(p) must be a linear function, i.e. 
(3:6) p' = <(p) es o> p + i, 

where w , i are fixed numbers (constants) with w > 0. 

So we see: If such a numerical valuation of utilities 1 exists at all, then 
it is determined up to a linear transformation. 2 ' 8 I.e. then utility is a 
number up to a linear transformation. 

In order that a numerical valuation in the above sense should exist it 
is necessary to postulate certain properties of the relation u > v and the 
operation au + (1 ct)v for utilities. The selection of these postulates 
or axioms and their subsequent analysis leads to problems of a certain 
mathematical interest. In what follows we give a general outline of the 
situation for the orientation of the reader; a complete discussion is found in 
the Appendix. 

3.5.2. A choice of axioms is not a purely objective task. It is usually 
expected to achieve some definite aim some specific theorem or theorems 
are to be derivable from the axioms and to this extent the problem is 
exact and objective. But beyond this there are always other important 
desiderata of a less exact nature: The axioms should not be too numerous, 
their system is to be as simple and transparent as possible, and each axiom 
should have an immediate intuitive meaning by which its appropriateness 
may be judged directly. 4 In a situation like ours this last requirement is 
particularly vital, in spite of its vagueness: we want to make an intuitive 
concept amenable to mathematical treatment and to see as clearly as 
possible what hypotheses this requires. 

The objective part of our problem is clear: the postulates must imply 
the existence of a correspondence (3:2:a) with the properties (3:l:a), 
(3:l:b) as described in 3.5.1. The further heuristic, and even esthetic 
desiderata, indicated above, do not determine a unique way of finding 
this axiomatic treatment. In what follows we shall formulate a set of 
axioms which seems to be essentially satisfactory. 

1 I.e. a correspondence (3:2:a) which fulfills (3:1 :a), (3:1 :b). 
8 I.e. one of the form (3:6). 

3 Remember the physical examples of the same situation given in 3.4.4. (Our present 
discussion is somewhat more detailed.) We do not undertake to fix an absolute zero 
and an absolute unit of utility. 

4 The first and the last principle may represent at least to a certain extent opposite 
influences: If we reduce the number of axioms by merging them as far as technically 
possible, we may lose the possibility of distinguishing the various intuitive backgrounds. 
Thus we could have expressed the group (3:B) in 3.6.1. by a smaller number of axioms, 
but this would have obscured the subsequent analysis of 3.6.2. 

To strike a proper balance is a matter of practical and to some extent even esthetic 
judgment. 



26 FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

3.6. The Axioms and Their Interpretation 

3.6.1. Our axioms are these: 

We consider a system U of entities 1 u, v, w, . In V a relation is 
given, u > v, and for any number a, (0 < a < 1), an operation 

au + (1 a)v = w. 
These concepts satisfy the following axioms: 

(3: A) u > v is a complete ordering of f/. 2 

This means: Write u < v when v > u. Then: 

(3:A:a) For any two u y v one and only one of the three following 

relations holds: 

u = v t u > v, u < v. 

(3:A:b) u > v, v > w imply u > w. z 

(3:B) Ordering and combining. 4 

(3:B:a) u < v implies that u < au + (1 a)v. 

(3:B:b) u > v implies that u > au + (1 a)v. 

(3:B:c) u < w < v implies the existence of an a with 

au + (1 a)v < w. 
(3:B:d) u > w > v implies the existence of an a with 

au + (1 a)v > w. 
(3:C) Algebra of combining. 

(3:C:a) au + (1 - a)v = (1 - a)v + au. 

(3:C:b) a(ftu + (1 - fiv) + (1 - a)v = yu + (1 - y)v 

where 7 = aft. 

One can show that these axioms imply the existence of a correspondence 
(3:2:a) with the properties (3:1 :a), (3:1 :b) as described in 3.5.1. Hence 
the conclusions of 3.5.1. hold good: The system U i.e. in our present 
interpretation, the system of (abstract) utilities is one of numbers up to 
a linear transformation. 

The construction of (3:2:a) (with (3:1 :a), (3:1 :b) by means of the 
axioms (3:A)-(3:C)) is a purely mathematical task which is somewhat 
lengthy, although it runs along conventional lines and presents no par- 

1 This is, of course, meant to be the system of (abstract) utilities, to be characterized 
by our axioms. Concerning the general nature of the axiomatic method, cf. the remarks 
and references in the last part of 10.1.1. 

* For a more systematic mathematical discussion of this notion, cf. 65.3.1. The 
equivalent concept of the completeness of the system of preferences was previously con- 
sidered at the beginning of 3.3.2. and of 3.4.6. 

8 These conditions (3:A:a), (3: Aft) correspond to (65:A:a), (65:A:b) in 65.3.1. 

4 Remember that the a, 0, y occurring here are always > 0, < 1. 



THE NOTION OF UTILITY 27 

ticular difficulties. (Cf. Appendix.) 

It seems equally unnecessary to carry out the usual logistic discussion 
of these axioms 1 on this occasion. 

We shall however say a few more words about the intuitive meaning 
i.e. the justification of each one of our axioms (3:A)-(3:C). 

3.6.2. The analysis of our postulates follows: 

(3:A:a*) This is the statement of the completeness of the system of 

individual preferences. It is customary to assume this when 
discussing utilities or preferences, e.g. in the " indifference curve 
analysis method." These questions were already considered in 
3.3.4. and 3.4.6. 

(3:A:b*) This is the " transitivity " of preference, a plausible and 

generally accepted property. 

(3:B:a*) We state here: If v is preferable to u, then even a chance 

1 a of v alternatively to u is preferable. This is legitimate 
since any kind of complementarity (or the opposite) has been 
excluded, cf. the beginning of 3.3.2. 

(3:B:b*) This is the dual of (3:B:a*), with "less preferable" in place of 

" preferable." 

(3:B:c*) We state here: If w is preferable to u, and an even more 

preferable v is also given, then the combination of u with a 
chance 1 a of v will not affect w'& preferability to it if this 
chance is small enough. I.e.: However desirable v may be in 
itself, one can make its influence as weak as desired by giving 
it a sufficiently small chance. This is a plausible " continuity" 
assumption. 

(3 :B :d*) This is the dual of (3 :B :c*), with "less preferable " in place. of 

"preferable." 

(3:C:a*) This is the statement that it is irrelevant in which order the 

constituents u, v of a combination are named. It is legitimate, 
particularly since the constituents are alternative events, cf. 
(3:B:a*) above. 

(3:C:b*) This is the statement that it is irrelevant whether a com- 

bination of two constituents is obtained in two successive 
steps, first the probabilities a, 1 a, then the probabilities 0, 
1 /J; or in one operation, the probabilities 7, 1 y where 
7 = a. 2 The same things can be said for this as for (3:C:a*) 
above. It may be, however, that this postulate has a deeper 
significance, to which one allusion is made in 3.7.1. below. 

1 A similar situation is dealt with more exhaustively in 10.; those axioms describe a 
subject which is more vital for our main objective. The logistic discussion is indicated 
there in 10.2. Some of the general remarks of 10.3. apply to the present case also. 

2 This is of course the correct arithmetic of accounting for two successive admixtures 
of v with u. 



28 FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

3.7. General Remarks Concerning the Axioms 

3.7.1. At this point it may be well to stop and to reconsider the situa- 
tion. Have we not shown too much? We can derive from the postulates 
(3:A)-(3:C) the numerical character of utility in the sense of (3:2:a) and 
(3:1 :a), (3:1 :b) in 3.5.1.; and (3:1 :b) states that the numerical values of 
utility combine (with probabilities) like mathematical expectations! And 
yet the concept of mathematical expectation has been often questioned, 
and its legitimateness is certainly dependent upon some hypothesis con- 
cerning the nature of an " expectation." 1 Have we not then begged the 
question? Do not our postulates introduce, in some oblique way, the 
hypotheses which bring in the mathematical expectation? 

More specifically: May there not exist in an individual a (positive or 
negative) utility of the mere act of " taking a chance," of gambling, wRich 
the use of the mathematical expectation obliterates? 

How did our axioms (3:A)-(3:C) get around this possibility? 

As far as we can see, our postulates (3:A)-(3:C) do not attempt to avoid 
it. Even that one which gets closest to excluding a "utility of gambling" 
(3:C:b) (cf. its discussion in 3.6.2.), seems to be plausible and legitimate, 
unless a much more refined system of psychology is used than the one now 
available for the purposes of economics. The fact that a numerical utility 
with a formula amounting to the use of mathematical expectations can 
be built upon (3:A)-(3:C), seems to indicate this: We have practically 
defined numerical utility as being that thing for which the calculus of 
mathematical expectations is legitimate. 2 Since (3:A)-(3:C) secure that 
the necessary construction can be carried out, concepts like a " specific 
utility of gambling" cannot be formulated free of contradiction on this 
level. 3 

3.7.2. As we have stated, the last time in 3.6.1., our axioms are based 
on the relation u > v and on the operation au + (1 a)v for utilities. 
It seems noteworthy that the latter may be regarded as more immediately 
given than the former: One can hardly doubt that anybody who could 
imagine two alternative situations with the respective utilities u, v could 
not also conceive the prospect of having both with the given respective 
probabilities ,! . On the other hand one may question the postulate 
of axiom (3:A:a) for u > v, i.e. the completeness of this ordering. 

Let us consider this point for a moment. We have conceded that one 
may doubt whether a person^can always decide which of two alternatives 

1 Cf. Karl Menger: Das Unsicherheitsmoment in der Wertlehre, Zeitschrift ftir 
National6konomie, vol. 5, (1934) pp. 459ff. and Gerhard Tintner: A contribution to the 
non-static Theory of Choice, Quarterly Journal of Economics, vol. LVI, (1942) pp. 274ff. 
1 Thus Daniel Bernoulli's well known suggestion to "solve" the "St. Petersburg 
Paradox" by the use of the so-called "moral expectation" (instead of the mathematical 
expectation) means defining the utility numerically as the logarithm of one's monetary 
possessions. 

9 This may seem to be a paradoxical assertion. But anybody who has seriously tried 
to axiomatize that elusive concept, will probably concur with it. 



THE NOTION OF UTILITY 29 

with the utilities u, v he prefers. 1 But, whatever the merits of this 
doubt are, this possibility i.e. the completeness of the system of (indi- 
vidual) preferences must be assumed even for the purposes of the "indiffer- 
ence curve method" (cf. our remarks on (3:A:a) in 3.6.2.). But if this 
property of u > v 2 is assumed, then our use of the much less questionable 
au + (1 ot)v * yields the numerical utilities too! 4 

If the general comparability assumption is not made, 5 a mathematical 
theory based on au + (1 <x)v together with what remains of u > v 
is still possible. 6 It leads to what may be described as a many-dimensional 
vector concept of utility. This is a more complicated and less satisfactory 
set-up, but we do not propose to treat it systematically at this time. 

3.7.3. This brief exposition does not claim to exhaust the subject, but 
we hope to have conveyed the essential points. To avoid misunderstand- 
ings, the following further remarks may be useful. 

(1) We re-emphasize that we are considering only utilities experienced 
by one person. These considerations do not imply anything concerning the 
comparisons of the utilities belonging to different individuals. 

(2) It cannot be denied that the analysis of the methods which make use 
of mathematical expectation (cf. footnote 1 on p. 28 for the literature) is 
far from concluded at present. Our remarks in 3.7.1. lie in this direction, 
but much more should be said in this respect. There are many interesting 
questions involved, which however lie beyond the scope of this work. 
For our purposes it suffices to observe that the validity of the simple and 
plausible axioms (3:A)-(3:C) in 3.6.1. for the relation u > v and the oper- 
ation au + (1 a)v makes the utilities numbers up to a linear transforma- 
tion in the sense discussed in these sections. 

3.8. The Role of the Concept of Marginal Utility . 

3.8.1. The preceding analysis made it clear that we feel free to make 
use of a numerical conception of utility. On the other hand, subsequent 

1 Or that he can assert that they are precisely equally desirable. 

2 I.e. the completeness postulate (3:A:a). 

1 I.e. the postulates (3 :B), (3:C) together with the obvious postulate (3:A:b). 

4 At this point the reader may recall the familiar argument according to which the 
unnumerical ("indifference curve") treatment of utilities is preferable to any numerical 
one, because it is simpler and based on fewer hypotheses. This objection might be 
legitimate if the numerical treatment were based on Pareto's equality relation for utility 
differences (cf. the end of 3.4.6.). This relation is, indeed, a stronger and more compli- 
cated hypothesis, added to the original ones concerning the general comparability of 
utilities (completeness of preferences). 

However, we used the operation au + (1 ) instead, and we hope that the reader 
will agree with us that it represents an even safer assumption than that of the complete- 
ness of preferences. 

We think therefore that our procedure, as distinguished from Pareto's, is not open 
to the objections based on the necessity of artificial assumptions and a loss of simplicity. 

6 This amounts to weakening (3:A:a) to an (3:A:a') by replacing in it "one and only 
one" by "at most one/' The conditions (3:A:a') (3:A:b) then correspond to (65:B:a), 
(65:B:b). 

6 In this case some modifications in the groups of postulates (3:B), (3:0) are also 
necessary. 



30 FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

discussions will show that we cannot avoid the assumption that all subjects 
of the economy under consideration are completely informed about the 
physical characteristics of the situation in which they operate and are able 
to perform all statistical, mathematical, etc., operations which this knowl- 
edge makes possible. The nature and importance of this assumption has 
been given extensive attention in the literature and the subject is probably 
very far from being exhausted. We propose not to enter upon it. The 
question is too vast and too difficult and we believe that it is best to " divide 
difficulties." I.e. we wish to avoid this complication which, while interest- 
ing in its own right, should be considered separately from our present 
problem. 

Actually we think that our investigations although they assume 
" complete information" without any further discussion do make a con- 
tribution to the study of this subject. It will be seen that many economic 
and social phenomena which are usually ascribed to the individual's state of 
" incomplete information" make their appearance in our theory and can be 
satisfactorily interpreted with its help. Since our theory assumes " com- 
plete information," we conclude from this that those phenomena have 
nothing to do with the individual's " incomplete information." Some 
particularly striking examples of this will be found in the concepts of 
" discrimination" in 33.1., of "incomplete exploitation" in 38.3., and of the 
"transfer" or "tribute" in 46.11., 46.12. 

On the basis of the above we would even venture to question the impor- 
tance usually ascribed to incomplete information in its conventional sense 1 
in economic and social theory. It will appear that some phenomena which 
would prima facie have to be attributed to this factor, have nothing to do 
with it. 2 

3.8.2. Let us now consider an isolated individual with definite physical 
characteristics and with definite quantities of goods at his disposal. In 
view of what was said above, he is in a position to determine the maximum 
utility which can be obtained in this situation. Since the maximum is a 
well-defined quantity, the same is true for the increase which occurs when a 
unit of any definite good is added to the stock of all goods in the possession 
of the individual. This is, of course, the classical notion of the marginal 
utility of a unit of the commodity in question. 8 

These quantities are clearly of decisive importance in the "Robinson 
Crusoe" economy. The above marginal utility obviously corresponds to 

1 We shall see that the rules of the games considered may explicitly prescribe that 
certain participants should not possess certain pieces of information. Cf. 6.3., 6.4. 
(Games in which this does not happen are referred to in 14.8. and in (15:B) of 15.3.2., and 
are called games with " perfect information.") We shall recognize and utilize this kind of 
"incomplete information" (according to the above, rather to be called "imperfect 
information"). But we reject all other types, vaguely defined by the use of concepts 
like complication, intelligence, etc. 

2 Our theory attributes these phenomena to the possibility of multiple "stable 
standards of behavior" cf 4.6. and the end of 4.7. 

* More precisely: the so-called "indirectly dependent expected utility." 



SOLUTIONS AND STANDARDS OF BEHAVIOR 31 

the maximum effort which he will be willing to make if he behaves accord- 
ing to the customary criteria of rationality in order to obtain a further 
unit of that commodity. 

It is not clear at all, however, what significance it has in determining 
the behavior of a participant in a social exchange economy. We saw that 
the principles of rational behavior in this case still await formulation, and 
that they are certainly not expressed by a maximum requirement of the 
Crusoe type. Thus it must be uncertain whether marginal utility has any 
meaning at all in this case. 1 

Positive statements on this subject will be possible only after we have 
succeeded in developing a theory of rational behavior in a social exchange 
economy, that is, as was stated before, with the help of the theory of 
"games of strategy." It will be seen that marginal utility does, indeed, 
play an important role in this case too, but in a more subtle way than is 
usually assumed. 

4. Structure of the Theory : Solutions and Standards of Behavior 

4.1. The Simplest Concept of a Solution for One Participant 

4.1.1. We have now reached the point where it becomes possible to 
give a positive description of our proposed procedure. This means pri- 
marily an outline and an account of the main technical concepts and 
devices. 

As we stated before, we wish to find the mathematically complete 
principles which define " rational behavior" for the participants in a social 
economy, and to derive from them the general characteristics of that 
behavior. And while the principles ought to be perfectly general i.e., 
valid in all situations we may be satisfied if we can find solutions, for the 
moment, only in some characteristic special cases. 

First of all we must obtain a clear notion of what can be accepted as a 
solution of this problem; i.e., what the amount of information is which a 
solution must convey, and what we should expect regarding its formal 
structure, A precise analysis becomes possible only after these matters 
have been clarified. 

4.1.2. The immediate concept of a solution is plausibly a set of rules for 
each participant which tell him how to behave in every situation which may 
conceivably arise. One may object at this point that this view is unneces- 
sarily inclusive. Since we want to theorize about " rational behavior," there 
seems to be no need to give the individual advice as to his behavior in 
situations other than those which arise in a rational community. This 
would justify assuming rational behavior on the part of the others as well, 
in whatever way we are going to characterize that. Such a procedure 
would probably lead to a unique sequence of situations to which alone our 
theory need refer. 

1 All this is understood within the domain of our several simplifying assumptions. If 
they are relaxed, then various further difficulties ensue. 



32 FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

This objection seems to be invalid for two reasons: 

First, the "rules of the game," i.e. the physical laws which give the 
factual background of the economic activities under consideration may be 
explicitly statistical The actions of the participants of the economy may 
determine the outcome only in conjunction with events which depend on 
chance (with known probabilities), cf. footnote 2 on p. 10 and 6.2.1. If 
this is taken into consideration, then the rules of behavior even in a perfectly 
rational community must provide for a great variety of situations some of 
which will be very far from optimum. 1 

Second, and this is even more fundamental, the rules of rational behavior 
must provide definitely for the possibility of irrational conduct on the part 
of others. In other words: Imagine that we have discovered a set of rules 
for all participants to be termed as "optimal" or "rational" each of 
which is indeed optimal provided that the other participants conform. 
Then the question remains as to what will happen if some of the participants 
do not conform. If that should turn out to be advantageous for them and, 
quite particularly, disadvantageous to the conformists then the above 
"solution" would seem very questionable. We are in no position to give a 
positive discussion of these things as yet but we want to make it clear 
that under such conditions the "solution," or at least its motivation, must 
be considered as imperfect and incomplete. In whatever way we formulate 
the guiding principles and the objective justification of "rational behavior," 
provisos will have to be made for every possible conduct of "the others." 
Only in this way can a satisfactory and exhaustive theory be developed. 
But if the superiority of "rational behavior" over any other kind is to be 
established, then its description must include rules of conduct for all 
conceivable situations including those where "the others" behaved 
irrationally, in the sense of the standards which the theory will set for them. 

4.1,3. At this stage the reader will observe a great similarity with the 
everyday concept of games. We think that this similarity is very essential; 
indeed, that it is more than that. For economic and social problems the 
games fulfill or should fulfill the same function which various geometrico- 
mathematical models have successfully performed in the physical sciences. 
Such models are theoretical constructs with a precise, exhaustive and not 
too complicated definition; and they must be similar to reality in those 
respects which are essential in the investigation at hand. To reca- 
pitulate in detail: The definition must be precise and exhaustive in 
order to make a mathematical treatment possible. The construct must 
not be unduly complicated, so that the mathematical treatment can be 
brought beyond the mere formalism to the point where it yields complete 
numerical results. Similarity to reality is needed to make the operation 
significant. And this similarity must usually be restricted to a few traits 

1 That a unique optimal behavior is at all conceivable in spite of the multiplicity of 
the possibilities determined by chance, is of course due to the use of the notion of "mathe- 
matical expectation. 1 ' Cf. loc. cit. above. 



SOLUTIONS AND STANDARDS OF BEHAVIOR 33 

deemed "essential" pro tempore since otherwise the above requirements 
would conflict with each other. 1 

It is clear that if a model of economic activities is constructed according 
to these principles, the description of a game results. This is particularly 
striking in the formal description of markets which are after all the core 
of the economic system but this statement is true in all cases and without 
qualifications. 

4.1.4. We described in 4.1.2. what we expect a solution i.e. a character- 
ization of " rational behavior " to consist of. This amounted to a complete 
set of rules of behavior in all conceivable situations. This holds equiv- 
alently for a social economy and for games. The entire result in the 
above sense is thus a combinatorial enumeration of enormous complexity. 
But we have accepted a simplified concept of utility according to which all 
the individual strives for is fully described by one numerical datum (cf. 
2.1.1. and 3.3.). Thus the complicated combinatorial catalogue which 
we expect from a solution permits a very brief and significant summariza- 
tion: the statement of how much 2 - 3 the participant under consideration can 
get if he behaves " rationally. " This "can get" is, of course, presumed to 
be a minimum; he may get more if the others make mistakes (behave 
irrationally). 

It ought to be understood that all this discussion is advanced, as it 
should be, preliminary to the building of a satisfactory theory along the 
lines indicated. We formulate desiderata which will serve as a gauge of 
success in our subsequent considerations; but it is in accordance with the 
usual heuristic procedure to reason about these desiderata even before 
we are able to satisfy them. Indeed, this preliminary reasoning is an 
essential part of the process of finding a satisfactory theory. 4 

4.2. Extension to All Participants 

4.2.1. We have considered so far only what the solution ought to be for 
one participant. Let us now visualize all participants simultaneously. 
I.e., let us consider a social economy, or equivalently a game of a fixed 
number of (say n) participants. The complete information which a solution 
should convey is, as we discussed it, of a combinatorial nature. It was 
indicated furthermore how a single quantitative statement contains the 
decisive part of this information, by stating how much each participant 

1 E.g., Newton's description of the solar system by a small number of "masspomts." 
These points attract each other and move like the stars; this is the similarity in the essen- 
tials, while the enormous wealth of the other physical features of the planets has been left 
out of account. 

2 Utility; for an entrepreneur, profit ; for a player, gain or loss. 

8 We mean, of course, the "mathematical expectation," if there is an explicit element 
of chance. Cf. the first remark in 4.1.2. and also the discussion of 3.7.1. 

4 Those who are familiar with the development of physics will know how important 
such heuristic considerations can be. Neither general relativity nor quantum mechanics 
could have been found without a "T>rA-thpnrptip*i ;/ Hiannaainn nf thft HpaidemtA concern- 
ing the theory-to-be. 



34 FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

obtains by behaving rationally. Consider these amounts which the several 
participants ''obtain. " If the solution did nothing more in the quantitative 
sense than specify these amounts, 1 then it would coincide with the well 
known concept of imputation: it would just state how the total proceeds 
are to be distributed among the participants. 2 

We emphasize that the problem of imputation must be solved both 
when the total proceeds are in fact identically zero and when they are vari- 
able. This problem, in its general form, has neither been properly formu- 
lated nor solved in economic literature. 

4.2.2. We can see no reason why one should not be satisfied with a 
solution of this nature, providing it can be found: i.e. a single imputation 
which meets reasonable requirements for optimum (rational) behavior. 
(Of course we have not yet formulated these requirements. For an exhaus- 
tive discussion, cf. loc. cit. below.) The structure of the society under con- 
sideration would then be extremely simple: There would exist an absolute 
state of equilibrium in which the quantitative share of every participant 
would be precisely determined. 

It will be seen however that such a solution, possessing all necessary 
properties, does not exist in general. The notion of a solution will have 
to be broadened considerably, and it will be seen that this is closely con- 
nected with certain inherent features of social organization that are well 
known from a " common sense " point of view but thus far have not been 
viewed in proper perspective. (Cf. 4.6. and 4.8.1.) 

4.2.3. Our mathematical analysis of the problem will show that there 
exists, indeed, a not inconsiderable family of games where a solution can be 
defined and found in the above sense: i.e. as one single imputation. In 
such cases every participant obtains at least the amount thus imputed to 
him by just behaving appropriately, rationally. Indeed, he gets exactly 
this amount if the other participants too behave rationally; if they do not, 
he may get even more. 

These are the games of two participants where the sum of all payments 
is zero. While these games are not exactly typical for major economic 
processes, they contain some universally important traits of all games and 
the results derived from them are the basis of the general theory of games. 
We shall discuss them at length in Chapter III. 

4.3. The Solution as a Set of Imputations 

4.3.1. If either of the two above restrictions is dropped, the situation is 
altered materially. 

1 And of course, in the combinatorial sense, as outlined above, the procedure how to 
obtain them. 

*In games as usually understood the total proceeds are always zero; i.e. one 
participant can gain only what the others lose. Thus there is a pure problem of distri- 
bution i.e. imputation and absolutely none of increasing the total utility, the "social 
product." In all economic questions the latter problem arises as well, but the question 
of imputation remains. Subsequently we shall broaden the concept of a game by drop- 
ping the requirement of the total proceeds being zero (cf. Ch. XI). 



SOLUTIONS AND STANDARDS OF BEHAVIOR 35 

The simplest game where the second requirement is overstepped is a 
two-person game where the sum of all payments is variable. This cor- 
responds to a social economy with two participants and allows both for 
their interdependence and for variability of total utility with their behavior. 1 
As a matter of fact this is exactly the case of a bilateral monopoly (cf. 
6L2.-61.6.). The well known "zone of uncertainty " which is found in 
current efforts to solve the problem of imputation indicates that a broader 
concept of solution must be sought. This case will be discussed loc. cit. 
above. For the moment we want to use it only as an indicator of the diffi- 
culty and pass to the other case which is more suitable as a basis for a first 
positive step. 

4.3.2. The simplest game where the first requirement is disregarded is a 
three-person game where the sum of all payments is zero. In contrast to 
the above two-person game, this does not correspond to any fundamental 
economic problem but it represents nevertheless a basic possibility in human 
relations. The essential feature is that any two players who combine and 
cooperate against a third can thereby secure an advantage. The problem 
is how this advantage should be distributed among the two partners in this 
combination. Any such scheme of imputation will have to take into 
account that any two partners can combine; i.e. while any one combination 
is in the process of formation, each partner must consider the fact that his 
prospective ally could break away and join the third participant. 

Of course the rules of the game will prescribe how the proceeds of a 
coalition should be divided between the partners. But the detailed dis- 
cussion to be given in 22.1. shows that this will not be, in general, the 
final verdict. Imagine a game (of three or more persons) in which two 
participants can form a very advantageous coalition but where the rules 
of the game provide that the greatest part of the gain goes to the first 
participant. Assume furthermore that the second participant of this 
coalition can also enter a coalition with the third one, which is less effective 
in toto but promises him a greater individual gain than the former. In 
this situation it is obviously reasonable for the first participant to transfer 
a part of the gains which he could get from the first coalition to the second 
participant in order to save this coalition. In other words: One must 
expect that under certain conditions one participant of a coalition will be 
willing to pay a compensation to his partner. Thus the apportionment 
within a coalition depends not only upon the rules of the game but 
also upon the above principles, under the influence of the alternative 
coalitions. 2 

Common sense suggests that one cannot expect any theoretical state- 
ment as to which alliance will be formed 3 but only information concerning 

1 It will be remembered that we make use of a transferable utility, cf. 2.1.1. 

* This does not mean that the rules of the game are violated, since such compensatory 
payments, if made at all, are made freely in pursuance of a rational consideration. 

1 Obviously three combinations of two partners each are possible. In the example 
to be given in 21., any preference within the solution for a particular alliance will be a 



36 FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

how the partners in a possible combination must divide the spoils in order 
to avoid the contingency that any one of them deserts to form a combination 
with the third player. All this will be discussed in detail and quantitatively 
in Ch. V. 

It suffices to state here only the result which the above qualitative 
considerations make plausible and which will be established more rigorously 
loc. cit. A reasonable concept of a solution consists in this case of a system 
of three imputations. These correspond to the above-mentioned three 
combinations or alliances and express the division of spoils between respec- 
tive allies. 

4.3.3. The last result will turn out to be the prototype of the general 
situation. We shall see that a consistent theory will result from looking 
for solutions which are not single imputations, but rather systems of 
imputations. 

It is clear that in the above three-person game no single imputation 
from the solution is in itself anything like a solution. Any particular 
alliance describes only one particular consideration which enters the minds 
of the participants when they plan their behavior. Even if a particular 
alliance is ultimately formed, the division of the proceeds between the allies 
will be decisively influenced by the other alliances which each one might 
alternatively have entered. Thus only the three alliances and their 
imputations together form a rational whole which determines all of its 
details and possesses a stability of its own. It is, indeed, this whole which 
is the really significant entity, more so than its constituent imputations. 
Even if one of these is actually applied, i.e. if one particular alliance is 
actually formed, the others are present in a "virtual" existence: Although 
they have not materialized, they have contributed essentially to shaping and 
determining the actual reality. 

In conceiving of the general problem, a social economy or equivalently 
a game of n participants, we shall with an optimism which can be justified 
only by subsequent success expect the same thing: A solution should be a 
system of imputations 1 possessing in its entirety some kind of balance and 
stability the nature of which we shall try to determine. We emphasize 
that this stability whatever it may turn out to be will be a property 
of the system as a whole and not of the single imputations of which it is 
composed. These brief considerations regarding the three-person game 
have illustrated this point. 

4.3.4. The exact criteria which characterize a system of imputations as a 
solution of our problem are, of course, of a mathematical nature. For a 
precise and exhaustive discussion we must therefore refer the reader to the 
subsequent mathematical development of the theory. The exact definition 

limine excluded by symmetry. I.e. the game will be symmetric with respect to all three 
participants. Of. however 33.1.1. 

1 They may again include compensations between partners in a coalition, as described 
in 4.3.2. 



SOLUTIONS AND STANDARDS OF BEHAVIOR 37 

itself is stated in 30.1.1. We shall nevertheless undertake to give a prelimi- 
nary, qualitative outline. We hope this will contribute to the understanding 
of the ideas on which the quantitative discussion is based. Besides, the 
place of our considerations in the general framework of social theory will 
become clearer. 

4.4. The Intransitive Notion of "Superiority" or "Domination" 

4.4.1. Let us return to a more primitive concept of the solution which we 
know already must be abandoned. We mean the idea of a solution as a 
single imputation. If this sort of solution existed it would have to be an 
imputation which in some plausible sense was superior to all other imputa- 
tions. This notion of superiority as between imputations ought to be 
formulated in a way which takes account of the physical and social struc- 
ture of the milieu. That is, one should define that an imputation x is 
superior to an imputation y whenever this happens: Assume that society, 
i.e. the totality of all participants, has to consider the question whether or 
not to "accept" a static settlement of all questions of distribution by the 
imputation y. Assume furthermore that at this moment the alternative 
settlement by the imputation x is also considered. Then this alternative x 
will suffice to exclude acceptance of y. By this we mean that a sufficient 
number of participants prefer in their own interest x to i/, and are convinced 
or can be convinced of the possibility of obtaining the advantages of x. 
In this comparison of x to y the participants should not be influenced by 
the consideration of any third alternatives (imputations). I.e. we conceive 
the relationship of superiority as an elementary one, correlating the two 
imputations x and y only. The further comparison of three or more 
ultimately of all imputations is the subject of the theory which must 
now follow, as a superstructure erected upon the elementary concept of 
superiority. 

Whether the possibility of obtaining certain advantages by relinquishing 
y for x y as discussed in the above definition, can be made convincing to the 
interested parties will depend upon the physical facts of the situation in 
the terminology of games, on the rules of the game. 

We prefer to use, instead of " superior" with its manifold associations, a 
word more in the nature of a terminus technicus. When the above described 
relationship between two imputations x and y exists, 1 then we shall say 
that x dominates y. 

If one restates a little more carefully what should be expected from a 
solution consisting of a single imputation, this formulation obtains: Such 
an imputation should dominate all others and be dominated by 
none. 

4.4.2. The notion of domination as formulated or rather indicated 
above is clearly in the nature of an ordering, similar to the question of 

1 That is, when it holds in the mathematically precise form, which will be given in 
30.1.1. 



38 FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

preference, or of size in any quantitative theory. The notion of a single 
imputation solution 1 corresponds to that of the first element with respect 
to that ordering. 2 

The search for such a first element would be a plausible one if the order- 
ing in question, i.e. our notion of domination, possessed the important 
property of transitivity ; that is, if it were true that whenever x dominates 
y and y dominates z, then also x dominates z. In this case one might proceed 
as follows: Starting with an arbitrary x, look for a y which dominates a:; if 
such a y exists, choose one and look for a z which dominates y\ if such a z 
exists, choose one and look for a u which dominates z, etc. In most practical 
problems there is a fair chance that this process either terminates after a 
finite number of steps with a w which is undominated by anything else, or 
that the sequence x, y, z, u, , goes on ad infinitum, but that these 
x, y, z, u, tend to a limiting position w undominated by anything else. 
And, due to the transitivity referred to above, the final w will in either case 
dominate all previously obtained x, y, z, w, . 

We shall not go into more elaborate details which could and should 
be given in an exhaustive discussion. It will probably be clear to the reader 
that the progress through the sequence #, y, z, u, - corresponds to 
successive " improvements " culminating in the " optimum," i.e. the "first" 
element w which dominates all others and is not dominated. 

All this becomes very different when transitivity does not prevail. 
In that case any attempt to reach an "optimum" by successive improve- 
ments may be futile. It can happen that x is dominated by y y y by z, and 
z in turn by x. 8 

4.4.3. Now the notion of domination on which we rely is, indeed, not 
transitive. In our tentative description of this concept we indicated that x 
dominates y when there exists a group of participants each one of whom 
prefers his individual situation in x to that in y, and who are convinced 
that they are able as a group i.e. as an alliance to enforce their prefer- 
ences. We shall discuss these matters in detail in 30.2. This group of 
participants shall be called the "effective set" for the domination of x over y. 
Now when x dominates y and y dominates z, the effective sets for these two 
dominations may be entirely disjunct and therefore no conclusions can be 
drawn concerning the relationship between z and x. It can even happen 
that z dominates x with the help of a third effective set, possibly disjunct' 
from both previous ones. 

1 We continue to use it as an illustration although we have shown already that it is a 
forlorn hope. The reason for this is that, by showing what is involved if certain complica- 
tions did not arise, we can put these complications into better perspective. Our real 
interest at this stage lies of course in these complications, which are quite fundamental. 

1 The mathematical theory of ordering is very simple and leads probably to a deeper 
understanding of these conditions than any purely verbal discussion. The necessary 
mathematical considerations will be found in 65.3. 

8 In the case of transitivity this is impossible because if a proof be wanted x never 
dominates itself. Indeed, if e.g. y dominates x, z dominates y, and x dominates z, then 
we can infer by transitivity that x dominates x. 



SOLUTIONS AND STANDARDS OF BEHAVIOR 39 

This lack of transitivity, especially in the above formalistic presentation, 
may appear to be an annoying complication and it may even seem desirable 
to make an effort to rid the theory of it. Yet the reader who takes another 
look at the last paragraph will notice that it really contains only a circum- 
locution of a most typical phenomenon in all social organizations. The 
domination relationships between various imputations z, i/, z, i.e. 
between various states of society correspond to the various ways in which 
these can unstabilize i.e. upset each other. That various groups of 
participants acting as effective sets in various relations of this kind may 
bring about "cyclical" dominations e.g., y over x, z over y, and x over z 
is indeed one of the most characteristic difficulties which a theory of these 
phenomena must face. 

4.5. The Precise Definition of a Solution 

4.6.1. Thus our task is to replace the notion of the optimum i.e. of the 
first element by something which can take over its functions in a static 
equilibrium. This becomes necessary because the original concept has 
become untenable. We first observed its breakdown in the specific instance 
of a certain three-person game in 4.3.2.-4.3.3. But now we have acquired 
a deeper insight into the cause of its failure: it is the nature of our concept of 
domination, and specifically its intransitivity. 

This type of relationship is not at all peculiar to our problem. Other 
instances of it are well known in many fields and it is to be regretted that 
they have never received a generic mathematical treatment. We mean all 
those concepts which are in the general nature of a comparison of preference 
or "superiority," or of order, but lack transitivity: e.g., the strength of 
chess players in a tournament, the "paper form" in sports and races, etc. 1 

4.5.2. The discussion of the three-person game in 4.3.2.-4.3.3. indicated 
that the solution will be, in general, a set of imputations instead of a single 
imputation. That is, the concept of the "first element" will have to be 
replaced by that of a set of elements (imputations) with suitable properties. 
In the exhaustive discussion of this game in 32. (cf. also the interpreta- 
tion in 33.1.1. which calls attention to some deviations) the system of three 
imputations, which was introduced as the solution of the three-person game in 
4.3.2.-4.3.3., will be derived in an exact way with the help of the postulates 
of 30.1.1. These postulates will be very similar to those which character- 
ize a first element. They are, of course, requirements for a set of elements 
(imputations), but if that set should turn out to consist of a single element 
only, then our postulates go over into the characterization of the first 
element (in the total system of all imputations). 

We do not give a detailed motivation for those postulates as yet, but we 
shall formulate them now hoping that the reader will find them to be some- 

1 Some of these problems have been treated mathematically by the introduction of 
chance and probability. Without denying that this approach has a certain justification, 
we doubt whether it is conducive to a complete understanding even in those cases. It 
would be altogether inadequate for our considerations of social organization. 



40 FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

what plausible. Some reasons of a qualitative nature, or rather one possible 
interpretation, will be given in the paragraphs immediately following. 

4.5.3. The postulates are as follows: A set S of elements (imputations) 
is a solution when it possesses these two properties: 

(4:A:a) No y contained in S is dominated by an x contained in S. 

(4:A:b) Every y not contained in S is dominated by some x con- 

tained in S. 

(4:A:a) and (4:A:b) can be stated as a single condition: 

(4:A:c) The elements of S are precisely those elements which are 

undominated by elements of S. 1 

The* reader who is interested in this type of exercise may now verify 
our previous assertion that for a set S which consists of a single element x 
the above conditions express precisely that x is the first element. 

4.5.4. Part of the malaise which the preceding postulates may cause at 
first sight is probably due to their circular character. This is particularly 
obvious in the form (4:A:c), where the elements of S are characterized by a 
relationship which is again dependent upon S. It is important not to 
misunderstand the meaning of this circumstance. 

Since our definitions (4:A:a) and (4:A:b), or (4:A:c), are circular i.e. 
implicit for S, it is not at all clear that there really exists an S which 
fulfills them, nor whether if there exists one the S is unique. Indeed 
these questions, at this stage still unanswered, are the main subject of the 
subsequent theory. What is clear, however, is that these definitions tell 
unambiguously whether any particular S is or is not a solution. If one 
insists on associating with the concept of a definition the attributes of 
existence and uniqueness of the object defined, then one must say: We 
have not given a definition of S, but a definition of a property of S we 
have not defined the solution but characterized all possible solutions. 
Whether the totality of all solutions, thus circumscribed, contains no S, 
exactly one S, or several <S's, is subject for further inquiry. 2 

4.6. Interpretation of Our Definition in Terms of "Standards of Behavior" 

4.6.1. The single imputation is an often used and well understood con- 
cept of economic theory, while the sets of imputations to which we have 
been led are rather unfamiliar ones. It is therefore desirable to correlate 
them with something which has a well established place in our thinking 
concerning social phenomena. 

1 Thus (4:A:c) is an exact equivalent of (4:A:a) and (4:A:b) together. It may impress 
the mathematically untrained reader as somewhat involved, although it is really a 
straightforward expression of rather simple ideas. 

2 It should be unnecessary to say that the circularity, or rather implicitness, of 
(4:A:a) and (4:A:b), or (4:A:c), does not at all mean that they are tautological. They 
express, of course, a very serious restriction of S. 



SOLUTIONS AND STANDARDS OF BEHAVIOR 41 

Indeed, it appears that the sets of imputations S which we are consider- 
ing correspond to the "standard of behavior " connected with a social 
organization. Let us examine this assertion more closely. 

Let the physical basis of a social economy be given, or, to take a 
broader view of the matter, of a society. 1 According to all tradition and 
experience human beings have a characteristic way of adjusting themselves 
to such a background. This consists of not setting up one rigid system of 
apportionment, i.e. of imputation, but rather a variety of alternatives, 
which will probably all express some general principles but nevertheless 
differ among themselves in many particular respects. 2 This system of 
imputations describes the " established order of society " or " accepted 
standard of behavior/ 1 

Obviously no random grouping of imputations will do as such a " stand- 
ard of behavior ": it will have to satisfy certain conditions which character- 
ize it as a possible order of things. This concept of possibility must clearly 
provide for conditions of stability. The reader will observe, no doubt, 
that our procedure in the previous paragraphs is very much in this spirit: 
The sets S of imputations x, y, z, correspond to what we now call 
"standard of behavior/' and the conditions (4:A:a) and (4:A:b), or (4:A:c), 
which characterize the solution S express, indeed, a stability in the above 
sense. 

4.6.2. The disjunction into (4:A:a) and (4:A:b) is particularly appropri- 
ate in this instance. Recall that domination of y by x means that the 
imputation x, if taken into consideration, excludes acceptance of the 
imputation y (this without forecasting what imputation will ultimately be 
accepted, cf. 4.4.1. and 4.4.2.). Thus (4:A:a) expresses the fact that the 
standard of behavior is free from inner contradictions: No imputation y 
belonging to S i.e. conforming with the "accepted standard of behavior" 
can be upset i.e. dominated by another imputation x of the same kind. 
On the other hand (4:A:b) expresses that the "standard of behavior " can 
be used to discredit any non-conforming procedure: Every imputation y 
not belonging to S can be upset i.e. dominated by an imputation x 
belonging to S. 

Observe that we have not postulated in 4.5.3. that a y belonging to S 
should never be dominated by any x. 3 Of course, if this should happen, then 
x would have to be outside of S, due to (4:A:a). In the terminology of 
social organizations: An imputation y which conforms with the "accepted 

1 In the case of a game this means simply as we have mentioned before that the 
rules of the game are given. But for the present simile the comparison with a social 
economy is more useful. We suggest therefore that the reader forget temporarily the 
analogy with games and think entirely in terms of social organization. 

2 There may be extreme, or to use a mathematical term, "degenerate" special cases 
where the setup is of such exceptional simplicity that a rigid single apportionment can 
be put into operation. But it seems legitimate to disregard them as non-typical. 

8 It can be shown, cf. (31 :M) in 31.2.3., that such a postulate cannot be fulfilled 
in general; i.e. that in all really interesting cases it is impossible to find an S which satisfies 
it together with our other requirements. 



42 FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

standard of behavior" may be upset by another imputation x, but in this 
case it is certain that x does not conform. l It follows from our other require- 
ments that then x is upset in turn by a third imputation z which again 
conforms. Since y and z both conform, z cannot upset y a further illustra- 
tion of the intransitivity of " domination. " 

Thus our solutions S correspond to such " standards of behavior ' as 
have an inner stability: once they are generally accepted they overrule 
everything else and no part of them can be overruled within the limits of 
the accepted standards. This is clearly how things are in actual social 
organizations, and it emphasizes the perfect appropriateness of the circular 
character of our conditions in 4.5.3. 

4.6.3. We have previously mentioned, but purposely neglected to dis- 
cuss, an important objection: That neither the existence nor the uniqueness 
of a solution S in the sense of the conditions (4:A:a) and (4:A:b), or (4:A:c), 
in 4.5.3. is evident or established. 

There can be, of course, no concessions as regards existence. If it 
should turn out that our requirements concerning a solution S are, in any 
special case, unfulfillable, this would certainly necessitate a fundamental 
change in the theory. Thus a general proof of the existence of solutions S 
for all particular cases 2 is most desirable. It will appear from our subse- 
quent investigations that this proof has not yet been carried out in full 
generality but that in all cases considered so far solutions were found. 

As regards uniqueness the situation is altogether different. The often 
mentioned " circular" character of our requirements makes it rather 
probable that the solutions are not in general unique. Indeed we shall in 
most cases observe a multiplicity of solutions. 3 Considering what we have 
said about interpreting solutions as stable " standards of behavior" this has 
a simple and not unreasonable meaning, namely that given the same 
physical background different " established orders of society" or " accepted 
standards of behavior" can be built, all possessing those characteristics of 
inner stability which we have discussed. Since this concept of stability 
is admittedly of an "inner" nature i.e. operative only under the hypothesis 
of general acceptance of the standard in question these different standards 
may perfectly well be in contradiction with each other. 

4.6.4. Our approach should be compared with the widely held view 
that a social theory is possible only on the basis of some preconceived 
principles of social purpose. These principles would include quantitative 
statements concerning both the aims to be achieved in toto and the appor- 
tionments between individuals. Once they are accepted, a simple maximum 
problem results. 

1 We use the word "conform" (to the "standard of behavior'') temporarily as a 
synonym for being contained in S, and the word "upset" as a synonym for dominate. 

*In the terminology of games: for all numbers of participants and for all possible 
rules of the game. 

1 An interesting exception is 65.8. 



SOLUTIONS AND STANDARDS OF BEHAVIOR 43 

Let us note that no such statement of principles is ever satisfactory 
per se, and the arguments adduced in its favor are usually either those of 
inner stability or of less clearly defined kinds of desirability, mainly con- 
cerning distribution. 

Little can be said about the latter type of motivation. Our problem 
is not to determine what ought to happen in pursuance of any set of 
necessarily arbitrary a priori principles, but to investigate where the 
equilibrium of forces lies. 

As far as the first motivation is concerned, it has been our aim to give 
just those arguments precise and satisfactory form, concerning both global 
aims and individual apportionments. This made it necessary to take up 
the entire question of inner stability as a problem in its own right. A theory 
which is consistent at this point cannot fail to give a precise account of the 
entire interplay of economic interests, influence and power. 

4.7. Games and Social Organizations 

4.7. It may now be opportune to revive the analogy with games, which 
we purposely suppressed in the previous paragraphs (cf. footnote 1 on 
p. 41). The parallelism between the solutions S in the sense of 4.5.3. on 
one hand and of stable " standards of behavior " on the other can be used 
for corroboration of assertions concerning these concepts in both directions. 
At least we hope that this suggestion will have some appeal to the reader. 
We think that the procedure of the mathematical theory of games of 
strategy gains definitely in plausibility by the correspondence which exists 
between its concepts and those of social organizations. On the other 
hand, almost every statement which we or for that matter anyone else 
ever made concerning social organizations, runs afoul of some existing 
opinion. And, by the very nature of things, most opinions thus far could 
hardly have been proved or disproved within the field of social theory. 
It is therefore a great help that all our assertions can be borne out by specific 
examples from the theory of games of strategy. 

Such is indeed one of the standard techniques of using models in the 
physical sciences. This two-way procedure brings out a significant func- 
tion of models, not emphasized in their discussion in 4.1.3. 

To give an illustration: The question whether several stable " orders 
of society " or " standards of behavior " based on the same physical back- 
ground are possible or not, is highly controversial. There is little hope 
that it will be settled by the usual methods because of the enormous com- 
plexity of this problem among other reasons. But we shall give specific 
examples of games of three or four persons, where one game possesses several 
solutions in the sense of 4.5.3. And some of these examples will be seen 
to be models for certain simple economic problems. (Cf. 62.) 

4.8. Concluding Remarks 

4.8.1. In conclusion it remains to make a few remarks of a more formal 
nature. 



44 FORMULATION OF THE ECONOMIC PROBLEM 

We begin with this observation: Our considerations started with single 
imputations which were originally quantitative extracts from more 
detailed combinatorial sets of rules. From these we had to proceed to 
sets S of imputations, which under certain conditions appeared as solutions. 
Since the solutions do not seem to be necessarily unique, the complete 
answer to any specific problem consists not in finding a solution, but in 
determining the set of all solutions. Thus the entity for which we look in 
any particular problem is really a set of sets of imputations. This may seem 
to be unnaturally complicated in itself; besides there appears no guarantee 
that this process will not have to be carried further, conceivably because 
of later difficulties. Concerning these doubts it suffices to say: First, the 
mathematical structure of the theory of games of strategy provides a formal 
justification of our procedure. Second, the previously discussed connections 
with " standards of behavior " (corresponding to sets of imputations) and 
of the multiplicity of " standards of behavior " on the same physical back- 
ground (corresponding to sets of sets of imputations) make just this amount 
of complicatedness desirable. 

One may criticize our interpretation of sets of imputations as " standards 
of behavior." Previously in 4.1.2. and 4.1.4. we introduced a more ele- 
mentary concept, which may strike the reader as a direct formulation of a 
" standard of behavior": this was the preliminary combinatorial concept 
of a solution as a set of rules for each participant, telling him how to behave 
in every possible situation of the game. (From these rules the single 
imputations were then extracted as a quantitative summary, cf. above.) 
Such a simple view of the " standard of behavior" could be maintained, 
however, only in games in which coalitions and the compensations between 
coalition partners (cf. 4.3.2.) play no role, since the above rules do not 
provide for these possibilities. Games exist in which coalitions and compen- 
sations can be disregarded: e.g. the two-person game of zero-sum mentioned 
in 4.2.3., and more generally the " inessential " games to be discussed in 
27.3. and in (31 :P) of 31.2.3. But the general, typical game in particular 
all .significant problems of a social exchange economy cannot be treated with- 
out these devices. Thus the same arguments which forced us to consider sets 
of imputations instead of single imputations necessitate the abandonment 
of that narrow concept of " standard of behavior." Actually we shall call 
these sets of rules the " strategies" of the game. 

4.8.2. The next subject to be mentioned concerns the static or dynamic 
nature of the theory. We repeat most emphatically that our theory is 
thoroughly static. A dynamic theory would unquestionably be more 
complete and therefore preferable. But there is ample evidence from other 
branches of science that it is futile to try to build one as long as the static 
side is not thoroughly understood. On the other hand, the reader may 
object to some definitely dynamic arguments which were made in the course 
of our discussions. This applies particularly to all considerations concern- 
ing the interplay of various imputations under the influence of "domina- 



SOLUTIONS AND STANDARDS OF BEHAVIOR 45 

tion," cf. 4.6.2. We think that this is perfectly legitimate. A static 
theory deals with equilibria. 1 The essential characteristic of an equilibrium 
is that it has no tendency to change, i.e. that it is not conducive to dynamic 
developments. An analysis of this feature is, of course, inconceivable 
without the use of certain rudimentary dynamic concepts. The important 
point is that they are rudimentary. In other words: For the real dynamics 
which investigates the precise motions, usually far away from equilibria, a 
much deeper knowledge of these dynamic phenomena is required. 2 ' 3 

4.8.3. Finally let us note a point at which the theory of social phenomena 
will presumably take a very definite turn away from the existing patterns of 
mathematical physics. This is, of course, only a surmise on a subject where 
much uncertainty and obscurity prevail. 

Our static theory specifies equilibria i.e. solutions in the sense of 4.5.3. 
which are sets of imputations. A dynamic theory when one is found 
will probably describe the changes in terms of simpler concepts: of a single 
imputation valid at the moment under consideration or something 
similar. This indicates that the formal structure of this part of the theory 
the relationship between statics and dynamics may be generically different 
from that of the classical physical theories. 4 

All these considerations illustrate once more what a complexity of 
theoretical forms must be expected in social theory. Our static analysis 
alone necessitated the creation of a conceptual and formal mechanism which 
is very different from anything used, for instance, in mathematical physics. 
Thus the conventional view of a solution as a uniquely defined number or 
aggregate of numbers was seen to be too narrow for our purposes, in spite 
of its success in other fields. The emphasis on mathematical methods 
seems to be shifted more towards combinatorics and set theory and away 
from the algorithm of differential equations which dominate mathematical 
physics. 

1 The dynamic theory deals also with inequilibria even if they are sometimes called 
"dynamic equilibria." 

1 The above discussion of statics versus dynamics is, of course, not at all a construction 
ad hoc. The reader who is familiar with mechanics for instance will recognize in it a 
reformulation of well known features of the classical mechanical theory of statics and 
dynamics. What we do claim at this time is that this is a general characteristic of 
scientific procedure involving forces and changes in structures. 

3 The dynamic concepts which enter into the discussion of static equilibria are parallel 
to the "virtual displacements " in classical mechanics. The reader may also remember at 
this point the remarks about "virtual existence 1 ' in 4.3.3. 

4 Particularly from classical mechanics. The analogies of the type used in footnote 2 
above, cease at this point. 



CHAPTER II 
GENERAL FORMAL DESCRIPTION OF GAMES OF STRATEGY 

5. Introduction 
5.1. Shift of Emphasis from Economics to Games 

5.1. It should be clear from the discussions of Chapter I that a theory 
of rational behavior i.e. of the foundations of economics and of the main 
mechanisms of social organization requires a thorough study of the " games 
of strategy/' Consequently we must now take up the theory of games as an 
independent subject. In studying it as a problem in its own right, our 
point of view must of necessity undergo a serious shift. In Chapter I our 
primary interest lay in economics. It was only after having convinced 
ourselves of the impossibility of making progress in that field without a 
previous fundamental understanding of the games that we gradually 
approached the formulations and the questions which are partial to that 
subject. But the economic viewpoints remained nevertheless the dominant 
ones in all of Chapter I. From this Chapter II on, however, we shall have 
to treat the games as games. Therefore we shall not mind if some points 
taken up have no economic connections whatever, it would not be possible 
to do full justice to the subject otherwise. Of course most of the main 
concepts are still those familiar from the discussions of economic literature 
(cf. the next section) but the details will often be altogether alien to it 
and details, as usual, may dominate the exposition and overshadow the 
guiding principles. 

5.2. General Principles of Classification and of Procedure 

5.2.1. Certain aspects of " games of strategy" which were already 
prominent in the last sections of Chapter I will not appear in the beginning 
stages of the discussions which we are now undertaking. Specifically: 
There will be at first no mention of coalitions between players and the 
compensations which they pay to each other. (Concerning these, cf. 
4.3.2., 4.3.3., in Chapter I.) We give a brief account of the reasons, which 
will also throw some light on our general disposition of the subject. 

An important viewpoint in classifying games is this: Is the sum of all 
payments received by all players (at the end of the game) always zero; or 
is this not the case? If it is zero, then one can say that the players pay only 
to each other, and that no production or destruction of goods is involved. 
All games which are actually played for entertainment are of this type. But 
the economically significant schemes are most essentially not such. There 
the sum of all payments, the total social product, will in general not be 

46 



INTRODUCTION 47 

zero, and not even constant. I.e., it will depend on the behavior of the 
players the participants in the social economy. This distinction was 
already mentioned in 4.2.1., particularly in footnote 2, p. 34. We shall call 
games of the first-mentioned type zero-sum games, and those of the latter 
type non-zero-sum games. 

We shall primarily construct a theory of the zero-sum games, but it will 
be found possible to dispose, with its help, of all games, without restriction. 
Precisely: We shall show that the general (hence in particular the variable 
sum) n-person game can be reduced to a zero-sum n + 1-person game. 
(Cf. 56.2.2.) Now the theory of the zero-sum r?-person game will be based 
on the special case of the zero-sum two-person game. (Cf. 25.2.) Hence 
our discussions will begin with a theory of these games, which will indeed 
be carried out in Chapter III. 

Now in zero-sum two-person games coalitions and compensations 
can play no role. 1 The questions which are essential in these games are 
of a different nature. These are the main problems: How does each 
player plan his course i.e. how does one formulate an exact concept of a 
strategy? What information is available to each player at every stage 
of the game? What is the role of a player being informed about the other 
player's strategy? About the entire theory of the game? 

5.2.2. All these questions are of course essential in all games, for any 
number of players, even when coalitions and compensations have come into 
their own. But for zero-sum two-person games they are the only ones 
which matter, as our subsequent discussions will show. Again, all these 
questions have been recognized as important in economics, but we think that 
in the theory of games they arise in a more elementary as distinguished 
from composite fashion. They can, therefore, be discussed in a precise 
way and as we hope to show be disposed of. But in the process of this 
analysis it will be technically advantageous to rely on pictures and examples 
which are rather remote from the field of economics proper, and belong 
strictly to the field of games of the conventional variety. Thus the dis- 
cussions which follow will be dominated by illustrations from Chess, 
" Matching Pennies," Poker, Bridge, etc., and not from the structure of 
cartels, markets, oligopolies, etc. 

At this point it is also opportune to recall that we consider all trans- 
actions at the end of a game as purely monetary ones i.e. that we ascribe 
to all players an exclusively monetary profit motive. The meaning of this 
in terms of the utility concept was analyzed in 2.1.1. in Chapter I. For the 
present particularly for the " zero-sum two-person games" to be discussed 

1 The only fully satisfactory "proof" of this assertion lies in the construction of a 
complete theory of all zero-sum two-person games, without use of those devices. This 
will be done in Chapter III, the decisive result being contained in 17. It ought to be 
clear by common sense, however, that "understandings" and "coalitions" can have no 
role here: Any such arrangement must involve at least two players hence in this case all 
players for whom the sum of payments is identically zero. I.e. th re are no opponents 
left and no possible objectives. 



48 DESCRIPTION OF GAMES OF STRATEGY 

first (cf. the discussion of 5.2.1.) it is an absolutely necessary simplifi- 
cation. Indeed, we shall maintain it through most of the theory, although 
variants will be examined later on. (Cf. Chapter XII, in particular 66.) 

6.2.3. Our first task is to give an exact definition of what constitutes a 
game. As long as the concept of a game has not been described with 
absolute mathematical combinatorial precision, we cannot hope to 
give exact and exhaustive answers to the questions formulated at the end 
of 5.2.1. Now while our first objective is as was explained in 5.2.1. the 
theory of zero-sum two-person games, it is apparent that the exact descrip- 
tion of what constitutes a game need not be restricted to this case. Conse- 
quently we can begin with the description of the general n-person game. 
In giving this description we shall endeavor to do justice to all conceivable 
nuances and complications which can arise in a game insofar as they are 
not of an obviously inessential character. In this way we reach in several 
successive steps a rather complicated but exhaustive and mathematically 
precise scheme. And then we shall see that it is possible to replace this 
general scheme by a vastly simpler one, which is nevertheless fully and 
rigorously equivalent to it. Besides, the mathematical device which 
permits this simplification is also of an immediate significance for our 
problem: It is the introduction of the exact concept of a strategy. 

It should be understood that the detour which leads to the ultimate, 
simple formulation of the problem, over considerably more complicated 
ones is not avoidable. It is necessary to show first that all possible 
complications have been taken into consideration, and that the mathe- 
matical device in question does guarantee the equivalence of the involved 
setup to the simple. 

All this can and must be done for all games, of any number of play- 
ers. But after this aim has been achieved in entire generality, the next 
objective of the theory is as mentioned above to find a complete solution 
for the zero-sum two-person game. Accordingly, this chapter will deal 
with all games, but the next one with zero-sum two-person games only. After 
they are disposed of and some important examples have been discussed, we 
shall begin to re-extend the scope of the investigation first to zero-sum n- 
person games, and then to all games. 

Coalitions and compensations will only reappear during this latter stage. 

6. The Simplified Concept of a Game 

6.1. Explanation of the Termini Technici 

6.1. Before an exact definition of the combinatorial concept of a game 
can be given, we must first clarify the use of some termini. There are 
some notions which are quite fundamental for the discussion of games, 
but the use of which in everyday language is highly ambiguous. The words 
which describe them are used sometimes in one sense, sometimes in another, 
and occasionally worst of all as if they were synonyms. We must 



SIMPLIFIED CONCEPT OF A GAME 49 

therefore introduce a definite usage of termini technici, and rigidly adhere 
to it in all that follows. 

First, one must distinguish between the abstract concept of a game, 
and the individual plays of that game. The game is simply the totality 
of the rules which describe it. Every particular instance at which the 
game is played in a particular way from beginning to end, is a play. 1 

Second, the corresponding distinction should be made for the moves, 
which are the component elements of the game. A move is the occasion 
of a choice between various alternatives, to be made either by one of the 
players, or by some device subject to chance, under conditions precisely 
prescribed by the rules of the game. The move is nothing but this abstract 
" occasion/' with the attendant details of description, i.e. a component 
of the game. The specific alternative chosen in a concrete instance i.e. 
in a concrete play is the choice. Thus the moves are related to the 
choices in the same way as the game is to the play. The game consists 
of a sequence of moves, and the play of a sequence of choices. 2 

Finally, the rules of the game should not be confused with the strategies 
of the players. Exact definitions will be given subsequently, but the 
distinction which we stress must be clear from the start. Each player 
selects his strategy i.e. the general principles governing his choices freely. 
While any particular strategy may be good or bad provided that these 
concepts can be interpreted in an exact sense (cf. 14.5. and 17.8-17.10.) 
it is within the player's discretion to use or to reject it. The rules of the 
game, however, are absolute commands. If they are ever infringed, then 
the whole transaction by definition ceases to be the game described by those 
rules. In many cases it is even physically impossible to violate them. 3 

6.2. The Elements of the Game 

6.2.1. Let us now consider a game F of n players who, for the sake of 
brevity, will be denoted by 1, , n. The conventional picture provides 
that this game is a sequence of moves, and we assume that both the number 
and the arrangement of these moves is given ab initio. We shall see later 
that these restrictions are not really significant, and that they can be 
removed without difficulty. For the present let us denote the (fixed) 
number of moves in F by v this is an integer v = 1, 2, . The moves 
themselves we denote by 3TCi, , 3TC,, and we assume that this is the 
chronological order in which they are prescribed to take place. 

1 In most games everyday usage calls a play equally a game ; thus in chess, in poker, 
in many sports, etc. In Bridge a play corresponds to a "rubber," in Tennis to a "set," 
but unluckily in these games certain components of the play are again called "games." 
The French terihinology is tolerably unambiguous: "game" * "jeu," "play" 
"partie." 

1 In this sense we would talk in chess of the first move, and of the choice "E2-E4." 
1 E.g. : In Chess the rules of the game forbid a player to move his king into a position 
of "check." This is a prohibition in the same absolute sense in which he may not move a 
pawn sideways. But to move the king into a position where the opponent can "check- 
mate" him at the next move is merely unwise, but not forbidden. 



50 DESCRIPTION OF GAMES OF STRATEGY 

Every move 3TC,, K = 1, , v, actually consists of a number of 
alternatives, among which the choice which constitutes the move 9TC, 
takes place. Denote the number of these alternatives by a< and the 
alternatives themselves by GL K (l), , &() 

The moves are of two kinds. A move of the first kind, or a personal 
move, is a choice made by a specific player, i.e. depending on his free decision 
and nothing else. A move of the second kind, or a chance move, is a choice 
depending on some mechanical device, which makes its outcome fortuitous 
with definite probabilities. 1 Thus for every personal move it must be 
specified which player's decision determines this move, whose move it is. 
We denote the player in question (i.e. his number) by k K . So fc, = 1, , 
n. For a chance move we put (conventionally) fc< = 0. In this case the 
probabilities of the various alternatives a(l), , &(<*) must be given. 
We denote these probabilities by p(l), , p(a) respectively. 2 

6.2.2. In a move 3TC, the choice consists of selecting an alternative 
(*(!), ' , Ct(<O> i.e. its number !,,. We denote the number 
so chosen by <r,. Thus this choice is characterized by a number <r = 1, 

, a,. And the complete play is described by specifying all choices, 
corresponding to all moves OTli, , 9R,. I.e. it is described by a sequence 

Now the rule of the game T must specify what the outcome of the play 
is for each player k = !,- , n, if the play is described by a given sequence 
<TI, ov I.e. what payments every player receives when the play is 
completed. Denote the payment to the player k by $ k ($k > if k receives 
a payment, $ k < if he must make one, $* = if neither is the case). 
Thus each $* must be given as a function of the <TI, , <r,: 

$k = SF*(<ri, , <r v ), k = 1, , n. 

We emphasize again that the rules of the game T specify the function 
$k(*i) ' ' ' , <r>) only as a function, 3 i.e. the abstract dependence of each 
5u on the variables <TI, , <r . But all the time each cr, is a variable, 
with the domain of variability !,-,,. A specification of particular 
numerical values for the <r<, i.e. the selection of a particular sequence <n, 

, <r,, is no part of the game T. It is, as we pointed out above, the 
definition of a play. 

1 E.g., dealing cards from an appropriately shuffled deck, throwing dice, etc. It is 
even possible to include certain games of strength and skill, where "strategy" plays a role, 
e.g. Tennis, Football, etc. In these the actions of the players are up to a certain point 
personal moves i.e. dependent upon their free decision and beyond this point chance 
moves, the probabilities being characteristics of the player in question. 

Since the p(l), , p K (a K ) are probabilities, they are necessarily numbers *z 0. 
Since they belong to disjunct but exhaustive alternatives, their sum (for a fixed K) must 
be one. I.e. : 

3 For a systematic exposition of the concept of a function cf. 13.1. 



SIMPLIFIED CONCEPT OF A GAME 51 

6.3. Information and Preliminarity 

6.3.1. Our description of the game F is not yet complete. We have 
failed to include specifications about the state of information of every 
player at each decision which he has to make, i.e. whenever a personal 
move turns up which is his move. Therefore we now turn to this aspect 
of the matter. 

This discussion is best conducted by following the moves 9fTli, , 2fTl,, 
as the corresponding choices are made. 

Let us therefore fix our attention on a particular move 3fH. If this 
3TC< is a chance move, then nothing more need be said: the choice is decided 
by chance; nobody's will and nobody's knowledge of other things can 
influence it. But if $TC, is a personal move, belonging to the player fc, then 
it is quite important what k K 'a state of information is when he forms his 
decision concerning TO, i.e. his choice of <r. 

The only things he can be informed about are the choices corresponding 
to the moves preceding 9fR the moves SfTCi, , 9fTC_i. I.e. he may know 
the values of <TI, , <r K -.i. But he need not know that much. It is an 
important peculiarity of F, just how much information concerning (TI, , 
<r K -i the player k K is granted, when he is called upon to choose <? K . We 
shall soon show in several examples what the nature of such limitations is. 

The simplest type of rule which describes k K 's state of information at 3fn, 
is this: a set A consisting of some numbers from among X = 1, , K 1, 
is given. It is specified that k K knows the values of the a\ with X belong- 
ing to A, and that he is entirely ignorant of the <r\ with any other X. 

In this case we shall say, when X belongs to A,, that X is preliminary 
to /c. This implies X = 1, , K 1, i.e. X < K, but need not be implied 
by it. Or, if we consider, instead of X, K, the corresponding moves SfTlx, 3Tl: 
Preliminarity implies anteriority, 1 but need not be implied by it. 

6.3.2. In spite of its somewhat restrictive character, this concept of 
preliminarity deserves a closer inspection. In itself, and in its relationship 
to anteriority (cf. footnote 1 above), it gives occasion to various combina- 
torial possibilities. These have definite meanings in those games in which 
they occur, and we shall now illustrate them by some examples of particu- 
larly characteristic instances. 

6.4. Preliminarity, Transitivity, and Signaling 

6.4.1. We begin by observing that there exist games in which pre- 
liminarity and anteriority are the same thing. I.e., where the players k K 
who makes the (personal) move 9TC, is informed about the outcome of the 
choices of all anterior moves 3Tli, * , 9Tl<_ i. Chess is a typical representa- 
tive of this class of games of "perfect" information. They are generally 
considered to be of a particularly rational character. We shall see in 15., 
specifically in 15.7., how this can be interpreted in a precise way. 

1 In time, X < K means that 9H\ occurs before WL K . 



52 DESCRIPTION OF GAMES OF STRATEGY 

Chess has the further feature that all its moves are personal. Now it 
is possible to conserve the first-mentioned property the equivalence of 
preliminarity and anteriority even in games which contain chance moves. 
Backgammon is an example of this. 1 Some doubt might be entertained 
whether the presence of chance moves does not vitiate the " rational char- 
acter" of the game mentioned in connection with the preceding examples. 

We shall see in 15.7.1. that this is not so if a very plausible interpretation 
of that " rational character" is adhered to. It is not important whether 
all moves are personal or not; the essential fact is that preliminarity and 
anteriority coincide. 

6.4.2. Let us now consider games where anteriority does not imply 
preliminarity. I.e., where the player fc who makes the (personal) move 9TC, 
is not informed about everything that happened previously. There is a 
large family of games in which this occurs. These games usually con- 
tain chance moves as well as personal moves. General opinion considers 
them as being of a mixed character: while their outcome is definitely 
dependent on chance, they are also strongly influenced by the strategic 
abilities of the players. 

Poker and Bridge are good examples. These two games show, further- 
more, what peculiar features the notion of preliminarity can present, 
once it has been separated from anteriority. This point perhaps deserves 
a little more detailed consideration. 

Anteriority, i.e. the chronological ordering of the moves, possesses 
the property of transitivity. 2 Now in the present case, preliminarity 
need not be transitive. Indeed it is neither in Poker nor in Bridge, and the 
conditions under which this occurs are quite characteristic. 

Poker: Let 3TC M be the deal of his "hand" to player 1 a chance move; 
3Tlx the first bid of player 1 a personal move of 1 ; 9fTC the first (subsequent) 
bid of player 2 a personal move of 2. Then 3flfl M is preliminary to 9fTlx and 
3Tlx to 3fll but 2fTl M is not preliminary to 3TC,. 3 Thus we have intransitivity, 
but it involves both players. Indeed, it may first seem unlikely that 
preliminarity could in any game be intransitive among the personal moves 
of one particular player. It would require that this player should "forget" 
between the moves 9fTl\ and 3TC, the outcome of the choice connected with 
3TV and it is difficult to see how this "forgetting" could be achieved, and 

1 The chance moves in Backgammon are the dice throws which decide the total num- 
ber of steps by which each player's men may alternately advance. The personal moves 
are the decisions by which each player partitions that total number of steps allotted to 
him among his individual men. Also his decision to double the risk, and his alternative 
to accept or to give up when the opponent doubles. At every move, however, the out- 
come of the choices of all anterior moves are visible to all on the board. 

2 I.e. : If 3TC M is anterior to 9Tlx and 311 x to 9K then 3TC M is anterior to 9TC. Special situa- 
tions where the presence or absence of transitivity was of importance, were analyzed in 
4.4.2., 4.6.2. of Chapter I in connection with the relation of domination. 

3 I.e., 1 makes his first bid knowing his own "hand"; 2 makes his first bid knowing 
1's (preceding) first bid; but at the same time 2 is ignorant of 1's "hand." 

4 We assume that 9TC M is preliminary to 9fR\ and 3Tlx to 3TZ* but 9TC M not to 3TC*. 



SIMPLIFIED CONCEPT OF A GAME 53 

even enforced 1 Nevertheless our next example provides an instance of 
just this. 

Bridge: Although Bridge is played by 4 persons, to be denoted by 
A,B,C,D, it should be classified as a two-person game. Indeed, A and C 
form a combination which is more than a voluntary coalition, and so do 
B and D. For A to cooperate with B (or D) instead of with C would be 
" cheating," in the same sense in which it would be "cheating" to look into 
JB's cards or failing to follow suit during the play. I.e. it would be a viola- 
tion of the rules of the game. If three (or more) persons play poker, then 
it is perfectly permissible for two (or more) of them to cooperate against 
another player when their interests are parallel but in Bridge A and C 
(and similarly B and D) must cooperate, while A and B are forbidden to 
cooperate. The natural way to describe this consists in declaring that A 
and C are really one player 1, and that B and D are really one player 2. 
Or, equivalently: Bridge is a two-person game, but the two players 1 and 2 
do not play it themselves. 1 acts through two representatives A and C and 
2 through two representatives B and D. 

Consider now the representatives of 1, A and C. The rules of the game 
restrict communication, i.e. the exchange of information, between them. 
E.g.: let 9TC M be the deal of his "hand" to A a chance move; 9TCx the first 
card played by A a personal move of 1 ; 3TI, the card played into this trick 
by C a personal move of 1. Then 9TI M is preliminary to 3fllx and 2fllx to 9TC, 
but 2(TI M is not preliminary to 9TC,. 1 Thus we have again intransitivity, but 
this time it involves only one player. It is worth noting how the necessary 
"forgetting" of 3TI M between 3Tlx and 3Tl was achieved by "splitting the 
personality" of 1 into A and C. 

6.4.3. The above examples show that intransitivity of the relation of 
preliminarity corresponds to a very well known component of practical 
strategy: to the possibility of "signaling." If no knowledge of 3fTC M is 
available at 3fTC, but if it is possible to observe 9Hx's outcome at 3TC, and 3Tlx 
has been influenced by 9fTl M (by knowledge about 9TC/S outcome), then 
OTx is really a signal from 9TI M to 3TC, a device which (indirectly) relays 
information. Now two opposite situations develop, according to whether 
3flflx and 9TC, are moves of the same player, or of two different players. 

In the first case which, as we saw, occurs in Bridge the interest of 
the player (who is fc x = fc,). lies in promoting the "signaling," i.e. the 
spreading of information "within his own organization." This desire 
finds its realization in the elaborate system of "conventional signals" in 
Bridge. 2 These are parts of the strategy, and not of the rules of the game 

1 I.e. A plays his first card knowing his own "hand"; C contributes to this trick know- 
ing the (initiating) card played by A ; but at the same time C is ignorant of A's "hand/ 1 

1 Observe that this " signaling " is considered to be perfectly fair in Bridge if it is 
carried out by actions which are provided for by the rules of the game. E.g. it is correct 
for A and C (the two components of player 1, cf. 6.4.2.) to agree before the play begins! 
that an "original bid" of two trumps " indicates " a weakness of the other suits. But 
it is incorrect i.e. "cheating 11 to indicate a weakness by an inflection of the voice at 
bidding, or by tapping on the table, etc. 



54 DESCRIPTION OF GAMES OF STRATEGY 

(cf. 6.1.), and consequently they may vary, 1 while the game of Bridge 
remains the same. 

In the second case which, as we saw, occurs in Poker the interest 
of the player (we now mean k\, observe that here k\ ^ k K ) lies in preventing 
this "signaling," i.e. the spreading of information to the opponent (&<). 
This is usually achieved by irregular and seemingly illogical behavior 
(when making the choice at 3Tlx) this makes it harder for the opponent 
to draw inferences from the outcome of 3fTlx (which he sees) concerning the 
outcome of 91Z M (of which he has no direct news). I.e. this procedure makes 
the "signal" uncertain and ambiguous. We shall see in 19.2.1. that this is 
indeed the function of "bluffing" in Poker. 2 

We shall call these two procedures direct and inverted signaling. It ought 
to be added that inverted signaling i.e. misleading the opponent occurs 
in almost all games, including Bridge. This is so since it is based on the 
intransitivity of preliminarity when several players are involved, which is 
easy to achieve. Direct signaling, on the other hand, is rarer; e.g. Poker 
contains no vestige of it. Indeed, as we pointed out before, it implies the 
intransitivity of preliminarity when only one player is involved i.e. it 
requires a well-regulated " f orgetf ulness " of that player, which is obtained in 
Bridge by the device of "splitting the player up" into two persons. 

At any rate Bridge and Poker seem to be reasonably characteristic 
instances of these two kinds of intransitivity of direct and of inverted 
signaling, respectively. 

Both kinds of signaling lead to a delicate problem of balancing in actual 
playing, i.e. in the process of trying to define "good," "rational" playing. 
Any attempt to signal more or to signal less than "unsophisticated" playing 
would involve, necessitates deviations from the "unsophisticated" way of 
playing. And this is usually possible only at a definite cost, i.e. its direct 
consequences are losses. Thus the problem is to adjust this "extra" signal- 
ing so that its advantages by forwarding or by withholding information 
overbalance the losses which it causes directly. One feels that this involves 
something like the search for an optimum, although it is by no means clearly 
defined. We shall see how the theory of the two-person game takes care 
already of this problem, and we shall discuss it exhaustively in one charac- 
teristic instance. (This is a simplified form of Poker. Cf. 19.) 

Let us observe, finally, that all important examples of intransitive 
preliminarity are games containing chance moves. This is peculiar, because 
there is no apparent connection between these two phenomena. 3 - 4 Our 

1 They may even be different for the two players, i.e. for A and C on one hand and 
B and D on the other. But "within the organization' 1 of one player, e.g. for A and C, 
they must agree. 

1 And that "bluffing" is not at all an attempt to secure extra gains in any direct 
sense when holding a weak hand. Cf. loc. cit. 

* Cf . the corresponding question when preliminarity coincides with anteriority, and 
thus is transitive, as discussed in 6.4.1. As mentioned there, the presence or absence of 
chance moves is immaterial in that case. 

4 "Matching pennies" is an example which has a certain importance in this connec- 
tion. This and other related games will be diacussed in 18. 



(COMPLETE CONCEPT OF A GAME 55 

subsequent analysis will indeed show that the presence or absence of chance 
moves scarcely influences the essential aspects of the strategies in this 
situation. 

7. The Complete Concept of a Game 
7.1. Variability of the Characteristics of Each Move 

7.1.1. We introduced in 6.2.1. the a* alternatives &*(!), , Gt<(a) 
of the move STl*. Also the index fc* which characterized the move as a 
personal or chance one, and in the first case the player whose move it is; 
and in the second case the probabilities p*(l), * * , P K (<X K ) of the above alter- 
natives. We described in 6.3.1. the concept of preliminarity with the help 
of the sets A,, this being the set of all X (from among the X = 1, ,* !) 
which are preliminary to K. We failed to specify, however, whether all 
these objects a*, k f , A and the Ct(<r), p*(a) for o- = 1, , a* depend 
solely on K or also on other things. These " other things " can, of course, 
only be the outcome of the choices corresponding to the moves which are 
anterior to 3fn. I.e. the numbers <n, , <r_i. (Cf. 6.2.2.) 
This dependence requires a more detailed discussion. 
First, the dependence of the alternatives (%((?) themselves (as distin- 
guished from their number a!) on <n, , o-,_i is immaterial. We may 
as well assume that the choice corresponding to the move 311, is made not 
between the Ct,(<r) themselves, but between their numbers a. In fine, it is 
only the <r of 311*, i.e. cr, which occurs in the expressions describing the out- 
come of the play, i.e. in the functions SF*(<M, , cr*), k = 1, , n. 1 
(Cf. 6.2.2.) 

Second, all dependences (on en, , (7<_i) which arise when 3TI* turns 
out to be a chance move i.e. when k K = (cf. the end of 6.2.1.) cause no 
complications. They do not interfere with our analysis of the behavior of 
the players. This disposes, in particular, of all probabilities p(<r), since 
they occur only in connection with chance moves. (The A,, on the other 
hand, never occur in chance moves.) 

Third, we must consider the dependences (on <n, , <r_i) of the 
k K , A, when 2KI, turns out to be a personal move. 2 Now this possibility 
is indeed a source of complications. And it is a very real possibility. 3 The 
reason is this. 

1 The form and nature of the alternatives GL K (<r) offered at 3TI, might, of course, convey 
to the player k K (if WL K is a personal move) some information concerning the anterior 
<TX, , <r_i values, if the a(<r) depend on those. But any such information should 
be specified separately, as information available to A; at 2fTl*. We have disfcussed the 
simplest schemes concerning the subject of information in 6.3.1., and shall complete the 
discussion in 7.1.2. The discussion of , k K , A*, which follows further below, is charac- 
teristic also as far as the role of the a,t(<r) as possible sources of information is concerned. 

8 Whether this happens for a given K, will itself depend on k K and hence indirectly 
on <n, , <7-i since it is characterized by k K & (cf. the end of 6.2.1.). 

3 E.g.: In Chess the number of possible alternatives at 9R K depends on the positions 
of the men, i.e. the previous course of the play. In Bridge the player who plays the first 



56 DESCRIPTION OF GAMES OF STRATEGY 

7.1.2. The player k K must be informed at 311, of the values of a,, k K , 
A* since these are now part of the rules of the game which he must observe. 
Insofar as they depend upon ai, , <r_i, he may draw from them certain 
conclusions concerning the values of <TI, , <7_i. But he is supposed 
to know absolutely nothing concerning the <r\ with X not in A K ! It is hard 
to see how conflicts can be avoided. 

To be precise: There is no conflict in this special case: Let A, be inde- 
pendent of all (T\, - - - , <7\_], and let K , k K depend only on the <r\ with X in A*. 
Then the player k K can certainly not get any information from a K , k K , A 
beyond what he knows anyhow (i.e. the values of the <r\ with X in A*). If 
this is the case, we say that we have the special form of dependence. 

But do we always have the special form of dependence? To take an 
extreme case: What if A K is always empty i.e. k K expected to be completely 
uninformed at 3TC, and yet e.g. a* explicitly dependent on some of the 
<n, , <r._i! 

This is clearly inadmissible. We must demand that all numerical con- 
clusions which can be derived from the knowledge of a*, & A K , must be 
explicitly and ab initio specified as information available to the player k K 
at 3TC,. It would be erroneous, however, to try to achieve this by including 
in A* the indices X of all these o-x, on which a,, fc,, A, explicitly depend. In 
the first place great care must be exercised in order to avoid circularity in 
this requirement, as far as A is concerned. 1 But even if this difficulty does 
not arise, because A, depends only on K and not on cri, , o-^i i.e. if the 
information available to every player at every moment is independent of 
the previous course of the play the above procedure may still be inadmis- 
sible. Assume, e.g., that a K depends on a certain combination of some <r\ 
from among the X = l, -,* 1, and that the rules of the game do 
indeed provide that the player k K at y(l K should know the value of this com- 
bination, but that it does not allow him to know more (i.e. the values of the 
individual ai, , ov-i). E.g.: He may know the value of cr M + <r\ where 
M, X are both anterior to K (ju, X < K), but he is not allowed to know the 
separate values of <T M and a\. 

One could try various tricks to bring back the above situation to our 
earlier, simpler, scheme, which describes fc/s state of information by means 
of the set A,. 2 But it becomes completely impossible to disentangle the 
various components of fc/s information at 3TI,, if they themselves originate 
from personal moves of different players, or of the same player but in 

card to the next trick, i.e. k K at 911*, is the one who took the last trick, i.e. again dependent 
upon the previous course of the play. In some forms of Poker, and some other related 
games, the amount of information available to a player at a given moment, i.e. A* at 9H K , 
depends on what he and the others did previously. 

1 The <r\ on which, among others, A, depend are only defined if the totality of all A, 
for all sequences <n, - , <r<_i, is considered. Should every A* contain these X? 

2 In the above example one might try to replace the move 9TI M by a new one in which 
not o> is chosen, but <? -f *\. SHI* would remain unchanged. Then k* at 9R K would be 
informed about the outcome of the choice connected with the new 3TCu onlv. 



COMPLETE CONCEPT OF A GAME 57 

different stages of information. In our above example this happens if 
fc M 5^ fc\, or if fc^ = fc x but the state of information of this player is not the 
same at 311,, and at SfTCx. 1 

7.2. The General Description 

7.2.1. There are still various, more or less artificial, tricks by which one 
could try to circumvent these difficulties. But the most natural procedure 
seems to be to admit them, and to modify our definitions accordingly. 

This is done by sacrificing the A, as a means of describing the state of 
information. Instead, we describe the state of information of the player fc, 
at the time of his personal move 311, explicitly : By enumerating those func- 
tions of the variable <r\ anterior to this move i.e. of the <TI, , <r_i the 
numerical values of which he is supposed to know at this moment. This is 
a system of functions, to be denoted by <,. 

So $, is a set of functions 



Since the elements of < describe the dependence on <TI, , <r_i, so <, itself 
is fixed, i.e. depending on K only. 2 , k K may depend on <n, , <r_i, and 
since their values are known to k K at 91Z,, these functions 



must belong to $. Of course, whenever it turns out that k K = (for a 
special set of <ri, , cr_i values), then the move 3fTl is a chance one (cf. 
above), and no use will be made of <!>* but this does not matter. 

Our previous mode of description, with the A*, is obviously a special 
case of the present one, with the $*. 8 

7.2.2. At this point the reader may feel a certain dissatisfaction about 
the turn which the discussion has taken. It is true that the discussion was 
deflected into this direction by complications which arose in actual and 
typical games (cf. footnote 3 on p. 55). But the necessity of replacing 
the A K by the <$ originated in our desire to maintain absolute formal 
(mathematical) generality. These decisive difficulties, which caused us 
to take this step (discussed in 7.1.2., particularly as illustrated by the 
footnotes there) were really extrapolated. I.e. they were not characteristic 



1 In the instance of footnote 2 on p. 56, this means : If fr M ?* fc\, there is no player to whom 
the new move 3!Z M (where <r M 4- <rx is chosen, and which ought to be personal) can be 
attributed. If & M = k\ but the state of information varies from 3TI M to $TCx, then no state 
of information can be satisfactorily prescribed for the new move 9Tt M . 

1 This arrangement includes nevertheless the possibility that the state of information 
expressed by * depends on <n, , <r K _\. This is the case if, e.g., all functions 
h(vi, , <r_0 of <J> show an explicit dependence on o> for one set of values of <r\, while 
being independent of o> for other values of <r\. Yet * is fixed. 

1 If ** happens to consist of all functions of certain variables <r\ say of those for 
which X belongs to a given set M* and of no others, then the $* description specializes 
back to the A one: A, being the above set M. But we have seen that we cannot, in 
general, count upon the existence of such a set. 



58 DESCRIPTION OF GAMES OF STRATEGY 

of the original examples, which are actual games. (E.g. Chess and Bridge 
can be described with the help of the A*.) 

There exist games which require discussion by means of the $. But in 
most of them one could revert to the A, by means of various extraneous 
tricks and the entire subject requires a rather delicate analysis upon which 
it does not seem worth while to enter here. 1 There exist unquestionably 
economic models where the $ are necessary. 2 

The most important point, however, is this. 

In pursuit of the objectives which we have set ourselves we must achieve 
the certainty of having exhausted all combinatorial possibilities in connec- 
tion with the entire interplay of the various decisions of the players, their 
changing states of information, etc. These are problems, which have been 
dwelt upon extensively in economic literature. We hope to show that they 
can be disposed of completely. But for this reason we want to be safe 
against any possible accusation of having overlooked some essential possi- 
bility by undue specialization. 

Besides, it will be seen that all the formal elements which we are intro- 
ducing now into the discussion do not complicate it ultima analyst. I.e. 
they complicate only the present, preliminary stage of formal descrip- 
tion. The final form of the problem turns out to be unaffected by them. 
(Cf. 11.2.) 

7.2.3. There remains only one more point to discuss: The specializing 
assumption formulated at the very start of this discussion (at the beginning 
of 6.2.1.) that both the number and the arrangement of the moves are given 
(i.e. fixed) ab initio. We shall now see that this restriction is not essential. 

Consider first the "arrangement" of the moves. The possible varia- 
bility of the nature of each move i.e. of its fc has already received full 
consideration (especially in 7.2.1.). The ordering of the moves SHI,, k = 1, 
, v, was from the start simply the chronological one. Thus there is 
nothing left to discuss on this score. 

Consider next the number of moves v. This quantity too could be 
variable, i.e. dependent upon the course of the play. 3 In describing this 
variability of v a certain amount of care must be exercised. 

1 We mean card games where players may discard some cards without uncovering 
them, and are allowed to take up or otherwise use openly a part of their discards later. 
There exists also a game of double-blind Chess sometimes called " Kriegsspiel " which 
belongs in this class. (For its description cf. 9.2.3. With reference to that description: 
Each player knows about the " possibility" of the other's anterior choices, without 
knowing those choices themselves and this "possibility" is a function of all anterior 
choices.) 

1 Let a participant be ignorant of the full details of the previous actions of the others, 
but let him be informed concerning certain statistical resultants of those actions. 

3 It is, too, in most games: Chess, Backgammon, Poker, Bridge. In the case of Bridge 
this variability is due first to the variable length of the "bidding" phase, and second to 
the changing number of contracts needed to make a "rubber" (i.e. a play). Examples 
of games with a fixed v are harder to find: we shall see that we can make v fixed in every 
game by an artifice, but games in which v is ab initio fixed are apt to be monotonous. 



COMPLETE CONCEPT OF A GAME 59 

The course of the play is characterized by the sequence (of choices) 
*i, ' ' ' , <r (cf. 6.2.2.). Now one cannot state simply that v may be a 
function of the variables <TI, , <r,, because the full sequence <TI, , a, 
cannot be visualized at all, without knowing beforehand what its length v 
is going to be. 1 The correct formulation is this: Imagine that the variables 
0*1, 0*2, ffs, * are chosen one after the other. 2 If this succession of choices 
is carried on indefinitely, then the rules of the game must at some place v 
stop the procedure. Then v for which the stop occurs will, of course, depend 
on all the choices up to that moment. It is the number of moves in that 
particular play. 

Now this stop rule must be such as to give a certainty that every con- 
ceivable play will be stopped sometime. I.e. it must be impossible to 
arrange the successive choices of a\, <r 2 , <r 3 , in such a manner (subject 
to the restrictions of footnote 2 above) that the stop never comes. The 
obvious way to guarantee this is to devise a stop rule for which it is 
certain that the stop will come before a fixed moment, say *>*. I.e. that 
while v may depend on o-i, a*, a^ - , it is sure to be v ^ v* where v* 
does not depend on <TI, <r 2 , <r 3 , . If this is the case we say that the 
stop rule is bounded by v*. We shall assume for the games which we con- 
sider that they have stop rules bounded by (suitable, but fixed) numbers 

* 3,4 

1 I.e. one cannot say that the length of the game depends on all choices made in con- 
nection with all moves, since it will depend on the length of the game whether certain 
moves will occur at all. The argument is clearly circular. 

* The domain of variability of <r\ is 1, , on. The domain of variability of <TI is 
1, , at, and may depend on <n: a 2 = az(<ri). The domain of variability of <r is 
1, , ai, and may depend on <TI, <r z : i ai(<n, <rt). Etc., etc. 

8 This stop rule is indeed an essential part of every game. In most games it is easy 
to find v's fixed upper bound v*. Sometimes, however, the conventional form of the 
rules of the game does not exclude that the play might under exceptional conditions go 
on ad infinitum. In all these cases practical safeguards have been subsequently incor- 
porated into the rules of the game with the purpose of securing the existence of the 
bound v*. It must be said, however, that these safeguards are not always absolutely 
effective although the intention is clear in every instance, and even where exceptional 
infinite plays exist they are of little practical importance. It is nevertheless quite 
instructive, at least from a mathematical point of view, to discuss a few typical examples. 

We give four examples, arranged according to decreasing effectiveness. 

ficarte": A play is a "rubber," a "rubber" consists of winning two "games" out of 
three (cf. footnote 1 on p. 49), a "game" consists of winning five "points," and each 
"deal" gives one player or the other one or two points. Hence a "rubber" is complete 
after at most three "games," a "game" after at most nine "deals," and it is easy to 
verify that a "deal" consists of 13, 14 or 18 moves. Hence v* - 3 ^9 18 - 486. 

Poker: A priori two players could keep "overbidding" each other ad infinitum. It is 
therefore customaiy to add to the rules a proviso limiting the permissible number of 
"overbids." (The amounts of the bids are also limited, so as to make the number of 
alternatives a at these personal moves finite.) This of course secures a finite v*. 

Bridge: The play is a "rubber" and this could go on forever if both sides (players) 
invariably failed to make their contract. It is not inconceivable that the side which is in 
danger of losing the "rubber," should in this way permanently prevent a completion of 
the play by absurdly high bids. This is not done in practice, but there is nothing explicit 
in the rules of the game to prevent it. In theory, at any rate, some stop rule should be 
introduced in Bridge. 

Chess: It is easy to construct sequences of choices (in the usual terminology: 



60 DESCRIPTION OF GAMES OF STRATEGY 

Now we can make use of this bound v* to get entirely rid of the variabil- 
ity of v. 

This is done simply by extending the scheme of the game so that there 
are always v* moves 2fEi, , 9TI,*. For every sequence <TI, <r, 0-3, 
everything is unchanged up to the move 3TI,, and all moves beyond 2fTl, are 
"dummy moves." I.e. if we consider a move 3TC,, K = 1, , v*, for a 
sequence o-i, era, <TS, for which v < K, then we make 9TC a chance move 
with one alternative only 1 i.e. one at which nothing happens. 

Thus the assumptions made at the beginning of 6.2.1. particularly 
that v is given ab initio are justified ex post. 

8. Sets and Partitions 
8.1. Desirability of a Set-theoretical Description of a Game 

8.1. We have obtained a satisfactory and general description of the 
concept of a game, which could now be restated with axiomatic precision 
and rigidity to serve as a basis for the subsequent mathematical discussion. 
It is worth while, however, before doing that, to pass to a different formula- 
tion. This formulation is exactly equivalent to the one which we reached 
in the preceding sections, but it is more unified, simpler when stated in a 
general form, and it leads to more elegant and transparent notations. 

In order to arrive at this formulation we must use the symbolism of 
the theory of sets and more particularly of partitions more extensively 
than we have done so far. This necessitates a certain amount of explana- 
tion and illustration, which we now proceed to give. 

"moves") particularly in the "end game" which can go on ad infinitum without ever 
ending the play (i.e. producing a "checkmate"). The simplest ones are periodical, i.e. 
indefinite repetitions of the same cycle of choices, but there exist non-periodical ones as 
well. All of them offer a very real possibility for the player who is in danger of losing to 
secure sometimes a " tie." For this reason various "tie rules " i.e. stop rules are in use 
just to prevent that phenomenon. 

One well known "tie rule" is this: Any cycle of choices (i.e. "moves"), when three 
times repeated, terminates the play by a "tie." This rule excludes most but not all 
infinite sequences, and hence is really not effective. 

Another "tie rule" is this: If no pawn has been moved and no officer taken (these 
are "irreversible" operations, which cannot be undone subsequently) for 40 moves, then 
the play is terminated by a "tie." It is easy to see that this rule is effective, although the 
v* is enormous. 

4 From a purely mathematical point of view, the following question could be asked : 
Let the stop rule be effective in this sense only, that it is impossible so to arrange the 
successive choices <TI, at, at, that the stop never comes. I.e. let there always be a 
finite v dependent upon <n, <rj, <rj, . Does this by itself secure the existence of a 
fixed, finite v* bounding the stop rule? I.e. such that all v ^ v*? 

The question is highly academic since all practical game rules aim to establish a v* 
directly. (Cf., however, footnote 3 above.) It is nevertheless quite interesting 
mathematically. 

The answer is ".Yes," i.e. v* always exists. Cf. e.g. D. K&nig: tJber eine Schluss- 
weise aus dem Endlichen ins Unendliche, Acta Litt. ac Scient. Univ. Szeged, Sect. Math. 
Vol. III/II (1927) pp. 121-130; particularly the Appendix, pp. 12&-130. 
1 This means, of course, that = 1, k K = 0, and p*(l) *= 1. 



SETS AND PARTITIONS 61 

8.2. Sets, Their Properties, and Their Graphical Representation 

8.2.1. A set is an arbitrary collection of objects, absolutely no restriction 
being placed on the nature and number of these objects, the elements 
of the set in question. The elements constitute and determine the set as 
such, without any ordering or relationship of any kind between them. I.e. 
if two sets A, B are such that every element of A is also one of B and vice 
versa, then they are identical in every respect, A = B. The relationship 
of a being an element of the set A is also expressed by saying that a belongs 
to A. 1 

We shall be interested chiefly, although not always, in finite sets only, 
i.e. sets consisting of a finite number of elements. 

Given any objects a, 0, 7, we denote the set of which they are the 
elements by (a, 0, 7, ) It is also convenient to introduce a set which 
contains no elements at all, the empty set. 2 We denote the empty set by . 
We can, in particular, form sets with precisely one element, one-element sets. 
The one-element set (a), and its unique element a, are not the same thing 
and should never be confused. 3 

We re-emphasize that any objects can be elements of a set. Of course 
we shall restrict ourselves to mathematical objects. But the elements 
can, for instance, perfectly well be sets themselves (cf. footnote 3), thus 
leading to sets of sets, etc. These latter are sometimes called by some other 
equivalent name, e.g. systems or aggregates of sets. But this is not 
necessary. 

8.2.2. The main concepts and operations connected with sets are these: 

(8:A:a) A is a subset of B, or B a superset of A, if every element of 

A is also an element of B. In symbols: A B or B 2 A. A\s 
a proper subset of B, or B a proper superset of A, if the above is 
true, but if B contains elements which are not elements of A. 
In symbols: A c B or B => A. We see: If A is a subset of B and 
B is a subset of A , then A = B. (This is a restatement of the 
principle formulated at the beginning of 8.2.1.) Also: A is a 
proper subset of B if and only if A is a subset of B without 
A = B. 

1 The mathematical literature of the theory of sets is very extensive. We make no 
use of it beyond what will be said in the text. The interested reader will find more 
information on set theory in the good introduction: A. Fraenkel: Einleitung in die Men- 
genlehre, 3rd Edit. Berlin 1928; concise and technically excellent :F. Hausdorff: Mengen- 
lehre, 2nd Edit. Leipzig 1927. 

* If two sets A, B are both without elements, then we may say that they have the 
same elements. Hence, by what we said above, A ~ B. I.e. there exists only one 
empty set. 

This reasoning may sound odd, but it is nevertheless faultless. 

8 There are some parts of mathematics where (a) and a can be identified. This is 
then occasionally done, but it is an unsound practice. It is certainly not feasible in 
general. E.g., let a be something which is definitely not a one-element set, i.e. a 
two-element set (, 0), or the empty set Q. Then (a) and a must be distinguished, since 
(a) is a one-element set while a is not. 



62 DESCRIPTION OF GAMES OF STRATEGY 

(8:A:b) The sum of two sets A, B is the set of all elements of A 

together with all elements of B, to be denoted by A u B. Simi- 
larly the sums of more than two sets are formed. 1 

(8:A:c) The product, or intersection, of two sets A, B is the set of all 

common elements of A and of B, to be denoted by A n B. 
Similarly the products of more than two sets are formed. l 

(8:A:d) The difference of two sets A, B (A the minuend, B the subtra- 

hend) is the set of all those elements of A which do not belong to 
B, to be denoted by A - B. 1 

(8:A:e) When B is a subset of A, we shall also call A B the comple- 

ment of B in A. Occasionally it will be so obvious which set 
A is meant that we shall simply write B and talk about the 
complement of B without any further specifications. 

(8:A:f) Two sets A, B are disjunct if they have no elements in com- 

mon, i.e. if A n B = . 

(8:A:g) A system (set) & of sets is said to be a system of pairwise dis- 

junct sets if all pairs of different elements of Q, are disjunct sets, 
i.e. if for A, B belonging to a, A ^ B implies A n B = . 

8.2.3. At this point some graphical illustrations may be helpful. 
We denote the objects which are elements of sets in these considerations 
by dots (Figure 1). We denote sets by encircling the dots (elements) 




Figure 1. 

which belong to them, writing the symbol which denotes the set across 
the encircling line in one or more places (Figure 1). The sets A, C in this 
figure are, by the way, disjunct, while A, B are not. 

1 This nomenclature of sums, products, differences, is traditional. It is based on 
certain algebraic analogies which we shall not use here. In fact, the algebra of these 
operations U, n, also known as Boolean algebra, has a considerable interest of its own. 
Cf. e.g. A. Tarski: Introduction to Logic, New York, 1941. Cf. further Garrett Birkhoff: 
Lattice Theory, New York 1940. This book is of wider interest for the understanding of 
the modern abstract method. Chapt. VI. deals with Boolean Algebras. Further litera- 
ture is given there. 



SETS AND PARTITIONS 



63 



With this device we can also represent sums, products and differences of 
sets (Figure 2). In this figure neither A is a subset of B nor B one of A, 
hence neither the difference A B nor the difference JB A is a comple- 
ment. In the next figure, however, B is a subset of A, and so A B is the 
complement of B in A (Figure 3). 





Figure 2. 



Figure 3. 



8.3. Partitions, Their Properties, and Their Graphical Representation 

8.3.1. Let a set ft and a system of sets Ct be given. We say that a 
is a partition in ft if it fulfills the two following requirements: 

(8:B:a) Every element A of a is a subset of ft, and not empty. 

(8:B:b) ft is a system of pairwise disjunct sets. 

This concept too has been the subject of an extensive literature. 1 
We say for two partitions ft, (B that a is a subpartition of (B, if they fulfill 
this condition: 

(8:B:c) Every element A of a is a subset of some element B of (B. 2 

Observe that if a is a subpartition of (B and (B a subpartition of 
a, then a = (B. 3 
Next we define: 

(8 :B :d) Given two partitions a, (B, we form the system of all those 

intersections A n B A running over all elements of ft and B over 

1 Cf. G. Birkhoff loc. cit. Our requirements (8:B:a), (8:B:b) are not exactly the 
customary ones. Precisely: 

Ad (8:B:a): It is sometimes not required that the elements A of a be not empty. 
Indeed, we shall have to make one exception in 9.1.3. (cf. footnote 4 on p. 69). 

Ad (8:B:b): It is customary to require that the sum of all elements of d be exactly 
the set ft. It is more convenient for our purposes to omit this condition. 

2 Since Ct, (B are also sets, it is appropriate to compare the subset relation (as far as 
Ct, (B are concerned) with the subpartition relation. One verifies immediately that if Ct 
is a subset of (B then Q, is also a subpartition of (B, but that the converse statement is not 
(generally) true. 

3 Proof: Consider an element A of a. It must be subset of an element B of (B, and 
B in turn subset of an element Ai of Ct. So A, A\ have common elements all those of 
the not empty set A i.e. are not disjunct. Since they both belong to the partition d, 
this necessitates A *= AI. So A is a subset of B and B one of A ( = AI). Hence A = J3, 
and thus A belongs to (B; 

I.e.: a is a subset of (B. (Cf. footnote 2 above.) Similarly (B is a subset of a. 
Hence a = (B. 



64 



DESCRIPTION OF GAMES OF STRATEGY 



all those of (B which are not empty. This again is clearly a 
partition, the superposition of Ot, (B. 1 

Finally, we also define the above relations for two partitions Ct, (B within 
a given set C. 

(8:B:e) a is a subpartition of (B within C, if every A belonging to ft 

which is a subset of C is also subset of some B belonging to (B 
which is a subset of C. 

(8:B:f) Ot is equal to (B within C if the same subsets of C are elements 

of a and of (B. 

Clearly footnote 3 on p. 63 applies again, mutatis mutandis. Also, 
the above concepts within ft are the same as the original unqualified ones. 




Figure 4. 



.S3v 




Figure 5. 

8.3.2. We give again some graphical illustrations, in the sense of 8.2.3. 

We begin by picturing a partition. We shall not give the elements 
of the partition which are sets names, but denote each one by an encir- 
cling line (Figure 4). 

We picture next two partitions a, (B distinguishing them by marking the 
encircling lines of the elements of a by and of the elements of (B by 

1 It is easy to show that the superposition of a, (B is a subpartition of both a and (B 
and that every partition C which is a subpartition of both a and (B is also one of their 
superposition. Hence the name. Cf . O. Birkhoff, loc. cit. Chapt. I-II. 



SETS AND PARTITIONS 



65 



- (Figure 5). In this figure a is a subpartition of (B. In the following 
one neither a is a subpartition (B nor is & one of a (Figure 6). We leave it 
to the reader to determine the superposition of Ot, (B in this figure. 




Figure 6. 





Figure 7. 



Figure 8. 




Figure 9. 

Another, more schematic, representation of partitions obtains by repre- 
senting the set 8 by one dot, and every element of the partition which is a 



66 DESCRIPTION OF GAMES OF STRATEGY 

subset of 12 by a line going upward from this dot. Thus the partition a of 
Figure 5 will be represented by a much simpler drawing (Figure 7). This 
representation does not indicate the elements within the elements of the 
partition, and it cannot be used to represent several partitions in 12 simul- 
taneously, as was done in Figure 6. However, this deficiency can be 
removed if the two partitions ft, (B in 12 are related as in Figure 5 : If Q is a 
subpartition of (B. In this case we can represent 12 again by a dot at the 
bottom, every element of (B by a line going upward from this dot as in 
Figure 7 and every element of ft as another line going further upward, 
beginning at the upper end of that line of (B, which represents the element of 
(B of which this element of ft is a subset. Thus we can represent the two 
partitions ft, (B of Figure 5 (Figure 8). This representation is again less 
revealing than the corresponding one of Figure 5. But its simplicity makes 
it possible to extend it further than pictures in the vein of Figures 4-6 could 
practically go. Specifically: We can picture by this device a sequence of 
partitions fti, , ft M , where each one is a subpartition of its immediate 
predecessor. We give a typical example with ju = 5 (Figure 9). 

Configurations of this type have been studied in mathematics, and are 
known as trees. 

8.4. Logistic Interpretation of Sets and Partitions 

8.4.1. The notions which we have described in 8.2.1.-8.3.2. will be useful 
in the discussion of games which follows, because of the logistic interpreta- 
tion which can be put upon them. 

Let us begin with the interpretation concerning sets. 

If 12 is a set of objects of any kind, then every conceivable property 
which some of these objects may possess, and others not can be fully 
characterized by specifying the set of those elements of 12 which have this 
property. I.e. if two properties correspond in this sense to the same set 
(the same subset of 12), then the same elements of 12 will possess these two 
properties, i.e. they are equivalent within 12, in the sense in which this term 
is understood in logic. 

Now the properties (of elements of 12) are not only in this simple cor- 
respondence with sets (subsets of 12), but the elementary logical operations 
involving properties correspond to the set operations which we discussed in 
8.2.2. 

Thus the disjunction of two properties i.e. the assertion that at least 
one of them holds corresponds obviously to forming the sum of their sets, 
the operation A u B. The conjunction of two properties i.e. the assertion 
that both hold corresponds to forming the product of their sets, the oper- 
ation A n B. And finally, the negation of a property i.e. the assertion 
of the opposite corresponds to forming the complement of its set, the 
operation A. 1 

1 Concerning the connection of set theory and of formal logic cf., e.g., O. Birkhoff, 
loc. cit. Chapt. VIII. 



SET-THEORETICAL DESCRIPTION 67 

Instead of correlating the subsets of ft to properties in ft as done above 
we may equally well correlate them with all possible bodies of information 
concerning an otherwise undetermined element of ft. Indeed, any such 
information amounts to the assertion that this unknown element of ft 
possesses a certain specified property. It is equivalently represented 
by the set of all those elements of ft which possess this property; i.e. to 
which the given information has narrowed the range of possibilities for 
the unknown element of ft. 

Observe, in particular, that the empty set corresponds to a property 
which never occurs, i.e. to an absurd information. And two disjunct sets 
correspond to two incompatible properties, i.e. to two mutually exclusive 
bodies of information. 

8.4.2. We now turn our attention to partitions. 

By reconsidering the definition (8:B:a), (8:B:b) in 8.3.1., and by restat- 
ing it in our present terminology, we see: A partition is a system of pairwise 
mutually exclusive bodies of information concerning an unknown element 
of ft none of which is absurd in itself. In other words: A partition is a 
preliminary announcement which states how much information will be 
given later concerning an otherwise unknown element of ft; i.e. to what 
extent the range of possibilities for this element will be narrowed later. But 
the actual information is not given by the partition, that would amount to 
selecting an element of the partition, since such an element is a subset of ft, 
i.e. actual information. 

We can therefore say that a partition in ft is a pattern of information. 
As to the subsets of ft: we saw in 8.4.1. that they correspond to definite 
informati6n. In order to avoid confusion with the terminology used for 
partitions, we shall use in this case i.e. for a subset of ft the words actual 
information. 

Consider now the definition (8:B:c) in 8.3.1., and relate it to our present 
terminology. This expresses for two partitions d, (B in ft the meaning of ft 
being a subpartition of (B: it amounts to the assertion that the information 
announced by d includes all the information announced by (B (and possibly 
more) ; i.e. that the pattern of information a includes the pattern of informa- 
tion (B. 

These remarks put the significance of the Figures 4-9 in 8.3.2. in a new 
light. It appears, in particular, that the tree of Figure 9 pictures a sequence 
of continually increasing patterns of information. 

9. The Set-theoretical Description of a Game 
9.1. The Partitions Which Describe a Game 

9.1.1. We assume the number of moves as we now know that we may 
to be fixed. Denote this number again by v, and the moves themselves 
again by 3TCi, , SKI,. 

Consider all possible plays of the game F, and form the set ft of which 
they are the elements. If we use the description of the preceding sections, 



68 DESCRIPTION OF GAMES OE STRATEGY 

then all possible plays are simply all possible sequences <n, , *. l There 
exist only a finite number of such sequences, 2 and so ft is a finite set. 

There are, however, also more direct ways to form ft. We can, e.g., 
form it by describing each play as the sequence of the v + 1 consecutive 
positions 8 which arise during its course. In general, of course, a given 
position may not be followed by an arbitrary position, but the positions 
which are possible at a given moment are restricted by the previous posi- 
tions, in a way which must be precisely described by the rules of the game. 4 
Since our description of the rules of the game begins by forming ft, it may be 
undesirable to let ft itself depend so heavily on all the details of those rules. 
We observe, therefore, that there is no objection to including in ft absurd 
sequences of positions as well. 6 Thus it would be perfectly acceptable even 
to let ft consist of all sequences of v -f 1 successive positions, without any 
restrictions whatsoever. 

Our subsequent descriptions will show how the really possible plays 
are to be selected from this, possibly redundant, set ft. 

9.1.2. v and ft being given, we enter upon the more elaborate details of 
the course of a play. 

Consider a definite moment during this course, say that one which 
immediately precedes a given move 3TI,. At this moment the following 
general specifications must be furnished by the rules of the game. 

First it is necessary to describe to what extent the events which have 
led up to the move 9TC. 6 have determined the course of the play. Every 
particular sequence of these events narrows the set ft down to a subset A K : 
this being the set of all those plays from ft, the course of which is, up to 3^,, 
the particular sequence of events referred to. In the terminology of the 
earlier sections, ft is as pointed out in 9.1.1. the set of all sequences 
<TI, , a,} then A t would be the set of those sequences <n, - , a, for 
which the <TI, , <r,_i have given numerical values (cf. footnote 6 above). 
But from our present broader point of view we need only say that A K must 
be a subset of ft. 

Now the various possible courses the game may have taken up to 3TC, 
must be represented by different sets A K . Any two such courses, if they are 
different from each other, initiate two entirely disjunct sets of plays; i.e. 
no play can have begun (i.e. run up to 9TC,) both ways at once. This means 
that any two different sets A x must be disjunct. 

1 Cf . in particular^ 6.2.2. The range of the <TI, , <r v is described in footnote 2 
on p. 59. 

1 Verification by means of the footnote referred to above is immediate. 

1 Before 3Jli, between 9lli and 9Rj, between 9R 2 and 9flli, etc., etc., between 9TC,>_i and 
3H,, after 3Hp. 

4 This is similar to the development of the sequence <n, , <r,, as described in 
footnote 2 on p. 59. 

* I.e. ones which will ultimately be found to be disallowed by the fully formulated 
rules of the game. 

I.e. the choices connected with the anterior moves 9Tli, - , 9TC*-.i i.e. the numeri- 
cal values <ri, 



SET-THEORETICAL DESCRIPTION 69 

Thus the complete formal possibilities of the course of all conceivable 
plays of our game up to 9TC, are described by a family of pairwise disjunct 
subsets of ft. This is the family of all the sets A K mentioned above. We 
denote this family by a. 

The sum of all sets A K contained in a, must contain all possible plays. 
But since we explicitly permitted a redundancy of 12 (cf. the end of 9.1.1.), 
this sum need nevertheless not be equal to ft. Summing up: 

(9: A) ft is a partition in ft. 

We could also say that the partition &< describes the pattern of informa- 
tion of a person who knows everything that happened up to 3NI,; 1 e.g. of an 
umpire who supervises the course of the play. 2 

9.1.3. Second, it must be known what the nature of the move 3fll is 
going to be. This is expressed by the k< of 6.2.1.: k K = 1, , n if the 
move is personal and belongs to the player fc,; fc, = if the move is chance. 
kt may depend upon the course of the play up to 3TI,, i.e. upon the informa- 
tion embodied in a,. 3 This means that fc must be a constant within each 
set A K of Gfc,, but that it may vary from one A K to another. 

Accordingly we may form for every fc = 0, 1, , n a set B*(k), which 
contains all sets A K with k K = k, the various B K (k) being disjunct. Thus the 
B K (k), k = 0, 1, , n, form a family of disjunct subsets of ft. We denote 
this family by (B,. 

(9:B) (B, is again a partition in ft. Since every A K of ft, is a subset 

of some B K (k) of (B, therefore & is a subpartition of (B*. 

But while there was no occasion to specify any particular enumeration 
of the sets A K of Q K , it is not so with (B,. (B* consists of exactly n + 1 sets 
B K (k), k = 0, 1, , n, which in this way appear in a fixed enumeration 
by means of the k = 0, 1, , n. 4 And this enumeration is essential 
since it replaces the function k K (cf. footnote 3 above). 

9.1.4. Third, the conditions under which the choice connected with the 
move 311, is to take place must be described in detail. 

Assume first that 311, is a chance move, i.e. that we are within the set 
jB(0). Then the significant quantities are: the number of alternatives a 
and the probabilities p*(l), , p*(ctt) of these various alternatives (cf. 
the end of 6.2.1.). As was pointed out in 7.1.1. (this was the second item 

1 I.e. the outcome of all choices connected with the moves 9Ri, , 9TC-i. In our 
earlier terminology: the values of <n, , <T*_I. 

1 It is necessary to introduce such a person since, in general, no player will be in 
possession of the full information embodied in a. 

8 In the notations of 7.2.1., and in the sense of the preceding footnotes: k* - 
fc(<ri, , <r,(_i). 

4 Thus (B is really not a set and not a partition, but a more elaborate concept: it con- 
sists of the sets (B,c(fc), A; = 0, 1, , n, in this enumeration. 

It possesses, however, the properties (8:B:a), (8:B:b) of 8.3.1., which characterize a 
partition. Yet even there an exception must be made: among the sets (B(fc) there can 
be empty ones. 



70 DESCRIPTION OF GAMES OF STRATEGY 

of the discussion there), all these quantities may depend upon the entire 
information embodied in GL K (cf. footnote 3 on p. 69), since 3TI* is now a 
chance move. I.e. a K and the p(l), , />(<*) must be constant within 
each set A K of Q K l but they may vary from one A K to another. 

Within each one of these A K the choice among the alternatives &(!), 
, &(*) takes place, i.e. the choice of a a K = 1, , a K (cf. 6.2.2.). 
This can be described by specifying a K disjunct subsets of A K which cor- 
respond to the restriction expressed by A K , plus the choice of a K which has 
taken place. We call these sets C K , and their system consisting of all C K 
in all the A K which are subsets of B K (0) e(0). Thus 6^(0) is a partition in 
B K (0). And since every C K of G(0) is a subset of some A K of a,, therefore 
C(0) is a subpartition of Q, K . 

The a K are determined by (()) ; 2 hence we need not mention them any 
more. For the p(l), , p(cO this description suggests itself: with 
every C K of C^O) a number p K (C^) (its probability) must be associated, 
subject to the equivalents of footnote 2 on p. 50. 8 

9.1.5. Assume, secondly, that 9ffl is a personal move, say of the player 
k = 1, , n, i.e. that we are within the set B K (k). In this case we 
must specify the state of information of the player k at 311*. In 6.3.1. this 
was described by means of the set A, in 7.2.1. by means of the family of 
functions <, the latter description being the more general and the final one. 
According to this description k knows at 3fTC the values of all functions 
h(<n, , 0"ic-i) of $ and no more. This amount of information operates 
a subdivision of B K (k) into several disjunct subsets, corresponding to the 
various possible contents of fc's information at ?RI K . We call these sets 
D, and their system > K (k). Thus ><(&) is a partition in B K (k). 

Of course fc's information at STC* is part of the total information existing 
at that moment in the sense of 9.1.2. which is embodied in ft, Hence 
in an A K of &, which is a subset of B K (k), no ambiguity can exist, i.e. this 
A K cannot possess common elements with mt>re than one D K of ><(&). This 
means that the A K in question must be a subset of a D K of ><(&). In other 
words: within B K (k) Q K is a subpartition of >(&) 

In reality the course of the play is narrowed down at am, within a set 
A K of GL X . But the player k whose mo've 9TI K is, does not know as much: 
as far as he is concerned, the play is merely within a set D K of >(fc). He 
must now make the choice among the alternatives &*(!), , d(cx)> i.e. 
the choice of a <r = 1, , a,. As was pointed out in 7.1.2. and 7.2.1. 
(particularly at the end of 7.2.1.), a K may well be variable, but it can only 
depend upon the information embodied in ><(&). I.e. it must be a constant 
within the set D K of 3D(fc) to which we have restricted ourselves. Thus 
the choice of a <T K = 1, , a, can be described by specifying a disjunct 
subsets of D,, which correspond to the restriction expressed by D K , plus the 

1 We are within B K (Q), hence all this refers only to AJs which are subsets of #(()). 
1 is the number of those C of e(0) which are subsets of the given A K . 
* I.e. every p(C*) ;> 0, and for each A K , and the sum extended over all C of e,t(0) 
which are subsets of A t we have Sp.tC*) = 1. 



SET-THEORETICAL DESCRIPTION 71 

choice of <r, which has taken place. We call these sets C, and their system 
consisting of all C K in all the D K of )*(fc) <3(fc). Thus G K (k) is a partition 
in B K (k). And since every C K of Q K (k) is a subset of some D K of >*(fc), there- 
fore e(fc) is a subpartition of >(&). 

The a* are determined by e(fc); 1 hence we need not mention them 
any more, a* must not be zero, i.e., given a D< of $> K (k), some C of C(fc), 
which is a subset of D,, must exist. 2 

9.2. Discussion of These Partitions and Their Properties 

9.2.1. We have completely described in the preceding sections the 
situation at the moment which precedes the move 3TC,. We proceed now to 
discuss what happens as we go along these moves K = 1, -,*>. It 
is convenient to add to these a K = v + 1, too, which corresponds to the 
conclusion of the play, i.e. follows after the last move 311,. 

For K = 1, , v we have, as we discussed in the preceding sections, 
the partitions 

a., (B, = (B,(0), B.(l), , B.(n)), C.(0), C.(l), , C.(n), 

>,(!), , 3>.(n). 

All of these, with the sole exception of &, refer to the move 3TC,, hence 
they need not and cannot be defined for K = v + 1. But &+! has a per- 
fectly good meaning, as its discussion in 9.1.2. shows: It represents the 
full information which can conceivably exist concerning a play, i.e. the 
individual identity of the play. 3 

At this point two remarks suggest themselves : In the sense of the above 
observations Oti corresponds to a moment at which no information is 
available at all. Hence Cti should consist of the one set 0. On the other 
hand, Ot,+i corresponds to the possibility of actually identifying the play 
which has taken place. Hence <$+! is a system of one-element sets. 

We now proceed to describe the transition from K to K + 1, when 
K = 1, , v. 

9.2.2. Nothing can be said about the change in the (B, e(fc), 5)(fc) 
when K is replaced by K + 1, our previous discussions have shown that 
when this replacement is made anything may happen to those objects, i.e. 
to what they represent. 

It is possible, however, to tell how Q K +i obtains from 6t. 

The information embodied in &,+) obtains from that one embodied 
in a by adding to it the outcome of the choice connected with the move 
SHI*. 4 This ought to be clear from the discussions of 9.1.2. Thus the 

1 is the number of those C K of e(fc) which are subsets of the given A*. 

1 We required this for k = 1, , n only, although it must be equally true for 
Jc = with an A K , subset of #(0), in place of our D K of 3)*(fc). But it is unnecessary to 
state it for that case, because it is a consequence of footnote 3 on p. 70; indeed, if no 
0* of the desired kind existed, the Sp(C) of loc. cit, would be and not 1. 

8 In the sense of footnote 1 on p. 69, the values of all <n, , <r,. And the sequence 
<TI, , <r, characterizes, as stated in 6.2.2., the play itself. 

4 In our earlier terminology: the value of <r. 



72 DESCRIPTION OF GAMES OF STRATEGY 

information in Ot,+i which goes beyond that in ft, is precisely the information 
embodied in the e(0), &(!), , C,(n). 

This means that the partitions a+i obtains by superposing the partition 
a. with all partitions 6(0), 6(1), , <S>*(k). I.e. by forming the inter- 
section of every A , in a, with every C< in any C^O), C(l), , C(n), and 
then throwing away the empty sets. 

Owing to the relationship of ft, and of the e(fc) to the sets B K (k) as 
discussed in the preceding sections we can say a little more about this 
process of superposition. 

In B(0), C(0) is a subpartition of Ofc (cf. the discussion in 9.1.4.). Hence 
there Q K +i simply coincides with G(0). In (&), k = 1, , n, G(fc) 
and ft, are both subpartitions of )(&) (cf. the discussion in 9.1.5.). Hence 
there &<+i obtains by first taking every D K of 3)(fc), then for every such D, 
all A K of & x and all C of C,(fc) which are subsets of this D K , and forming all 
intersections A K n C K . 

Every such set A K n C represents those plays which arise when the 
player fc, with the information of D before him, but in a situation which is 
really in A K (a subset of D), makes the choice C K at the move 9TC, so as to 
restrict things to C. 

Since this choice, according to what was said before, is a possible one, 
there exist such plays. I.e. the set A K n C K must not be empty. We 
restate this: 

(9:C) If A K of Ot and C of C(fc) are subsets of the same D K of >(&), 

then the intersection A K n C must not be empty. 

9.2.3. There are games in which one might be tempted to set this require- 
ment aside. These are games in which a player may make a legitimate 
choice which turns out subsequently to be a forbidden one; e.g. the double- 
blind Chess referred to in footnote 1 on p. 58: here a player can make an 
apparently possible choice ("move") on his own board, and will (possibly) 
be told only afterwards by the "umpire" that it is an "impossible" one. 

This example is, however, spurious. The move in question is best 
resolved into a sequence of several alternative ones. It seems best to give 
the contemplated rules of double-blind Chess in full. 

The game consists of a sequence of moves. At each move the "umpire " 
announces to both players whether the preceding move was a "possible" 
one. If it was not, the next move is a personal move of the same player 
as the preceding one; if it was, then the next move is the other player's 
personal move. At each move the player is informed about all of his own 
anterior choices, about the entire sequence of "possibility" or "impossibil- 
ity" of all anterior choices of both players, and about all anterior instances 
where either player threatened check or took anything. But he knows 
the identity of his own losses only. In determining the course of the game, 
the "umpire" disregards the "impossible" moves. Otherwise the game is 
played like Chess, with a stop rule in the sense of footnote 3 on p. 59, 



AXIOMATIC FORMULATION 73 

amplified by the further requirement that no player may make ("try") 
the same choice twice in any one uninterrupted sequence of his own personal 
moves. (In practice, of course, the players need two chessboards out of 
each other's view but both in the " umpire's " view to obtain these condi- 
tions of information.) 

At any rate we shall adhere to the requirement stated above. It will 
be seen that it is very convenient for our subsequent discussion (cf. 11.2.1.). 

9.2.4. Only one thing remains: to reintroduce in our new terminology, 
the quantities SF*, k = 1, , n, of 6.2.2. SF* is the outcome of the play 
for the player k. $ k must be a function of the actual play which has taken 
place. 1 If we use the symbol ir to indicate that play, then we may say: 
$k is a function of a variable IT with the domain of variability 12. I.e. : 

$k = ^W, v in 12, k = 1, , n. 

10. Axiomatic Formulation 
10.1. The Axioms and Their Interpretations 

10.1.1. Our description of the general concept of a game, with the new 
technique involving the use of sets and of partitions, is now complete. 
All constructions and definitions have been sufficiently explained in the 
past sections, and we can therefore proceed to a rigorous axiomatic definition 
of a game. This is, of course, only a concise restatement of the things 
which we discussed more broadly in the preceding sections. 

We give first the precise definition, without any commentary: 2 
An n-person game F, i.e. the complete system of its rules, is determined 
by the specification of the following data: 

(10:A:a) A number v. 

(10:A:b) A finite set 12. 

(10:A:c) For every k = 1, , n: A function 

3k = $*(*), TT in 12. 

(10:A:d) For every K = 1, , v, v + 1: A partition & K in 12. 

(10:A:e) For every K = 1, , v: A partition (B, in 12. (B con- 

sists of n + 1 sets B K (k), k = 0, 1, , n, enumerated in 

this way. 
(10:A:f) For every K = 1, , v and every k = 0, 1, , n: 

A partition e(fc) in B K (k). 
(10:A:g) For every K = 1, , v and every k = 1, , n: A 

partition >(/;) in J3,(fc). 
(10:A:h) For every * = 1, , v and every C* of C(0): A number 



These entities must satisfy the following requirements: 

(10:1 :a) ft, is a subpartition of (B,. 

(10:1 :b) e(0) is a subpartition of a. 

1 In the old terminology, accordingly, we had ff* - g*(ai, , o>). Cf. 6.2.2. 

2 For "explanations" cf. the end of 10.1.1. and the discussion of 10.1.2. 



74 DESCRIPTION OF GAMES OF STRATEGY 

(10:1 :c) For k = 1, , n: C,(fc) is a subpartition of ><(fc). 

(10:1 :d) For k = 1, , n: Within B<(fc), 6t is a subpartition of 

ft(*). 

(10:1 :e) For every K = 1, , ? and every .A* of Ot which is a 

subset of 5(0): For all C K of C(0) which are subsets of this 
<4, P*(C*) ^ 0, and for the sum extended over them Sp^C,) = 1. 

(10:1 :f) Cti consists of the one set Q. 

(10:1 :g) Ot.,+1 consists of one-element sets. 

(10:l:h) For K = 1, , v. Q K +i obtains from Q K by superposing it 

with all e,(*), k = 0, 1, , n. (For details, cf. 9.2.2.) 

(10:1 :i) For K = 1, , v: If A K of a, and C K of e*(fc), fc = 1, 

, n are subsets of the same D K of >*(fc), then the inter- 
section A K n C, must not be empty. 

(10:1 :j) For K = 1, , v and fc = 1, , n and every D K of 

>,(&) : Some C,(fc) of e,, which is a subset of D K , must exist. 

This definition should be viewed primarily in the spirit of the modern 
axiomatic method. We have even avoided giving names to the mathe- 
matical concepts introduced in (10:A:a)-(10:A:h) above, in order to estab- 
lish no correlation with any meaning which the verbal associations of names 
may suggest. In this absolute "purity" these concepts can then be the 
objects of an exact mathematical investigation. 1 

This procedure is best suited to develop sharply defined concepts. 
The application to intuitively given subjects follows afterwards, when 
the exact analysis has been completed. Cf. also what was said in 4.1.3. 
in Chapter I about the role of models in physics: The axiomatic models 
for intuitive systems are analogous to the mathematical models for (equally 
intuitive) physical systems. 

Once this is understood, however, there can be no harm in recalling 
that this axiomatic definition was distilled out of the detailed empirical 
discussions of the sections, which precede it. And it will facilitate its use, 
and make its structure more easily understood, if we give the intervening 
concepts appropriate names, which indicate, as much as possible, the 
intuitive background. And it is further useful to express, in the same 
spirit, the "meaning" of our postulates (10:l:a)-(10:l:j) i.e. the intuitive 
considerations from which they sprang. 

All this will be, of course, merely a concise summary of the intuitive con- 
siderations of the preceding sections, which lead up to this axiomatization. 

10.1.2. We state first the technical names for the concepts of (10:A:a)- 
(10:A:h) in 10.1.1. 

1 This is analogous to the present attitude in axiomatizing such subjects as logic, 
geometry, etc. Thus, when axiomatizing geometry, it is customary to state that the 
notions of points, lines, and planes are not to be a priori identified with anything intui- 
tive, they are only notations for things about which only the properties expressed in 
the axioms are assumed. Cf., e.g., D. Hilbert: Die Grundlagen der Geometrie, Leipzig 
1899, 2rd Engl. Edition Chicago 1910. 



AXIOMATIC FORMULATION 75 

(10:A:a*) v is the length of the game F. 

(10:A:b*) ft is the set of all plays of T. 

(10:A:c*) ^(TT) is the outcome of the play w for the player fc. 

(10:A:d*) Ct is the umpire's pattern of information, an A of ft, is the 

umpire's actual information at (i.e. immediately preceding) the 

move 3TC. (For K = v + 1 : At the end of the game.) 
(10:A:e*) (B* is the pattern of assignment, a B*(k) of (B, is the actual 

assignment, of the move 9TC,. 
(10:A:f*) <3*(fc) is the pattern of choice, a C, of 6<(fc) is the actual 

choice, of the player & at the move 3TZ*. (For A; = 0: Of 

chance.) 
(10:A:g*) 3)(A;) is the player k's pattern of information, a D K of >*(&) 

the player k's actual information, at the move 3TC. 
(10:A:h*) p*(C*) is the probability of the actual choice C at the 

(chance) move 3TI,. 

We now formulate the "meaning" of the requirements (10:1 :a)- 
(10:1 :j) in the sense of the concluding discussion of 10.1.1 with the use of 
the above nomenclature. 
(10:l:a*) The umpire's pattern of information at the move 3TC 

includes the assignment of that move. 
(10:l:b*) The pattern of choice at a chance move 9fTl includes the 

umpire's pattern of information at that move. 
(10 :1 :c*) The pattern of choice at a personal move 3TC, of the player k 

includes the player k's pattern of information at that move. 
(10:l:d*) The umpire's pattern of information at the move 9Tl 

includes to the extent to which this is a personal move of the 

player k the player k's pattern of information at that move. 
(10:l:e*) The probabilities of the various alternative choices at a 

chance move 9TC< behave like probabilities belonging to disjunct 

but exhaustive alternatives. 
(10:l:f*) The umpire's pattern of information at the first move is 

void. 
(10:1 :g*) The umpire's pattern of information at the end of the game 

determines the play fully. 
(10:l:h*) The umpire's pattern of information at the move ST^+i 

(for K = v: at the end of the game) obtains from that one at 

the move SfTl, by superposing it with the pattern of choice at 

the move 311,. 
(10:l:i*) Let a move 2(11, be given, which is a personal move of the 

player k, and any actual information of the player k at that 

move also be given. Then any actual information of the 

umpire at that move and any actual choice of the player k at 

that move, which are both within (i.e. refinements of) this 

actual (player's) information, are also compatible with each 

Othe r T ** +.VIPV nnniir in flftiifll nlnvs 



76 DESCRIPTION OF GAMES OF STRATEGY 

(10:1 :j*) Let a move SHI, be given, which is a personal move of the 

player A;, and any actual information of the player k at that 
move also be given. Then the number of alternative actual 
choices, available to the player k, is not zero. 

This concludes our formalization of the general scheme of a game. 

10.2. Logistic Discussion of the Axioms 

10.2. We have not yet discussed those questions which are convention- 
ally associated in formal logics with every axiomatization: freedom from 
contradiction, categoricity (completeness), and independence of the axioms. 1 
Our system possesses the first and the last-mentioned properties, but not the 
second one. These facts are easy to verify, and it is not difficult to see 
that the situation is exactly what it should be. In summa: 

Freedom from contradiction: There can be no doubt as to the existence 
of games, and we did nothing but give an exact formalism for them. We 
shall discuss the formalization of several games later in detail, cf. e.g. the 
examples of 18., 19. From the strictly mathematical logistic point of 
view, even the simplest game can be used to establish the fact of freedom 
from contradiction. But our real interest lies, of course, with the more 
involved games, which are the really interesting ones. 2 

Categoricity (completeness): This is not the case, since there exist 
many different games which fulfill these axioms. Concerning effective 
examples, cf. the preceding reference. 

The reader will observe that categoricity is not intended in this case, 
since our axioms have to define a class of entities (games) and not a unique 
entity. 8 

Independence: This is easy to establish, but we do not enter upon it. 

10.3. General Remarks Concerning the Axioms 

10.3. There are two more remarks which ought to be made in connection 
with this axiomatization. 

First, our procedure follows the classical lines of obtaining an exact 
formulation for intuitively empirically given ideas. The notion of a 
game exists in general experience in a practically satisfactory form, which is 
nevertheless too loose to be fit for exact treatment. The reader who has 
followed our analysis will have observed how this imprecision was gradually 

1 Cf. D. Hilbert, loc. cit.; 0. Veblen & J. W. Young: Projective Geometry, New York 
1910; H. Weyl: Philosophic der Mathematik und Naturwissenschaften, in Handbuch der 
Philosophic, Munich, 1927. 

1 This is the simplest game: v 0, 12 has only one element, sayiro. Consequently 
no (B, C(fc), 5>(fc), exist, while the only O is di, consisting of 12 alone. Define $(iro) 
for k = I, - , n. An obvious description of this game consists in the statement that 
nobody does anything and that nothing happens. This also indicates that the freedom 
from contradiction is not in this case an interesting question, 

8 This is an important distinction in the general logistic approach to axiomatization. 
Thus the axioms of Euclidean geometry describe a unique object while those of group 
theory (in mathematics) or of rational mechanics (in physics) do not, since there exist 
many different groups and many different mechanical systems. 



AXIOMATIC FORMULATION 77 

removed, the "zone of twilight " successively reduced, and a precise formula- 
tion obtained eventually. 

Second, it is hoped that this may serve as an example of the truth of a 
much disputed proposition: That it is possible to describe and discuss 
mathematically human actions in which the main emphasis lies on the 
psychological side. In the present case the psychological element was 
brought in by the necessity of analyzing decisions, the information on the 
basis of which they are taken, and the interrelatedness of such sets of 
information (at the various moves) with each other. This interrelatedness 
originates in the connection of the various sets of information in time, 
causation, and by the speculative hypotheses of the players concerning 
each other. 

There are of course many and most important aspects of psychology 
which we have never touched upon, but the fact remains that a primarily 
psychological group of phenomena has been axiomatized. 

10.4. Graphical Representation 

10.4.1. The graphical representation of the numerous partitions which 
we had to use to represent a game is not easy. We shall not attempt to 
treat this matter systematically: even relatively simple games seem to 
lead to complicated and confusing diagrams, and so the usual advantages of 
graphical representation do not obtain. 

There are, however, some restricted possibilities of graphical representa- 
tion, and we shall say a few words about these. 

In the first place it is clear from (10:1 :h) in 10.1.1., (or equally by 
(10:1 :h*) in 10.1.2., i.e. by remembering the "meaning, ") that a,+i is a 
subpartition of ft,. I.e. in the sequence of partitions Cti, , ft,, ft,+i 
each one is a subpartition of its immediate predecessor. Consequently this 
much can be pictured with the devices of Figure 9 in 8.3.2., i.e. by a tree. 
(Figure 9 is not characteristic in one way: since the length of the game F is 
assumed to be fixed, all branches of the tree must continue to its full height. 
Cf. Figure 10 in 10.4.2. below.) We shall not attempt to add the ,(&), 
Cic(fc), 3D(fc) to this picture. 

There is, however, a class of games where the sequence Cti, , ft,,ft,+i 
tells practically the entire story. This is the important class already 
discussed in 6.4.1., and about which more will be said in 15. where 
preliminarity and anteriority are equivalent. Its characteristics find a 
simple expression in our present formalism. 

10.4.2. Preliminarity and anteriority are equivalent as the discussions 
of 6.4.1., 6.4.2. and the interpretation of 6.4.3. show if and only if every 
player who makes a personal move knows at that moment the entire anterior 
history of the play. Let the player be fc, the move 9TC,. The assertion 
that 9TI, is k'a personal move means, then, that we are within B K (k). Hence 
the assertion is that within B K (k) the player fc's pattern of information 
coincides with the umpire's pattern of information; i.e. that 2D(fc) is equal to 



78 



DESCRIPTION OF GAMES OF STRATEGY 



Q, K within B K (k). But >(&) is a partition in B K (k); hence the above state- 
ment means that >,(&) simply is that part of a* which lies in B K (k). 
We restate this: 

(10:B) Preliminarity and anteriority coincide i.e. every player who 

makes a personal move is at that moment fully informed about 
the entire anterior history of the play if and only if > K (k) is 
that part of (t K which lies in B K (k). 

If this is the case, then we can argue on as follows: By (10:1 :c) in 10.1.1. 
and the above, Q K (k) must now be a subpartition of Q K . This holds for 
personal moves, i.e. for k = 1, , n, but for k = it follows immedi- 




Figure 10. 

ately from (10:1 :b) in 10.1.1. Now (10:1 :h) in 10.1.1. permits the inference 
from this (for details cf. 9.2.2.) that a+i coincides with Q K (k) in B K (k) for 
all k = 0, 1, , n. (We could equally have used the corresponding 
points in 10.1.2., i.e. the " meaning " of these concepts. We leave the verbal 
expression of the argument to the reader.) But Q K (k) is a partition in B K (k) ; 
hence the above statement means that C<(k) simply is that part of G^+i 
which lies in B^k). 
We restate this: 

(10:C) If the condition of (10:B) is fulfilled, then Q K (k) is that part 

of ft*+i which lies in B^k). 

Thus when preliminarity and anteriority coincide, then in our present 
formalism the sequence tti, , a,,a,+i and the sets B x (k), k = 0, 1, 
, n, for each K = 1, , v, describe the game fully. I.e. the picture 



STRATEGIES AND FINAL SIMPLIFICATION 79 

of Figure 9 in 8.3.2. must be amplified only by bracketing together those 
elements of each &, which belong to the same set (& K (k). (Cf. however, the 
remark made in 10.4.1.) We can do this by encircling them with a line, 
across which the number k of B K (k) is written. Such B K (k) as are empty can 
be omitted. We give an example of this for v = 5 and n = 3 (Figure 10). 

In many games of this class even this extra device is not necessary, 
because for every K only one B K (k) is not empty. I.e. the character of each 
move 311, is independent of the previous course of the play. 1 Then it 
suffices to indicate at each Ot, the character of the move 3fTC* i.e. the unique 
k = 0, 1, , n for which B K (k) j . 

11. Strategies and the Final Simplification of the Description of a Game 
11.1. The Concept of a Strategy and Its Formalization 

11.1.1. Let us return to the course of an actual play TT of the game F. 

The moves SfTC* follow each other in the order K = 1, , v. At each 
move 9Tl a choice is made, either by chance if the play is in B<(0) or by a 
player k = 1, , n if the play is in B K (k). The choice consists in the 
selection of a C K from Q K (k) (k = or k = 1, , n, cf. above), to which 
the play is then restricted. If the choice is made by a player fc, then pre- 
cautions must be taken that this player's pattern of information should be 
at this moment >*(&), as required. (That this can be a matter of some 
practical difficulty is shown by such examples as Bridge [cf. the end of 
6.4.2.] and double-blind Chess [cf. 9.2.3.].) 

Imagine now that each player k = 1, , n, instead of making each 
decision as the necessity for it arises, makes up his mind in advance for all 
possible contingencies; i.e. that the player k begins to play with a complete 
plan: $ plan which specifies what choices he will make in every possible situa- 
tion, for every possible actual information which he may possess at that 
moment in conformity with the pattern of information which the rules of 
the game provide for him for that case. We call such a plan a strategy. 

Observe that if we require each player to start the game with a complete 
plan of this kind, i.e. with a strategy, we by no means restrict his freedom 
of action. In particular, we do not thereby force him to make decisions 
on the basis of less information than there would be available for him in each 
practical instance in an actual play. This is because the strategy is sup- 
posed to specify every particular decision only as a function of just that 
amount of actual information which would be available for this purpose in 
an actual play. The only extra burden our assumption puts on the player 
is the intellectual one to be prepared with a rule of behavior for all even- 
tualities, although he is to go through one play only. But this is an innoc- 
uous assumption within the confines of a mathematical analysis. (Cf. 
also 4.1.2.) 

1 This is true for Chess. The rules of Backgammon permit interpretations both 



80 DESCRIPTION OF GAMES OF STRATEGY 

11.1.2. The chance component of the game can be treated in the same 
way. 

It is indeed obvious that it is not necessary to make the choices which are 
left to chance, i.e. those of the chance moves, only when those moves come 
along. An umpire could make them all in advance, and disclose their 
outcome to the players at the various moments and to the varying extent, 
as the rules of the game provide about their information. 

It is true that the umpire cannot know in advance which moves will be 
chance ones, and with what probabilities; this will in general depend upon 
the actual course of the play. But as in the strategies which we considered 
above he could provide for all contingencies: He could decide in advance 
what the outcome of the choice in every possible chance move should be, for 
every possible anterior course of the play, i.e. for every possible actual 
umpire's information at the move in question. Under these conditions the 
probabilities prescribed by the rules of the game for each one of the above 
instances would be fully determined and so the umpire could arrange for 
each one of the necessary choices to be effected by chance, with the appro- 
priate probabilities. 

The outcomes could then be disclosed by the umpire to the players at 
the proper moments and to the proper extent as described above. 

We call such a preliminary decision of the choices of all conceivable 
chance moves an umpire's choice. 

We saw in the last section that the replacement of the choices of all 
personal moves of the player k by the strategy of the player k is legitimate ; 
i.e. that it does not modify the fundamental character of the game F. 
Clearly our present replacement of the choices of all chance moves by the 
umpire's choice is legitimate in the same sense. 

11.1.3. It remains for us to formalize the concepts of a strategy and of 
the umpire's choice. The qualitative discussion of the two last sections 
makes this an unambiguous task. 

A strategy of the player k does this: Consider a move 3fTC,. Assume that 
it has turned out to be a personal move of the player &, i.e. assume that 
the play is within B(fc). Consider a possible actual information of the 
player k at that moment, i.e. consider a D* of ><(&). Then the strategy 
in question must determine his choice at this juncture, i.e. a C of Q K (k) 
which is a subset of the above D K . 

Formalized: 

(11:A) A strategy of the player A; is a function 2*(/c; D K ) which is 

defined for every * = !,,*/ and every D K of >, (k), and 
whose value 

2*(*; D,) = C, 

has always these properties: C K belongs to 6(fc) and is a subset 
ofD,. 

That strategies i.e. functions S*(K; D<) fulfilling the above requirement 
exist at all, coincides precisely with our postulate (10:1 :j) in 10.1.1. 



STRATEGIES AND FINAL SIMPLIFICATION 81 

An umpire's choice does this: 

Consider a move 9TC. Assume that it has turned out to be a chance 
move, i.e. assume that the play is within J3(0). Consider a possible 
actual information of the umpire at this moment; i.e. consider an A K of ft, 
which is a subset of B(0). Then the umpire's choice in question must 
determine the chance choice at this juncture, i.e. a C of <3(0) which is a 
subset of the above A K . 

Formalized : 

(11 :B) An umpire's choice is a function 2o(*; A K ) which is defined for 

every K = 1, , v and every A K of QL K which is a subset of 
B K (0) and whose value 

So(*; A K ) = C, 

has always these properties: C belongs to <B(0) and is a subset 
of A K . 

Concerning the existence of umpire's choices i.e. of functions 2 (*; ^) 
fulfilling the above requirement cf. the remark after (11:A) above, and 
footnote 2 on p. 71. 

Since the outcome of the umpire's choice depends on chance, the cor- 
responding probabilities must be specified. Now the umpire's choice is an 
aggregate of independent chance events. There is such an event, as 
described in 11.1.2., for every K = 1, , v and every A K of G, which is a 
subset of J3(0). I.e. for every pair *, A< in the domain of definition of 
SO(K; At). As far as this event is concerned the probability of the particular 
outcome 2o(*; A K ) = C K is p*(C^). Hence the probability of the entire 
umpire's choice, represented by the function 2 (*; A K ) is the product of the 
individual probabilities p K (C K ). 1 

Formalized : 

(11:C) The probability of the umpire's choice, represented by the 

function o(*; A K ) is the product of the probabilities p(C), 
where 2 (*; A K ) = C, and K, A K run over the entire domain of 
definition of 2o(*; A K ) (cf. (11 :B) above). 

If we consider the conditions of (10:l:e) in 10.1.1. for all these pairs 
K, A K , and multiply them all with each other, then these facts result: The 
probabilities of (11:C) above are all ^ 0, and their sum (extended over all 
umpire's choices) is one. This is as it should be, since the totality of all 
umpire's choices is a system of disjunct but exhaustive alternatives. 

ll.). The Final Simplification of the Description of a Game 
11.2.1. If a definite strategy has been adopted by each player k = 1, 
, n, and if a definite umpire's choice has been selected, then these 
determine the entire course of the play uniquely, and accordingly its 

1 The chance events in question must be treated as independent. 



82 DESCRIPTION OF GAMES OF STRATEGY 

outcome too, for each player k = 1, , n. This should be clear from 
the verbal description of all these concepts, but an equally simple formal 
proof can be given. 

Denote the strategies in question by 2*(/c; D K ), k = 1, , n, and the 
umpire's choice by 2 (/c; A K ). We shall determine the umpire's actual 
information at all moments K = 1, , v } v + 1. In order to avoid 
confusing it with the above variable A^, we denote it by A K . 

A i is, of course, equal to 12 itself. (Cf. (10:1 :f) in 10.1.1.) 

Consider now a K = 1, , v, and assume that the corresponding A K 
is already known. Then A K is a subset of precisely one B K (k), k = 0, 1, 
- , n. (Cf. (10:1 :a) in 10.1.1.) If k = 0, then 3TC, is a chance move, and 
so the outcome of the choice is 2o(*; A K ). Accordingly A f +i = 2o(*; A K ). 
(Cf. (10:1 :h) in 10.1.1. and the details in 9.2.2.) If k = 1, , n, then 
3TC, is a personal move of the player k. A K is a subset of precisely one D K of 
>,(fc). (Cf. (10:1 :d) in 10.1.1.) So the outcome of the choice is Z*(K; D K ). 
Accordingly A f +i = A K n S*(K; D K ). (Cf. (10:1 :h) in 10.1.1. and the details 
in 9.2.2.) 

Thus we determine inductively A\, A^ A^ - , A vy A v +i in succession. 
But A 9 +i is a one-element set (cf. (10:1 :g) in 10.1.1.); denote its unique 
element by if. 

This TT is the actual play which took place. 1 Consequently the outcome 
of the play is *(*) for the player k = 1, , n. 

11.2.2. The fact that the strategies of all players and the umpire's 
choice determine together the actual play and so its outcome for each 
player opens up the possibility of a new and much simpler description of 
the game F. 

Consider a given player k = 1, , n. Form all possible strategies 
of his, 2*(*; D K ), or for short 2*. While their number is enormous, 
it is obviously finite. Denote it by Pk, and the strategies themselves by 

ZJ, ' , 2&- 

Form similarly all possible umpire's choices, 2 (*; A K ), or for short 2 . 
Again their number is finite. Denote it by /3o, and the umpire's choices by 
2j, , 2?o. Denote their probabilities by p 1 , , p^o respectively. 
(Cf. (11 :C) in 11.1.3.) All these probabilities are ^ and their sum is one. 
(Cf. the end of 11.1.3.) 

A definite choice of all strategies and of the umpire's choices, say 2J* for 
k = 1, , n and for k = respectively, where 

T* = 1, , /fo for k = 0, 1, , n, 

determines the play TT (cf. the end of 11.2.1.), and its outcome ^(TT) for 
each player k = 1, , n. Write accordingly 

(11:1) IF*(T) = S*(T O , TI, , r n ) for k = 1, , n. 

1 The above inductive derivation of the Ai, ^2, ^j, , Av, A+i is just a mathemat- 
ical reproduction of the actual course of the play. The reader should verify the parallel- 
ism of the steps involved. 



STRATEGIES AND FINAL SIMPLIFICATION 83 

The entire play now consists of each player k choosing a strategy SJ, 
i.e. a number 7 fc =!, , 0*; and of the chance umpire's choice of T O = 1, 
, 0o, with the probabilities p\ , /A respectively. 

The player k must choose his strategy, i.e. his r*, without any information 
concerning the choices of the other players, or of the chance events (the 
umpire's choice). This must be so since all the information he can at any 
time possess is already embodied in his strategy 2* = SJ* i.e. in the function 
2jk = *(*; D K ). (Cf. the discussion of 11.1.1.) Even if he holds definite 
views as to what the strategies of the other players are likely to be, they 
must be already contained in the function 2* (K; D). 

11.2.3. All this means, however, that F has been brought back to the 
very simplest description, within the least complicated original framework of 
the sections 6.2.1. -6.3.1. We have n + I moves, one chance and one 
personal for each player k = 1, , n each move has a fixed number of 
alternatives, /3 for the chance move and 0i, , ft for the personal ones 
and every player has to make this choice with absolutely no information 
concerning the outcome of all other choices. 1 

Now we can get rid even of the chance move. If the choices of the 
players have taken place, the player k having chosen T*, then the total 
influence of the chance move is this : The outcome of the play for the player k 
may be any one of the numbers 

9*( T 0, TI, , T n ), 7 = 1, ' ' ' , 00, 

with the probabilities p 1 , , yA respectively. Consequently his 
" mathematical expectation " of the outcome is 



(11:2) JC*(TI, ,r n ) = P T .S*(T O , T lf , r n ). 

r -l 

The player's judgment must be directed solely by this " mathematical 
expectation/' because the various moves, and in particular the chance 
move, are completely isolated from each other. 2 Thus the only moves 
which matter are the n personal moves of the players k = 1, n. 

The final formulation is therefore this : 

(11:D) The n person game T, i.e. the complete system of its rules, is 

determined by the specification of the following data: 
(ll:D:a) For every k = !, , n: A number /3*. 

(ll:D:b) For every k = 1, , n: A function 

3C* = OC*(ri, , r n ), 
r, = 1, , ft for j = 1, - , n. 

1 Owing to this complete disconnectedness of the n -f 1 moves, it does not matter 
in what chronological order they are placed. 

2 We are entitled to use the unmodified "mathematical expectation" since we are 
satisfied with the simplified concept of utility, as stressed at the end of 5.2.2 This 
excludes in particular all those more elaborate concepts of "expectation," which are 
really attempts at improving that naive concept of utility. (E.g. D. Bernoulli's "moral 
expectation" in the "St. Petersburg Paradox.") 



84 DESCRIPTION OF GAMES OF STRATEGY 

The course of a play of T is this: 

Each player k chooses a number r = 1, ,/}. Each 
player must make his choice in absolute ignorance of the choices 
of the others. After all choices have been made, they are 
submitted to an umpire who determines that the outcome of the 
play for the player k is 3C*(ri, , r n ). 

11.3. The Role of Strategies in the Simplified Form of a Game 

11.3. Observe that in this scheme no space is left for any kind of further 
11 strategy." Each player has one move, and one move only; and he must 
make it in absolute ignorance of everything else. 1 This complete crystal- 
lization of the problem in this rigid and final form was achieved by our 
manipulations of the sections from 11.1.1. on, in which the transition from 
the original moves to strategies was effected. Since we now treat these 
strategies themselves as moves, there is no need for strategies of a higher 
order. 

11.4. The Meaning of the Zero-sum Restriction 

11.4. We conclude these considerations by determining the place of the 
zero-sum games (cf. 5.2.1.) within our final scheme. 

That T is a zero-sum game means, in the notation of 10.1.1., this: 

n 

(11:3) J 5k(*) = for all w of fl. 

Jb-l 

If we pass from ^(TT) to 8* (TO, r,, , r n ), in the sense of 11.2.2., then this 
becomes 

n 

(11:4) 9*(T ,Ti, , r n ) =0 for all TO, TI, ,r n . 

*-i 

And if we finally introduce JC*(TI, , r), in the sense of 1 1.2.3., we obtain 

n 

(11:5) 5) OC*(ri, , r n ) = for all n, , r n . 

*-i 

Conversely, it is clear that the condition (11 :5) makes the game F, which we 
defined in 11.2.3., one of zero sum. 

1 Reverting to the definition of a strategy as given in 11.1.1.: In this game a player A; 
has one and only one personal move, and this independently of the course of the play, 
the move 311*. And he must make his choice at Sdl* with nil information. So his 
strategy is simply a definite choice for the move 9R*, no more and no less; i.e. precisely 
r - 1, , 0*. 

We leave it to the reader to describe this game in terms of partitions, and to compare 
the above with the formalistic definition of a strategy in (11 : A) in 11.1.3. 



CHAPTER III 
ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

12. Preliminary Survey 
12.1. General Viewpoints 

12.1.1. In the preceding chapter we obtained an all-inclusive formal 
characterization of the general game of n persons (cf. 10.1.). We followed 
up by developing an exact concept of strategy which permitted us to replace 
the rather complicated general scheme of a game by a much more simple 
special one, which was nevertheless shown to be fully equivalent to the 
former (cf. 11.2.). In the discussion which follows it will sometimes be 
more convenient to use one form, sometimes the other. It is therefore 
desirable to give them specific technical names. We will accordingly call 
them the extensive and the normalized form of the game, respectively. 

Since these two forms are strictly equivalent, it is entirely within our 
province to use in each particular case whichever is technically more con- 
venient at that moment. We propose, indeed, to make full use of this 
possibility, and must therefore re-emphasize that this does not in the least 
affect the absolutely general validity of all our considerations. 

Actually the normalized form is better suited for the derivation of 
general theorems, while the extensive form is preferable for the analysis of 
special cases; i.e., the former can be used advantageously to establish pro- 
perties which are common to all games, while the latter brings out charac- 
teristic differences of games and the decisive structural features which 
determine these differences. (Cf. for the former 14., 17., and for the latter 
e.g. 15.) 

12.1.2. Since the formal description of all games has been completed, 
we must now turn to build up a positive theory. It is to be expected that 
a systematic procedure to this end will have to proceed from simpler games 
to more complicated games. It is therefore desirable to establish an 
ordering for all games according to their increasing degree of complication. 

We have already classified games according to the number of partici- 
pants a game with n participants being called an n-person game and 
also according to whether they are or are not of zero-sum. Thus we must 
distinguish zero-sum n-person games and general n-person games. It will 
be seen later that the general n-person game is very closely related to the 
zero-sum (n + l)-person game, in fact the theory of the former will 
obtain as a special case of the theory of the latter. (Cf. 56.2.2.) 

12.2. The One-person Game 

12.2.1. We begin with some remarks concerning the one-person game. 
In the normalized form this game consists of the choice of a number 

85 



86 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

r = 1, , 0, after which the (only) player 1 gets the amount 3C(r). 1 The 
zero-sum case is obviously void 2 and there is nothing to say concerning it. 
The general case corresponds to a general function 3C(r) and the "best" 
or " rational" way of acting i.e. of playing consists obviously of this: 
The player 1 will choose r = 1, , so as to make JC(r) a maximum. 

This extreme simplification of the one-person game is, of course, due 
to the fact that our variable r represents not a choice (in a move) but 
the player's strategy; i.e., it expresses his entire "theory" concerning the 
handling of all conceivable situations which may occur in the course of the 
play. It should be remembered that even a one-person game can be of a 
very complicated pattern: It may contain chance moves as well as personal 
moves (of the only player), each one possibly with numerous alternatives, 
and the amount of information available to the player at any particular 
personal move may vary in any prescribed way. 

12.2.2. Numerous good examples of many complications and subtleties 
which may arise in this way are given by the various games of "Patience" 
or "Solitaire." There is, however, an important possibility for which, to 
the best of our knowledge, examples are lacking among the customary 
one-person games. This is the case of incomplete information, i.e. of non- 
equivalence of anteriority and preliminarity of personal moves of the 
unique player (cf. 6.4.). For such an absence of equivalence it would be 
necessary that the player have two personal moves 311* and 3n\ at neither 
of which he is informed about the outcome of the choice of the other. 
Such a state of lack of information is not easy to achieve, but we discussed 
in 6.4.2. how it can be brought about by "splitting" the player into two 
or more persons of identical interest and with imperfect communications. 
We saw loc. cit. that Bridge is an example of this in a two-person game; 
it would be easy to construct an analogous one-person game but unluckily 
the known forms of "solitaire" are not such. 8 

This possibility is nevertheless a practical one for certain economic 
setups: A rigidly established communistic society, in which the structure 
of the distribution scheme is beyond dispute (i.e. where there is no exchange, 
but only one unalterable imputation) would be such since the interests 
of all the members of such a society are strictly identical 4 this setup must be 
treated as a one-person game. But owing to the conceivable imperfections 
of communications among the members, all sorts of incomplete information 
can occur. 

This is then the case which, by a consistent use of the concept of strategy 
(i.e. of planning), is naturally reduced to a simple maximum problem. On 
the basis of our previous discussions it will therefore be apparent now 

Cf. (ll:D:a), (ll:D:b) at the end of 11.2.3. We suppress the index 1 . 

8 Then3C(r) = 0, cf. 11.4. 

8 The existing "double solitaires " are competitive games between the two partici- 
pants, i.e. two-person games. 

4 The individual members themselves cannot be considered as players, since all 
possibilities of conflict among them, as well as coalitions of some of them against the 
others, are excluded. 



PRELIMINARY SURVEY 87 

that this and this only is the case in which the simple maximum formu- 
lation i.e. the "Robinson Crusoe" form of economics is appropriate. 

12.2.3. These considerations show also the limitations of the pure 
maximum i.e. the "Robinson Crusoe " approach. The above example 
of a society of a rigidly established and unquestioned distribution scheme 
shows that on this plane a rational and critical appraisal of the distribution 
scheme itself is impossible. In order to get a maximum problem it was 
necessary to place the entire scheme of distribution among the rules of the 
game, which are absolute, inviolable and above criticism. In order to 
bring them into the sphere of combat and competition i.e. the strategy 
of the game it is necessary to consider n-person games with n ^ 2 and 
thereby to sacrifice the simple maximum aspect of the problem. 

12.3. Chance and Probability 

12.3. Before going further, we wish to mention that the extensive 
literature of "mathematical games " which was developed mainly in 
the 18th and 19th centuries deals essentially only with an aspect of the 
matter which we have already left behind. This is the appraisal of the 
influence of chance. This was, of course, effected by the discovery and 
appropriate application of the calculus of probability and particularly 
of the concept of mathematical expectations. In our discussions, the 
operations necessary for this purpose were performed in 11.2.3. 1 * 2 

Consequently we are no longer interested in these games, where the 
mathematical problem consists only in evaluating the role of chance i.e. 
in computing probabilities and mathematical expectations. Such games 
lead occasionally to interesting exercises in probability theory; 8 but we 
hope that the reader will agree with us that they do not belong in the 
theory of games proper. 

12.4. The Next Objective 

12.4. We now proceed to the analysis of more complicated games. 
The general one-person game having been disposed of, the simplest one 
of the remaining games is the zero-sum two-person game. Accordingly 
we are going to discuss it first. 

Afterwards there is a choice of dealing either with the general two- 
person game or with the zero sum three-person game. It will be seen that 
our technique of discussion necessitates taking up the zero-sum three-person 

1 We do not in the least intend, of course, to detract from the enormous importance 
of those discoveries. It is just because of their great power that we are now in a position 
to treat this side of the matter as briefly as we do. We are interested in those aspects of 
the problem which are not settled by the concept of probability alone; consequently 
these and not the satisfactorily settled ones must occupy our attention. 

2 Concerning the important connection between the use of mathematical expectation 
and the concept of numerical utility, cf . 3.7. and the considerations which precede it. 

8 Some games like Roulette are of an even more peculiar character. In Roulette the 
mathematical expectation of the players is clearly negative. Thus the motives for 
participating in that game cannot be understood if one identifies the monetary return 
with utility. 



88 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

game first. After that we shall extend the theory to the zero-sum n-person 
game (for all n = 1, 2, 3, ) and only subsequently to this will it be 
found convenient to investigate the general n-person game. 

13. Functional Calculus 
13.1. Basic Definitions 

13.1.1. Our next objective is as stated in 12.4. the exhaustive dis- 
cussion of the zero-sum two-person games. In order to do this adequately, 
it will be necessary to use the symbolism of the functional calculus or at 
least of certain parts of it more extensively than we have done thus far. 
The concepts which we need are those of functions, of variables, of maxima 
and minima, and of the use of the two latter as functional operations. All 
this necessitates a certain amount of explanation and illustration, which 
will be given here. 

After that is done, we will prove some theorems concerning maxima, 
minima, and a certain combination of these two, the saddle value. These 
theorems will play an important part in the theory of the zero-sum two- 
person games. 

13.1.2. A function </> is a dependence which states how certain entities 
%, y, ' ' ' called the variables of <t> determine an entity u called the 
value of </>. Thus u is determined by <f> and by the x, y, - , and this 
determination i.e. dependence will be indicated by the symbolic equation 

u = </>(*, y, ). 

In principle it is necessary to distinguish between the function <t> itself 
which is an abstract entity, embodying only the general dependence of 
u = <t>(x, y, - - - ) on the x, y, - - and its value <t>(x, y, - ) for any 
specific x, y, . In practical mathematical usage, however, it is often 
convenient to write <t>(x, y, - - - ) but with x, y, - - - indeterminate 
instead of (cf. the examples (c)-(e) below; (a), (b) are even worse, cf. 
footnote 1 below). 

In order to describe the function < it is of course necessary among 
other things to specify the number of its variables x, y, - - - . Thus 
there exist one-variable functions <t>(x), two-variable functions <t>(x, y), etc. 

Some examples: 

(a) The arithmetical operations x + 1 and x 2 are one-variable functions. l 

(b) The arithmetical operations of addition and of multiplication x + y 
and xy, are two- variable functions. 1 

(c) For any fixed k the *(*) of 9.2.4. is a one- variable function (of w). 
But it can also be viewed as a two- variable function (of fc, w). 

(d) For any fixed k the S*(K, DJ of (11 :A) in 11.1.3. is a two-variable 
function (of ic, D). 2 

(e) For any fixed k the 3C*(ri, , r 5 ) of 11.2.3. is a n-variable function 
(of n, , r n ). 1 

1 Although they do not appear in the above canonical forms <t>(x), <t>(x, y). 
1 We could also treat k in (d) and k in (e) like k in (c), i.e. as a variable. 



FUNCTIONAL CALCULUS 89 

13.1.3. It is equally necessary, in order to describe a function < to 
specify for which specific choices of its variables x, y, the value 
<t>(%> y> ' ' ' ) is defined at all. These choices i.e. these combinations of 
x, y, form the domain of <t>. 

The examples (a)-(e) show some of the many possibilities for the domains 
of functions: They may consist of arithmetical or of analytical entities, as 
well as of others. Indeed: 

(a) We may consider the domain to consist of all integer numbers, 
or equally well of all real numbers. 

(b) All pairs of either category of numbers used in (a), form the domain. 

(c) The domain is the set Q of all objects * which represent the plays 
of the game T (cf. 9.1.1. and 9.2.4.). 

(d) The domain consists of pairs of a positive integer K and a set D. 

(e) The domain consists of certain systems of positive integers. 

A function <f> is an arithmetical function if its variables are positive 
integers; it is a numerical function if its variables are real numbers; it is a 
set-function if its variables are sets (as, e.g., D< in (d)). 

For the moment we are mainly interested in arithmetical and numerical 
functions. 

We conclude this section by an observation which is a natural conse- 
quence of our view of the concept of a function. This is, that the number 
of variables, the domain, and the dependence of the value on the varia- 
bles, constitute the function as such: i.e., if two functions <, \l/ have the 
same variables x, y, and the same domain, and if <t>(x, y, ) = 
y> ' * * ) throughout this domain, then <, \l/ are identical in all respects. 1 

13.2. The Operations Max and Min 
13.2.1. Consider a function <t> which has real numbers for values 



Assume first that is a one-variable function. If its variable can be 
chosen, say as x = z so that <f>(x ) ^ <t>(x') for all other choices x', then we 
say that <t> has the maximum <t>(x<>) and assumes it at x = x . 

Observe that this maximum </>(z ) is uniquely determined; i.e., the 
maximum may be assumed at x = XQ for several z , but they must all fur- 
nish the same value <t>(xo). 2 We denote this value by Max <t>(x), the maxi- 
mum value of <t>(x). 

If we replace ^ by ^, then the concept of </>'s minimum, <A(x ), obtains, 
and of XQ where </> assumes it. Again there may be several such x , but they 
must all furnish the same value <t>(x Q ). We denote this value by Min <t>(x), 
the minimum value of </>. 

1 The concept of a function is closely allied to that of a set, and the above should be 
viewed in parallel with the exposition of 8.2. 

* Proof: Consider two such a? , say x' and x'J. Then 4(si) *(x' ') and <K*'o') 
Hence 4>(x'>) 



90 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

Observe that there is no a priori guarantee that either Max <t>(x) or 
Min <(>(x) exist. 1 

If, however, the domain of </> over which the variable x may run 
consists only of a finite number of elements, then the existence of both 
Max <t>(x) and Min <t>(x) is obvious. This will actually be the case for most 
functions which we shall discuss. 2 For the remaining ones it will be a 
consequence of their continuity together with the geometrical limitations of 
their domains. 8 At any rate we are restricting our considerations to such 
functions, for which Max and Min exist. 

13.2.2. Let now <t> have any number of variables x,y,z, . By sin- 
gling out one of the variables, say x, and treating the others, y y z, - , as 
constants, we can view <t>(x, y, z, - - - ) as a one-variable function, of the 
variable x. Hence we may form Max <t>(x,y,z, ), Min </> (z, t/, 2, ) 
as in 13.2.1., of course with respect to this x. 

But since we could have done this equally well for any one of the other 
variables y, z, it becomes necessary to indicate that the operations 
Max, Min were performed with respect to the variable x. We do this by 
writing Max* </>(z, y, z, ), Min x <(z, y, z, ' ' * ) instead of the incom- 
plete expressions Max <t>, Min </>. Thus we can now apply to the function 
<t>(x> y, z > ' * ' ) an Y ne of the operators Max*, Min z , Max y , Min y , Max*, 
Min,, . They are all distinct and our notation is unambiguous. 

This notation is even advantageous for one variable functions, and we 
will use it accordingly; i.e. we write Max* <(#), Min* <t>(x) instead of the 
Max (x), Min 4>(x) of 13.2.1. 

Sometimes it will be convenient or even necessary to indicate the 
domain S for a maximum or a minimum explicitly. E.g. when the func- 
tion <t>(x) is defined also for (some) x outside of S, but it is desired to form the 
maximum or minimum within S only. In such a case we write 

Max xin5 0(x), Min xin5 <t>(x) 

instead of Max* <(#), Min x <(z). 

In certain other cases it may be simpler to enumerate the values of <f>(x) 
say o, 6, than to express <t>(x) as a function. We may then write 

1 E.g. if <t>(x) ss x with all real numbers as domain, then neither Max 0(x) nor Min <f>(x) 
exist. 

2 Typical examples: The functions 3C*(,n, , r n ) of 11.2.3. (or of (e) in 13.1.2.), the 
function 3C(ri, TZ) of 14.1.1. 

> > > > > 

8 Typical examples: The functions K( , 17 ), Max-> K( , 17 ), Min- K( , 17 ) in 

* * 

0i ft, 

17.4., the functions Min Tl ^/ ^(n, T 2 ) v Max fi ^ 3C(n, r t )ij r in 17.5.2. The vari- 

r^l^ ^ r t -l 

ables of all these functions are or j or both, with respect to which subsequent maxima 
and minima are formed. 

Another instance is discussed in 46.2.1. espec. footnote 1 on p. 384, where the 
mathematical background of this subject and its literature are considered. It seems 
unnecessary to enter upon these here, since the above examples are entirely elementary. 



FUNCTIONAL CALCULUS 91 

Max (a, &,-)> [Min (a, 6, )] instead of Max* <(z), [Min* 



13.2.3. Observe that while </>(x, y, z, - ) is a function of the variables 
x, y, z, , Max* <t>(x, y, z, - - - ), Min* <f>(x, y, *,) are still func- 
tions, but of the variables y, z, only. Purely typographically, x is 
still present in Max, </>(#, y, z, - ), Min* <t>(x, y, z, - - - ), but it is no 
longer a variable of these functions. We say that the operations Max*, 
Min* kill the variable x which appears as their index. 2 

Since Max* <t>(x, y, z, ), Min* 4>(x, y, z, ) are still functions 
of the variables y, z, , 3 we can go on and form the expressions 

Maxy Max* <t>(x, y, z, ), Max y Min* <f>(x, y, z, - ), 
Min y Max* <(z, y, z, - - ), Min y Min* <t>(x, y, z, - ), 

We could equally form 

Max* Maxy <j>(x, y, z, ), Max* Min y <t>(x, y, z, ) 

etc. ; 4 or use two other variables than x, y (if there are any) ; or use more 
variables than two (if there are any). 

In fine, after having applied as many operations Max or Min as there are 
variables of <t>(x, y, z, ) in any order and combination, but precisely 
one for each variable x, y, z, - we obtain a function of no variables 
at all, i.e. a constant. 

13.3. Commutativity Questions 

13.3.1. The discussions of 13.2.3. provide the basis for viewing the Max*, 
Min*, Maxy, Min tf , Max,, Min*, entirely as functional operations, each 
one of which carries a function into another function. 5 We have seen that 
we can apply several of them successively. In this latter case it is prima 
facie relevant, in which order the successive operations are applied. 

But is it really relevant? Precisely: Two operations are said to commute 
if, in case of their successive application (to the same object), the order in 
which this is done does not matter. Now we ask : Do the operations Max*, 
Min*, Maxy, Min y , Max,, Min,, all commute with each other or not? 

We shall answer this question. For this purpose we need use only two 
variables, say x, y and then it is not necessary that <f> be a function of further 
variables besides x, y. 6 

1 Of course Max (a, b, - ) [Min (a, b, )] is simply the greatest [smallest] one 
among the numbers a, b, - . 

1 A well known operation in analysis which kills a variable x is the definite integral: 

f\ 
4>(x) is a function of x, but / <j>(x)dx is a constant. 

8 We treated fy, z, as constant parameters in 13.2.2. But now that x has been 
killed we release the variables y, z, . 

4 Observe that if two or more operations are applied, the innermost applies first and 
kills its variable; then the next one follows suit, etc 

6 With one variable less, since these operations kill one variable each. 

8 Further variables of <, if any, may be treated as constants for the purpose of this 
analysis. 



92 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

So we consider a t Wo- variable function <t>(x, y). The significant ques- 
tions of commutativity are then clearly these: 

Which of the three equations which follow are generally true: 

(13:1) Max, Max y 0(x, y) = Max y Max, <t>(x f y), 

(13:2) Min, Min y <Kz, y) = Min y Min, <(x, y), 

(13:3) Max, Min y </>(x, y) = Min y Max, <t>(x, y). 1 

We shall see that (13:1), (13:2) are true, while (13:3) is not; i.e., any two 
Max or any two Min commute, while a Max and a Min do not commute in 
general. We shall also obtain a criterion which determines in which special 
cases Max and Min commute. 

This question of commutativity of Max and Min will turn out to be 
decisive for the zero-sum two-person game (cf. 14.4.2. and 17.6.). 

13.3.2. Let us first consider (13:1). It ought to be intuitively clear that 
Max, Max y <f>(x, y) is the maximum of <(x, y) if we treat x, y together as one 
variable; i.e. that for some suitable x () , 2/0, </>(x , 2/o) = Max x Max y 0(x, y) 
and that for all x', y', <f>(x , y ) ^ <t>(x', y'). 

If a mathematical proof is nevertheless wanted, we give it here: Choose 
xo so that Max y <f>(x, y) assumes its x-maximum at x = x , and then choose j/ 
so that <t>(xQ, y) assumes its y-maximum at y = y Q . Then 



/o) = Max y </>(x , y) = Max, Max y <(x, y), 
and for all x', y 1 

o, 2/0) = Max y </>(x , y) ^ Max y </>(x', y) ^ <t>(x', y'). 



This completes the proof. 

Now by interchanging x, y we see that Max y Max, <(x, y) is equally 
the maximum of </>(x, y) if we treat x, y as one variable. 

Thus both sides of (13:1) have the same characteristic property, and 
therefore they are equal to each other. This proves (13:1). 

Literally the same arguments apply to Mm in place of Max: we need 
only use ^ consistently in place of ^ . This proves (13 :2). 

This device of treating two variables x, y as one, is occasionally quite 
convenient in itself. When we use it (as, e.g., in 18.2.1., with n, r 2 , 3C(ri, r 2 ) 
in place of our present x, y, <(x, z/)), we shall write Max,, y <(x, y) and 
Min,. y <(x, 2/). 

13.3.3. At this point a graphical illustration may be useful. Assume 
that the domain of <f> for x, y is a finite set. Denote, for the sake of sim- 
plicity, the possible values of x (in this domain) by 1, , t and those of 
y by 1, ,$. Then the values of </(x, y) corresponding to all x, y in this 
domain i.e. to all combinations of x = 1, , /, y = 1, , $ can 
be arranged in a rectangular scheme: We use a rectangle of t rows and s 

1 The combination Min, Max,, requires no treatment of its own, since it obtains from 
the above Max, Min y by interchanging x, y. 



FUNCTIONAL CALCULUS 



93 



columns, using the number x = 1, , t to enumerate the former and 
the number y = 1, , s to enumerate the latter. Into the field of inter- 
section of row x and column y to be known briefly as the field x, y we 
write the value <t>(x t y) (Fig. 11). This arrangement, known in mathematics 
as a rectangular matrix, amounts to a complete characterization of the func- 
tion <t>(x, y). The specific values <(x, y) are the matrix elements. 





1 


2 




y 




s 
















1 


0(1, 1) 


$(1, 2) 




*>(!, y) 




^(l, ) 
















2 


d(2, 1) 


0(2, 2) 




<fr(2, y} 




0(2, ) 































x 


4>(x, 1) 


<t>(x t 2) 




0(z, y} 




0(s, s] 





























- 


t 


d(J, 1) 


4>(l 2) 




<t>(t y} 




4>(L a) 

















Figure 11. 

Now MaXy <t>(x, y) is the maximum of <(#, y) in the row x. 

Max x 



is therefore the maximum of the row maxima. On the other hand, 

Max* <t>(x, y) 

is the maximum of <f>(x, y) in the column y. Max y Max* <(#, y) is therefore 
the maximum of the column maxima. Our assertions in 13.3.2. concerning 
(13:1) can now be stated thus: The maximum of the row maxima is the 
same as the maximum of the column maxima; both are the absolute maxi- 
mum of <t>(x, y) in the matrix. In this form, at least, these assertions should 
be intuitively obvious. The assertions concerning (13:2) obtain in the 
same way if Min is put in place of Max. 

13.4. The Mixed Case. Saddle Points 

13.4.1. Let us now consider (13:3). Using the terminology of 13.3.3. 
the left-hand side of (13:3) is the maximum of the row minima and the 
right-hand side is the minimum of the column maxima. These two numbers 
are neither absolute maxima, nor absolute minima, and there is no prima 
fade evidence why they should be generally equal. Indeed, they are not. 
Two functions for which they are different are given in Figs. 12, 13. A 



94 



ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 



function for which they are equal is given in Fig. 14. (All these figures 
should be read in the sense of the explanations of 13.3.3. and of Fig. 11.) 

These figures as well as the entire question of commutativity of Max 
and Min will play an essential role in the theory of zero-sum two-person 
games. Indeed, it will be seen that they represent certain games which 
are typical for some important possibilities in that theory (cf. 18.1.2.). 
But for the moment we want to discuss them on their own account, without 
any reference to those applications. 



t - s - 2 



t - a - 3 





1 


2 


row 








minima 


1 


1 


j 


j 


2 


-1 


1 


-1 


column 


1 


1 




maxima 









Maximum of row minima 1 

Minimum of column maxima 1 

Figure 12. 





1 


2 


3 


row 
minima 


1 





-1 


1 


-1 


2 


1 





-1 


-1 


3 


-1 


1 





-1 


column 


1 


1 


1 




maxima 











Maximum of row minima 1 
Minimum of column maxima 1 
Figure 13. 



t -* -2 





1 


2 


row 








minima 


1 


-2 


1 


-2 


2 


-1 


2 


-1 


column 


-1 


2 




maxima 









Maximum of row minima 1 
Minimum of column maxima 1 
Figure 14. 

13.4.2. Since (13:3) is neither generally true, nor generally false, it is 
desirable to discuss the relationship of its two sides 

(13:4) Max* Min y </>(#, y) y Min y Max x </>(x, y), 

more fully. Figs. 12-14, which illustrated the behavior of (13:3) to a 
certain degree, give some clues as to what this behavior is likely to be. 

Specifically: 

(13 :A) In all three figures the left-hand side of (13:3) (i.e. the first 

expression of (13:4)) is ^ the right-hand side of (13:3) (i.e. the 
second expression in (13:4)). 



FUNCTIONAL CALCULUS 95 

(13 :B) In Fig. 14 where (13:3) is true there exists a field in the 

matrix which contains simultaneously the minimum of its row 
and the maximum of its column. (This happens to be the ele- 
ment 1 the left lower corner field of the matrix.) In the 
other figures 12, 13, where (13:3) is not true, there exists no 
such field. 

It is appropriate to introduce a general concept which describes the 
behavior of the field mentioned in (13 :B). We define accordingly: 

Let <f>(x, y) be any two-variable function. Then x , 3/0 is a saddle point 
of <f> if at the same time </>(x, y ) assumes its maximum at x = x and <(x , y) 
assumes its minimum at y = 3/0- 

The reason for the use of the name saddle point is this: Imagine the 
matrix of all x, y elements (x = 1, ,, y = 1, a; cf. Fig. 11) 
as an oreographical map, the height of the mountain over the field x, y 
being the value of <t>(x, y) there. Then the definition of a saddle point 
x , 2/0 describes indeed essentially a saddle or pass at that point (i.e. over the 
field xo, 2/0) ; the row XQ is the ridge of the mountain, and the column i/o is 
the road (from valley to valley) which crosses this ridge. 

The formula (13:C*) in 13.5.2. also falls in with this interpretation. 1 
13.4.3. Figs. 12, 13 show that a <f> may have no saddle points at all. 
On the other hand it is conceivable that < possesses several saddle points. 
But all saddle points x , 2/0 i? they exist at all must furnish the same 
value 0(x , 2/0)- 2 We denote this value if it exists at all by Sa x/v <(x, y), 
the saddle value of </>(x, y). 8 

We now formulate the theorems which generalize the indications of 
(13 :A), (13 :B). We denote them by (13 :A*), (13 :B*), and emphasize 
that they are valid for all functions <(x, y). 

(13 :A*) Always 

Max, Min y <(x, y) ^ Min y Max, #(x, y). 
(13 :B*) We have 

Max* Min y <(x, y) = Mm y Max z </>(x, y) 
if and only if a saddle point x , t/o of <#> exists. 

13.5. Proofs o! the Main Facts 

13.5.1. We define first two sets A*, B+ for every function <(x, 2/)- 
Min y <t>(x, 2/) is a function of x; let A+ be the set of all those x for which 
1 All this is closely connected with although not precisely a special case of; certain 
more general mathematical theories involving extremal problems, calculus of variations, 
etc. Cf. M . Morse: The Critical Points of Functions and the Calculus of Variations in 
the Large, Bull. Am. Math. Society, Jan .-Feb. 1929, pp. 38 cont., and What is Analysis in 
the Large?, Am. Math. Monthly, Vol. XLIX, 1942, pp. 358 cont. 

1 This follows from (13 :C*) in 13.5.2. There exists an equally simple direct proof: 
Consider two saddle points a? , y o, say 4, yj and 4', yi'. Then : 

'*) - Max, *(*, y'o) fc *(*", vl) Min, *(*' ', y) 



i.e.: +(*;, yi) <^x' ', j/ '). Similarly *(*' ', y' ') +(*;, yj). 
Hence 0(4, yi) - 0(4', yi'). 

1 Clearly the operation Sa/ V 0(x, y) kills both variables x } y. Cf. 13.2.3. 



96 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

this function assumes its maximum at x = XQ. Max, 4>(x, y) is a function 
of y ; let B+ be the set of all those y for which this function assumes its mini- 
mum at y = 2/0. 

We now prove (13:A*), (13:B*). 

Proof of (13 :A*) : Choose X Q in A+ and y in B*. Then 



Max* Min y <l>(x, y) = Min y <(zo, y) ^ <(zo, 2/0) 

g Max, <f>(x, 2/0) = Min y Max* <t>(x, y), 

i.e. : Max, Min y <f>(x, y) ^ Min y Max, <t>(x, y) as desired. 

Proof of the necessity of the existence of a saddle point in (13:B*): 
Assume that 

Max, Min y <t>(x, y) = Min y Max, <t>(x, y). 
Choose XQ in A* and yo in 5*; then we have 



Max, <(z, 2/0) = Min y Max, <t>(x, y) 

= Max, Min y <f>(x, y) = Min y 



y 
Hence for every x f 

g Max, <l>(x, y<>) = Min 



i.e. <t>(x , i/o) ^ </>(x', 2/0) so </>(z, 2/o) assumes its maximum at x = x . 
And for every 2/' 

y') ^ Min y ^(a: , y) = Max, </>(x, 2/0) ^ *(^o, 2/o), 



i.e. 0(x , 2/0) ^ *(^o, 2/0 so *(^o, 2/) assumes its minimum at y = 2/0. 

Consequently these XD, 2/0 form a saddle point. 

Proof of the sufficiency of the existence of a saddle point in (13:B*): 
Let XQ, 2/0 be a saddle point. Then 



Max, Min y </>(z, y) ^ Min y </>(z , 2/) = *(^o, 2/o), 
Min y Max, <f>(x, y) ^ Max, <t>(x, 2/0) = </>(z , t/o), 
hence 

Max, Min y <^(a:, y) ^ *(z , 2/0) ^ Min y Max, 0(z, 2/). 

Combining this with (13 :A*) gives 

Max, Min y <t>(x, y) = <t>(x , 2/0) = Min y Max, <t>(x, y), 

and hence the desired equation. 

13.5.2. The considerations of 13.5.1. yield some further results which 
are worth noting. We assume now the existence of saddle points, i.e. 
the validity of the equation of (13 :B*). 

For every saddle point a; , yo 



(13:C*) 0(x , 2/0) = Max, Min y <t>(x, y) = Min y Max, <t>(x, y). 

Proof: This coincides with the last equation of the sufficiency proof of 
(13:B*) in 13.5.1. 



FUNCTIONAL CALCULUS 97 

(13 :D*) x , 2/0 is a saddle point if and only if x belongs to A* and yo 

belongs to B*. 1 

Proof of sufficiency: Let x belong to A* and y* belong to B+. Then the 
necessity proof of (13:B*) in 13.5.1. shows exactly that this x , yo is a saddle 
point. 

Proof of necessity: Let xo, 2/0 be a saddle point. We use (13 :C*). For 
every x' 

Min y 0(s', y) ^ Max, Min y <t>(x, y) = <t>(x Q , y<>) = Min y 4>(z<>, y), 

i.e. Min y <(x , t/) ^ Min y <(x', i/) so Min y <(x, y) assumes its maximum 
at x = x . Hence x belongs to A+. Similarly for every y' 

Max* <(>(x, i/O ^ Min y Max* <(x, y) = ^(x 0| j/o) = Max* 0(x, 2/0), 

i.e. Max x <(x, 2/0) ^ Max z <t>(x, y') so Max* 0(x, y) assumes its minimum 
at y = I/O- Hence y belongs to B*. This completes the proof. 

The theorems (13:C*) ; (13:D*) indicate, by the way, the limitations 
of the analogy described at the end of 13.4.2.; i.e. they show that our con- 
cept of a saddle point is narrower than the everyday (oreographical) idea 
of a saddle or a pass. Indeed, (13 :C*) states that all saddles provided 
that they exist are at the same altitude. And (13 :D*) states if we depict 
the sets A*, B+ as two intervals of numbers 2 that all saddles together are 
an area which has the form of a rectangular plateau. 8 

13.5.3. We conclude this section by proving the existence of a saddle 
point for a special kind of x, y and <(x, y). This special case will be seen 
to be of a not inconsiderable generality. Let a function ^(x, u) of two 
variables x, u be given. We consider all functions /(x) of the variable 
which have values in the domain of u. Now we keep the variable x but 
in place of the variable u we use the function / itself. 4 The expression 
lK*/(z)) is determined by x,/; hence we may treat ^(x,/(ar)) as a function of 
the variables x, / and let it take the place of <(x, y}. 

We wish to prove that for these x, / and ^(x, /(x)) in place of x, y 
and <f>(x y y) a saddle point exists; i.e. that 

(13 :E) Max x Min/ ^(x, /(x)) = Min/ Max x f(x, /(x)). 



Proof: For every x choose a UQ with ^(x, u ) = Min u ^(x, w). This w 
depends on x, hence we can define a function / by w = /o(z). Thus 
^/(x, /o(z)) = Min M ^(x, u). Consequently 

Max* ^(x, /o(x)) = Max* Min u ^(x, u). 

1 Only under our hypothesis at the beginning of this section! Otherwise there exist 
no saddle points at all. 

1 If the x, y are positive integers, then this can certainly be brought about by two 
appropriate permutations of their domain. 

3 The general mathematical concepts alluded to in footnote 1 on p. 95 are free from 
these limitations. They correspond precisely to the everyday idea of a pass. 

4 The reader is asked to visualize this: Although itself a function, / may perfectly well 
be the variable of another function. 



98 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

A fortiori, 

(13 :F) Min/ Max, f(x, /(*)) ^ Max* Min u f(x, u). 



Now Min/ ^(z, f(x)) is the same thing as Min tt \(/(x y u) since / enters into 
this expression only via its value at the one place x, i.e. f(x), for which we 
may write u. So Min/ \l/(x, f(x)) = Min M ^(x, w) and consequently, 



(13 :G) Max* Min/ $(x, /(#)) = Max x Min M ^(z, u). 

(13:F), (13:G) together establish the validity of a ^ in (13:E). The ^ 
in (13 :E) holds owing to (13 :A*). Hence we have = in (13 :E), i.e. the 
proof is completed. 

14. Strictly Determined Games 
14.1. Formulation of the Problem 

14.1.1. We now proceed to the consideration of the zero-sum two-person 
game. Again we begin by using the normalized form. 

According to this the game consists of two moves: Player 1 chooses a 
number TI =!, , 0i, player 2 chooses a number r 2 = !, , # 2 , each 
choice being made in complete ignorance of the other, and then players 
1 and 2 get the amounts 3Ci(ri, r 2 ) and 3C 2 (Ti, T 2 ), respectively. 1 

Since the game is zero-sum, we have, by 11.4. 

3Ci(Ti, TI) + JC(T,, TI) = 0. 
We prefer to express this by writing 

3Cl(Ti, T 2 ) 35 3C(Ti, Tl), JCl(Ti, T 2 ) = -JC^i, T 2 ). 

We shall now attempt to understand how the obvious desires of the 
players 1, 2 will determine the events, i.e. the choices TI, r 2 . 

It must again be remembered, of course, that TI, r 2 stand ultima analysi 
not for a choice (in a move) but for the players' strategies; i.e. their entire 
"theory" or "plan" concerning the game. 

For the moment we leave it at that. Subsequently we shall also go 
"behind" the TI, T 2 and analyze the course of a play. 

14.1.2. The desires of the players 1, 2, are simple enough. I wishes 
to make 5Ci(ri, T 2 ) s= JC(TI, T 2 ) a maximum, 2 wishes to make 3C 2 (Ti, T 2 ) s 
#C(TI, T 2 ) a maximum; i.e. 1 wants to maximize and 2 wants to minimize 
3C(n, T t ). 

So the interests of the two players concentrate on the same object: the 
one function 3C(Ti, T 2 ). But their intentions are as is to be expected in a 
zero-sum two-person game exactly opposite : 1 wants to maximize, 2 wants 
to minimize. Now the peculiar difficulty in all this is that neither player 
has full control of the object of his endeavor of 3C(ri, T 2 ) i.e. of both 
its variables TI, T 2 . 1 wants to maximize, but he controls only TI; 2 wants to 
minimize, but he controls only T 2 : What is going to happen? 

l Cf. (ll:D)in 11.2.3. 



STRICTLY DETERMINED GAMES 



99 



The difficulty is that no particular choice of, say TI, need in itself make 
3C(ri, r 2 ) either great or small. The influence of r\ on 3C(ri, r 2 ) is, in general, 
no definite thing; it becomes that only in conjunction with the choice of 
the other variable, in this case r 2 . (Cf. the corresponding difficulty in 
economics as discussed in 2.2.3.) 

Observe that from the point of view of the player 1 who chooses a 
variable, say n, the other variable can certainly not be considered as a 
chance event. The other variable, in this case r 2 , is dependent upon the 
will of the other player, which must be regarded in the same light of " ration- 
ality " as one's own. (Cf. also the end of 2.2.3. and 2.2.4.) 

14.1.3. At this point it is convenient to make use of the graphical 
representation developed in 13.3.3. We represent 3C(ri, r 2 ) by a rectangular 
matrix: We form a rectangle of pi rows and 2 columns, using the number 
n = 1, , #1 to enumerate the former, and the number r 2 = 1, , 2 
to enumerate the latter; and into the field n, r 2 we write the matrix element 
3C(ri, r 2 ). (Cf. with Figure 11 in 13.3.3. The </>, x, y, t, s there correspond 
to our OC, TI, r 2 , 01, 2 (Figure 15).) 





1 


2 




7>2 





















1 


3C(1, 1) 


JC(1, 2) 




3C(1 rj) 




3C(1. 00 
















2 


3C(2, 1) 


3C(2, 2) 




3C(2, T 2 ) 




3C(2, 0) 






























7-1 


3C(ri, 1) 


3C(n, 2) 




3C(T1, T) 




3C(n, 2 ) 






























0i 


C(0i, 1) 


JC(0i, 2) 




3C(#i. n) 




3C(0i, 0i) 

















Figure 15. 

It ought to be understood that the function 3C(ri, r 2 ) is subject to no 
restrictions whatsoever; i.e., we are free to choose it absolutely at will. 1 
Indeed, any given function 5C(ri, r 2 ) defines a zero-sum two-person game 
in the sense of (11 :D) of 11.2.3. by simply defining 

3Ci(T!, T 2 ) s JC(TI, r 2 ), 3C 2 (ri, r 2 ) s -3C(ri, r 2 ) 

(cf. 14.1.1.). The desires of the players 1, 2, as described above in the 
last section, can now be visualized as follows: Both players are solely 



1 The domain, of course, is prescribed: It consists of all pairs n, TI with n 1, , 
; n = 1, , 0t. This is a finite set, so all Max and Min exist, cf. the end of 13.2.1. 



100 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

interested in the value of the matrix element JC(ri, r 2 ). Player 1 tries to 
maximize it, but he controls only the row, i.e. the number n. Player 2 
tries to minimize it, but he controls only the column, i.e. the number r 2 . 

We must now attempt to find a satisfactory interpretation for the out- 
come of this peculiar tug-of-war. 1 

14.2. The Minorant and the Majorant Gaifces 

14.2. Instead of attempting a direct attack on the game F itself for 
which we are not yet prepared let us consider two other games, which are 
closely connected with F and the discussion of which is immediately feasible. 

The difficulty in analyzing F is clearly that the player 1, in choosing n 
does not know what choice r 2 of the player 2 he is going to face and vice 
versa. Let us therefore compare F with other games where this difficulty 
does not arise. 

We define first a game Fi, which agrees with F in every detail except that 
player 1 has to make his choice of TI before player 2 makes his choice of 
T 2 , and that player 2 makes his choice in full knowledge of the value given 
by player 1 to TI (i.e. Ts move is preliminary to 2's move). 2 In this game 
Fi player 1 is obviously at a disadvantage as compared to his position 
in the original game F. We shall therefore call Fi the minor ant game of F. 

We define similarly a second game F 2 which again agrees with F in every 
detail except that now player 2 has to make his choice of r 2 before player 1 
makes his choice of r\ and that 1 makes his choice in full knowledge 
of the value given by 2 to r 2 (i.e. 2's move is preliminary to 1's move). 3 In 
this game F 2 the player 1 is obviously at an advantage as compared to 
his position in the game F. We shall therefore call F 2 the majorant game 
of F. 

The introduction of these two games FI, F 2 achieves this: It ought to 
be evident by common sense and we shall also establish it by an exact 
discussion that for FI, F 2 the "best way of playing" i.e. the concept of 
rational behavior has a clear meaning. On the other hand, the game F 
lies clearly "between" the two games FI, F 2 ; e.g. from 1's point of view FI 
is always less and F 2 is always more advantageous than F. 4 Thus FI, F 2 
may be expected to provide lower and upper bounds for the significant 
quantities concerning F. We shall, of course, discuss all this in an entirely 
precise form. A priori, these "bounds" could differ widely and leave a 
considerable uncertainty as to the understanding of F. Indeed, prima fade 
this will seem to be the case for many games. But we shall succeed in 
manipulating this technique in such a way by the introduction of certain 

1 The point is, of course, that this is not a tug-of-war. The two players have opposite 
interests, but the means by which they have to promote them are not in opposition to 
each other. On the contrary, these " means " i.e. the choices of n, TJ are apparently 
independent. This discrepancy characterizes the entire problem. 

1 Thus Ti while extremely simple is no longer in the normalized form. 

* Thus TI while extremely simple is no longer in the normalized form. 

4 Of course, to be precise we should say "less than or equal to" instead of "less," and 
"more than or equal to" instead of "more." 



STRICTLY DETERMINED GAMES 101 

further devices as to obtain in the end a precise theory of F, which gives 
complete answers to all questions. 

14.3. Discussion of the Auxiliary Games 

14.3.1. Let us first consider the minorant game IV After player 1 
has made his choice TI the player 2 makes his choice T 2 in full knowledge 
of the value of n. Since 2's desire is to minimize JC(ri, T 2 ), it is certain that 
he will choose T 2 so as to make the value of 5C(ri, r 2 ) a minimum for this TI. 
In other words: When 1 chooses a particular value of TI he can already foresee 
with certainty what the value of 3C(ri, r 2 ) will be. This will be Min Tj X(TI, r 2 ). l 
This is a function of TI alone. Now 1 wishes to maximize 3C(ri, r 2 ) and 
since his choice of TI is conducive to the value Min Ta 3C(ri, r 2 ) which depends 
on TI only, and not at all on T 2 so he will choose TI so as to maximize 
Min Tj JC(TI, T 2 ). Thus the value of this quantity will finally be 



Tf Min Tj JC(TI, T 2 ). 2 
Summing up: 

(14:A:a) The good way (strategy) for 1 to play the minorant game 

T i is to choose TI, belonging to the set A, A being the set of 
those TI for which Min Tj 3C(n, T 2 ) assumes its maximum value 
Max Tj Min, t OC(TI, T 2 ). 

(14:A:b) The good way (strategy) for 2 to play is this: If 1 has 

chosen a definite value of TI, S then T 2 should be chosen belong- 
ing to the set B r ^ B Ti being the set of those T 2 for which 
3C(ri, T 2 ) assumes its minimum value Min Tj 3C(n, T 2 ). 4 

On the basis of this we can state further: 

(14:A:c) If both players 1 and 2 play the minorant game Fj well, 

i.e. if TI belongs to A and T 2 belongs to B Ti then the value of 
JC(TI, T 2 ) will be equal to 

vi = Max Tj Min Tj JC(TI, T 2 ). 

1 Observe that TZ may not be uniquely determined: For a given n the T2-function 
3C(ri, T2) may assume its Tj-mmimum for several values of T^ The value of 3C(n, T2) 
will, however, be the same for all these T2, namely the uniquely defined minimum value 
Minr t 3C(n,ri). (Cf. 13.2.1.) 

2 For the same reason as in footnote 1 above, the value of n may not be unique, but the 
value of Min Tf 3C(ri, ri) is the same for all n in question, namely the uniquely-defined 
maximum value 

Max Tl Min Tl 3C(n r 2 ). 

8 2 is informed of the value of n when called upon to make his choice of r 2 , this is 
the rule of PI. It follows from our concept of a strategy (cf. 4.1.2. and end of 11.1.1.) 
that at this point a rule must be provided for 2's choice of T2 for every value of n, irre- 
spective of whether 1 has played well or not, i.e. whether or not the value chosen belongs 
to A. 

4 In all, this n is treated as a known parameter on which everything depends, includ- 
ing the set Br t from which n ought to be chosen. 



102 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

The truth of the above assertion is immediately established in the mathe- 
matical sense by remembering the definitions of the sets A and B V and by 
substituting accordingly in the assertion. We leave this exercise which 
is nothing but the classical operation of " substituting the defining for the 
defined" to the reader. Moreover, the statement ought to be clear by 
common sense. 

The entire discussion should make it clear that every play of the game 
Fi has a definite value for each player. This value is the above Vi for the 
player 1 and therefore Vi for the player 2. 

An even more detailed idea of the significance of Vi is obtained in this 
way: 

(14:A:d) Player 1 can, by playing appropriately, secure for himself 

a gain ^ Vi irrespective of what player 2 does. Player 2 
can, by playing appropriately, secure for himself a gain ^ Vi, 
irrespective of what player 1 does. 

(Proof: The former obtains by any choice of TI in A. The latter obtains 
by any choice of T^ in B T .* Again we leave the details to the reader; they 
are altogether trivial.) 

The above can be stated equivalently thus: 

(14:A:e) Player 2 can, by playing appropriately, make it sure that 

the gain of player 1 is ^ Vi, i.e. prevent him from gaming 
> Vi irrespective of what player 1 does. Player 1 can, by play- 
ing appropriately, make it sure that the gain of player 2 is 
g Vi, i.e. prevent him from gaining > Vi irrespective of 
what player 2 does. 

14.3.2. We have carried out the discussion of FI in rather profuse detail 
although the " solution" is a rather obvious one. That is, it is very likely 
that anybody with a clear vision of the situation will easily reach the same 
conclusions "unmathematically," just by exercise of common sense. 
Nevertheless we felt it necessary to discuss this case so minutely because 
it is a prototype of several others to follow where the situation will be much 
less open to " unmathematical " vision. Also, all essential elements of 
complication as well as the bases for overcoming them are really present 
in this very simplest case. By seeing their respective positions clearly 
in this case, it will be possible to visualize them in the subsequent, more 
complicated, ones. And it will be possible, in this way only, to judge 
precisely how much can be achieved by every particular measure. 

14.3.3. Let us now consider the majorant game F2. 

F2 differs from Fi only in that the roles of players 1 and 2 are inter- 
changed : Now player 2 must make his choice r 2 first and then the player 1 
makes his choice of r } in full knowledge of the value of r 2 . 

1 Recall that n must be chosen without knowledge of r 2 , while r 2 is chosen in full 
knowledge of n. 



STRICTLY DETERMINED GAMES 103 

But in saying that F 2 arises from FI by interchanging the players 1 and 2, 
it must be remembered that these players conserve in the process their 
respective functions 3Ci(ri, r 2 ), aC 2 (rj, r 2 ), i.e. 3C(ri, r 2 ), 3C(ri, r 2 ). That 
is, 1 still desires to maximize and 2 still desires to minimize X(TI, r 2 ). 

These being understood, we can leave the practically literal repetition 
of the considerations of 14.3.1. to the reader. We confine ourselves to 
restating the significant definitions, in the form in which they apply to F 2 . 

(14:B:a) The good way (strategy) for 2 to play the majorant game 

F 2 is to choose r 2 belonging to the set JB, B being the set of 
those r 2 for which Max Tf 3C(ri, r 2 ) assumes its minimum value 
Min Tj Max Tj X(TI, r 2 ). 

(14:B:b) The good way (strategy) for 1 to play is this: If 2 has 

chosen a definite value of T 2 ,* then TI should be chosen belong- 
ing to the set A Ti , A T ^ being the set of those r\ for which 
3C(ri, r 2 ) assumes its maximum value Max Ti 3C(ri, r 2 ). 2 

On the basis of this we can state further: 

(14:B:c) If both players 1 and 2 play the majorant game F 2 well, 

i.e. if r 2 belongs to B and TI belongs to A Tj then the value of 
5C(ri, T 2 ) will be equal to 

v 2 = Min tt Max Ti 5C(ri, r 2 ). 



The entire discussion should make it clear that every play of the game 
F 2 has a definite value for each player. This value is the above v 2 for the 
player 1 and therefore v 2 for the player 2. 

In order to stress the symmetry of the entire arrangement, we repeat, 
mutatis mutandis, the considerations which concluded 14.3.1. They now 
serve to give a more detailed idea of the significance of v 2 . 

(14:B:d) Player 1 can, by playing appropriately, secure for himself 

a gain ^ v 2 , irrespective of what player 2 does. Player 2 
can, by playing appropriately, secure for himself a gain 
i v 2 , irrespective of what player 1 does. 

(Proof: The latter obtains by any choice of r 2 in B. The former obtains 
by any choice of TI in A T ^ Cf. with the proof, loc. cit.) 
The above can again be stated equivalently thus : 

(14:B:e) Player 2 can, by playing appropriately, make it sure 

that the gain of player 1 is g v 2 , i.e. prevent him from gaining 

1 1 is informed of the value of T* when called upon to make his choice of n this is the 
rule of r a (Cf. footnote 3 on p. 101). 

2 In all this r a is treated as a known parameter on which everything depends, including 
the set A T| from which n ought to be chosen. 

8 Remember that rj must be chosen without any knowledge of n, while n is chosen 
with full knowledge of TI. 



104 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

> v 2 , irrespective of what player 1 does. Player 1 can, by 
playing appropriately, make it sure that the gain of player 2 
is ^ v 2 , i.e. prevent him from gaining > v 2 , irrespective 
of what player 2 does. 

14.3.4. The discussions of Fi and F 2 , as given in 14.3.1. and 14.3.3., 
respectively, are in a relationship of symmetry or duality to each other; 
they obtain from each other, as was pointed out previously (at the begin- 
ning of 14.3.3.) by interchanging the roles of the players 1 and 2. In itself 
neither game FI nor F 2 is symmetric with respect to this interchange; indeed, 
this is nothing but a restatement of the fact that the interchange of the 
players 1 and 2 also interchanges the two games Fi and F 2 , and so modifies 
both. It is in harmony with this that the various statements which we 
made in 14.3.1. and 14.3.3. concerning the good strategies of FI and F 2 , 
respectively i.e. (14:A:a), (l4:A:b), (14:B:a), (14:B:b), loc. cit. were 
not symmetric with respect to the players 1 and 2 either. Again we see: 
An interchange of the players 1 and 2 interchanges the pertinent definitions 
for Fi and F 2 , and so modifies both. 1 

It is therefore very remarkable that the characterization of the value 
of a play (vi for Fi, v 2 for F 2 ), as given at the end of 14.3.1 . and 14.3.3. i.e. 
(14:A:c), (14:A:d), (14:A:e), (14:B:c), (14:B:d), (14:B:e), loc. cit. (except 
for the formulae at the end of (14:A:c) and of (14:B:c)) are fully 
symmetric with respect to the players 1 and 2. According to what was 
said above, this is the same thing as asserting that these characterizations 
are stated exactly the same way for Fi and F 2 . 2 All this is, of course, equally 
clear by immediate inspection of the relevant passages. 

Thus we have succeeded in defining the value of a play in the same way 
for the games FI and F 2 , and symmetrically for the players 1 and 2: in 
(14:A:c), (14:A:d), (14:A:e), (14:B:c), (14:B:d) and (14:B:e) in 14.3.1. 
and in 14.3.3., this in spite of the fundamental difference of the individual 
role of each player in these two games. From this we derive the hope 
that the definition of the value of a play may be used in the same form for 
other games as well in particular for the game F which, as we know, 
occupies a middle position between FI and F 2 . This hope applies, of 
course, only to the concept of value itself, but not to the reasonings which 
lead to it; those were specific to Fi and F 2 , indeed different for Fi and for 
F 2 , and altogether impracticable for F itself; i.e., we expect for the future 
more from (14:A:d), (14:A:e), (14:B:d), (14:B:e) than from (14:A:a), 
(14:A:b), (14:B:a), (14:B:b). 

1 Observe that the original game T was symmetric with respect to the two players 
1 and 2, if we let each player take his function 3Ci(n, r a ), 3Cs(n, r 2 ) with him in an inter- 
change; i.e. the personal moves of 1 and 2 had both the same character in P. 

For a narrower concept of symmetry, where the functions 3Ci(n, T), JCs(ri, r) are 
held fixed, cf. 14.6. 

2 This point deserves careful consideration : Naturally these two characterizations 
must obtain from each other by interchanging the roles of the players 1 and 2. But in 
this case the statements coincide also directly when no interchange of the players is made 
at all. This is due to their individual symmetry. 



STRICTLY DETERMINED GAMES 105 

These are clearly only heuristic indications. Thus far we have not 
even attempted the proof that a numerical value of a play can be defined 
in this manner for F. We shall now begin the detailed discussion by which 
this gap will be filled. It will be seen that at first definite and serious 
difficulties seem to limit the applicability of this procedure, but that it will 
be possible to remove them by the introduction of a new device (Cf. 14.7.1. 
and 17.1.-17.3., respectively). 

14.4. Conclusions 

14.4.1. We have seen that a perfectly plausible interpretation of the 
value of a play determines this quantity as 

Vi = Max T( Min Tj OC(ri, r 2 ), 
v 2 = Min Tj Max Ti 3C(ri, r 2 ), 

for the games FI, F 2 , respectively, as far as the player 1 is concerned. 1 

Since the game FI is less advantageous for 1 than the game F 2 in FI 
he must make his move prior to, and in full view of, his adversary, while in 
F 2 the situation is reversed it is a reasonable conclusion that the value 
of Fi is less than, or equal to (i.e. certainly not greater than) the value of F 2 . 
One may argue whether this is a rigorous " proof." The question whether 
it is, is hard to decide, but at any rate a close analysis of the verbal argu- 
ment involved shows that it is entirely parallel to the mathematical proof 
of the same proposition which we already possess. Indeed, the proposition 
in question, 

Vi ^ V 2 

coincides with (13 :A*) in 13.4.3. (The tf>, x, y there correspond to our 

3C, TI, T 2 .) 

Instead of ascribing Vi, v 2 as values to two games FI and F 2 different 
from F we may alternatively correlate them with F itself, under suitable 
assumptions concerning the " intellect" of the players 1 and 2. 

Indeed, the rules of the game F prescribe that each player must make 
his choice (his personal move) in ignorance of the outcome of the choice 
of his adversary. It is nevertheless conceivable that one of the players, 
say 2, " finds out" his adversary; i.e., that he has somehow acquired the 
knowledge as to what his adversary's strategy is. 2 The basis for this 
knowledge does not concern us; it may (but need not) be experience from 
previous plays. At any rate we assume that the player 2 possesses this 
knowledge. It is possible, of course, that in this situation 1 will change 
his strategy; but again let us assume that, for any reason whatever, he 
does not do it. 8 Under these assumptions we may then say that player 2 
has " found out" his adversary. 

1 For player 2 the values are consequently vi, v. 

* In the game T which is in the normalized form the strategy is just the actual 
choice at the unique personal move of the player. Remember how this normalized form 
was derived from the original extensive form of the game; consequently it appears that 
this choice corresponds equally to the strategy in the original game. 

1 For an interpretation of all these assumptions! cf. 17.3.1. 



106 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

In this case, conditions in F become exactly the same as if the game were 
Fi, and hence all discussions of 14.3.1. apply literally. 

Similarly, we may visualize the opposite possibility, that player 1 has 
" found out" his adversary. Then conditions in F become exactly the same 
as if the game were F 2 ; and hence all discussions of 14.3.3. apply literally. 

In the light of the above we can say: 

The value of a play of the game F is a well-defined quantity if one of the 
following two extreme assumptions is made: Either that player 2 " finds 
out" his adversary, or that player 1 " finds out" his adversary. In the 
first case the value of a play is Vi for 1, and vi for 2; in the second case 
the value of a play is V2 for 1 and V2 for 2. 

14.4.2. This discussion shows that if the value of a play of F itself 
without any further qualifications or modifications can be defined at all, 
then it must lie between the values of Vi and v 2 . (We mean the values 
for the player 1.) I.e. if we write v for the hoped-for value of a play of F 
itself (for player 1), then there must be 

Vi 5jj V ^ V 2 . 

The length of this interval, which is still available for v, is 

A = v 2 Vi ^ 0. 

At the same time A expresses the advantage which is gained (in the 
game F) by "finding out" one's adversary instead of being " found out" 
by him. 1 

Now the game may be such that it does not matter which player " finds 
out" his opponent; i.e., that the advantage involved is zero. According 
to the above, this is the case if and only if 

A = 
or equivalently 

Vi = V 2 

Or, if we replace Vi, v 2 by their definitions: 

Max Tj Min Tj 3C(ri, r 2 ) = Min T2 Max Tj JC(TI, r 2 ). 



If the game F possesses these properties, then we call it strictly determined. 
The last form of this condition calls for comparison with (13:3) in 13.3.1. 
and with the discussions of 13. 4.1. -13. 5.2. (The 0, x, y there again corre- 
spond to our 3C, 7i, r 2 ). Indeed, the statement of (13:B*) in 13.4.3. says 
that the game F is strictly determined if and only if a saddle point of 
3C(ri, T 2 ) exists. 

14.5. Analysis of Strict Determinateness 

14.5.1. Let us assume the game F to be strictly determined; i.e. that a 
saddle point of 3C(ri, rj) exists. 

1 Observe that this expression for the advantage in question applies for both players: 
The advantage for the player 1 is v vi; for the player 2 it is ( ~vi) ( v 2 ) and these 
two expressions are equal to each other, i.e. to A. 



STRICTLY DETERMINED GAMES 107 

In this case it is to be hoped considering the analysis of 14.4.2. that 
it will be possible to interpret the quantity 

v = Vi = v 2 

as the value of a play of r (for the player 1). Recalling the definitions of 
Vi, v 2 and the definition of the saddle value in 13.4.3. and using (13:C*) in 
13.5.2., we see that the above equation may also be written as 

v = Max Ti Min Tj 3C(7i, r 2 ) == Min Tj Max^ OC(TI, r 2 ) 
= Sa r/rj 3C(ri, T 2 ). 

By retracing the steps made at the end of 14.3.1. and at the end of 14.3.3. 
it is indeed not difficult to establish that the above can be interpreted as 
the value of a play of F (for player 1). 

Specifically: (14:A:c), (14:A:d), (14:A:e), (14:B:c), (14:B:d), (14:B:e) 
of 14.3.1. and 14.3.3. where they apply to FI and F 2 respectively, can now 
be obtained for F itself. We restate first the equivalent of (14:A:d) and 
(14:B:d): 

(14:C:d) Player 1 can, by playing appropriately, secure for himself 

a gain ^ v, irrespective of what player 2 does. 

Player 2 can, by playing appropriately, secure for himself 
a gain ^ v irrespective of what player 1 does. 

In order to prove this, we form again the set A of (14:A:a) in 14.3.1. 
and the set B of (14:B:a) in 14.3.3. These are actually the sets A+, B+ of 
13.5.1. (the <t> corresponds to our 5C). We repeat: 

(14:D:a) A is the set of those TI for which Min Ta 3C(ri, r 2 ) assumes its 

maximum value; i.e. for which 

Min Ti JC(ri, T 2 ) = Max Tj Min rj 3C(n, r 2 ) = v. 

(14:D:b) B is the set of those r 2 for which Max Tj 3C(ri, r 2 ) assumes 

its minimum value; i.e. for which 

Max Ti 3C(ri, T 2 ) = Min Tj Max Ti JC(TI, n) = v. 

Now the demonstration of (14:C:d) is easy: 

Let player 1 choose TI from A. Then irrespective of what player 2 
does, i.e. for every r 2 , we have X(TI, r 2 ) ^ Min Tj JC(TI, r 2 ) = v, i.e., 1's gain 
is ^ v. 

Let player 2 choose r 2 from B. Then, irrespective of what player 1 
does, i.e. for every n, we have JC(n, r 2 ) ^ Max Tj 3C(ri y T 2 ) = v, i.e. 1's gain 
is ^ v and so 2*s gain is ^ v. 

This completes the proof. 

We pass now to the equivalent of (14:A:e) and (14:B:e). Indeed, 
(14:C:d) as formulated above can be equivalently formulated thus: 
(14:C:e) Player 2 can, by playing appropriately, make it sure that 

the gain of player 1 is : v, i.e. prevent him from gaining > v 
irrespective of what player 1 does. 



108 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

Player 1 can, by playing appropriately, make it sure thai 
the gain of player 2 is ^ v i.e. present him from gaining 
> v irrespective of what player 2 does. 

(14:C:d) and (14:C:e) establish satisfactorily our interpretation of v as the 
value of a play of T for the player 1, and of v for the player 2. 

14.5.2. We consider now the equivalents of (14:A:a), (14:A:b), (14:B:a), 
(14:B:b). 

Owing to (14:C:d) in 14.5.1. it is reasonable to define a good way for 1 
to play the game F as one which guarantees him a gain which is greater 
than or equal to the value of a play for 1, irrespective of what 2 does; i.e. a 
choice of TI for which X(TI, T 2 ) ^ v for all r 2 . This may be equivalently 
stated as Min Tj 3C(rj, r 2 ) ^ v. 

Now we have always Min Tf 3C(ri, T 2 ) ^ Max Ti Min Tj 3C(ri, r 2 ) = v. 

Hence the above condition for TI amounts to Min T 3C(ri, T 2 ) = v, i.e. 
(by (14:D:a) in 14.5.1.) to r\ being in A. 

Again, by (14:C:d) in 14.5.1. it is reasonable to define the good way for 
2 to play the game T as one which guarantees him a gain which is greater 
than or equal to the value of a play for 2, irrespective of what 1 does; i.e. 
a choice of r 2 for which 3C(ri, T 2 ) ^ v for all TI. That is, JC(TI, T 2 ) ^ v 
for all TI. This may be equivalently stated as Max Tj 5C(Ti, T Z ) ^ v. 

Now we have always Max Tj 3C(Ti, T 2 ) ^ Min Tj Max T OC(TI, T 2 ) = v. 
Hence the above conditions for T 2 amounts to Max Ti OC(TI, T 2 ) = v, i.e. (by 
(14:D:b) in 14.5.1.) to T 2 being in B. 

So we have: 

(14:C:a) The good way (strategy) for 1 to play the game F is to 

choose any TI belonging to A, A being the set of (14:D:a) in 

14.5.1. 
(14:C:b) The good way (strategy) for 2 to play the game F is to 

choose any T 2 belonging to B, B being the set of (14:D:b) 

in 14.5.1. 1 

Finally our definition of the good way of playing, as stated at the 
beginning of this section, yields immediately the equivalent of (14:A:c) 
or (14:B:c): 

(14:C:c) If both players 1 and 2 play the game F well i.e. if r\ 

belongs to A and T 2 belongs to B then the value of 3C(n, T 2 ) 
will be equal to the value of a play (for 1), i.e. to v. 

We add the observation that (13 :D*) in 13.5.2. and the remark concerning 
the sets A, B before (14:D:a), (14:D:b) in 14.5.1. together give this: 

(14:C:f) Both players 1 and 2 play the game F well i.e. TI belongs 

to A and T 2 belongs to B if and only if TI, T 2 is a saddle point 
of 3C(T,, T 2 ). 

1 Since this is the game F each player must make his choice (of n or r t ) without 
knowledge of the other player's choice (of TI or n). Contrast this with (14:A:b) in 
14.3.1. for Ti and with (14:B:b) in 14.3.3. fo* T f . 



STRICTLY DETERMINED GAMES 109 

14.6. The Interchange of Players. Symmetry 

14.6. (14:C:a)-(14:C:f) in 14.5.1. and 14.5.2. settle everything as far 
as the strictly determined two-person games are concerned. In this 
connection let us remark that in 14.3.1., 14.3.3. for Ti, T 2 we derived 
(14:A:d), (14:A:e), (14:B:d), (14:B:e) from (14:A:a), (14:A:b), (14:B:a), 
(14:B:b) while in 14.5.1., 14.5.2. for T itself we obtained (14:C:a), 
(14:C:b) from (14:C:d), (14:C:e). This is an advantage since the argu- 
ments of 14.3.1., 14.3.3. in favor of (14:A:a), (14:A:b), (14:B:a), (14:B:b) 
were of a much more heuristic character than those of 14.5.1., 14.5.2. in 
favor of (14:C:d), (14:C:e). 

Our use of the function 3C(ri, r 2 ) = 3Ci(ri, r 2 ) implies a certain asymmetry 
of the arrangement; the player 1 is thereby given a special role. It ought 
to be intuitively clear, however, that equivalent results would be obtained 
if we gave this special role to the player 2 instead. Since interchanging 
the players 1 and 2 will play a certain role later, we shall nevertheless give a 
brief mathematical discussion of this point also. 

Interchanging the players 1 and 2 in the game T of which we need 
not assume now that it is strictly determined amounts to replacing the 
functions 5Ci(ri, r 2 ), 3C 2 (ri, r 2 ) by 3C 2 (r 2 , TI), JCi(r 2 , ri). 1 - 2 It follows, there- 
fore, that this interchange means replacing the function 3C (r i, r 2 ) by 3C (r 2 , r i) . 

Now the change of sign has the effect of interchanging the operations 
Max and Min. Consequently the quantities 

Max Ti Min Tj OC(T], ? 2 ) = Vi, 
Min rf Max Ti 5C(ri, T 2 ) = v 2 , 

as defined in 14.4.1. become now 

Max Ti Min Tj [-3C(> 2 , TI)] = -Min Ti Max T| JC(r 2 , TI) 

= Min t| Max Ti JC(TI, r 2 ) 8 = v 2 . 
Min Tj Max Ti [ 3C(T 2 , TI)] = Max Tj Min Ti OC(r 2 , TI) 

= -Max Ti Min Tj JC(TI, T 2 ) 8 = -VL 

So Vi, v 2 become v 2 , Vi. 4 Hence the value of 

A = v 2 - Vi = (-Vi) - (-v 2 ) 

1 This is no longer the operation of interchanging the players used in 14.3.4. There 
we were only interested in the arrangement and the state of information at each move, 
and the players 1 and 2 were considered as taking their f unctions 3Ci(n, r 2 ) and 3Cj(ri, TI) 
with them (cf. footnote 1 on p. 104). In this sense r was symmetric, i.e. unaffected by 
that interchange (id.). 

At present we interchange the roles of the players 1 and 2 completely, even in their 
f unctions 3Ci(n, r a ) and 3C 2 (Ti, r 2 ). 

* We had to interchange the variables n, r t since r\ represents the choice of player 1 
and T2 the choice of player 2. Consequently it is now T which has the domain 1, , 0i. 
Thus it is again true for 3C*(r2, TI) as it was before for3C*(ri, TJ) that the variable before 
the comma has the domain 1, , ft and the variable after the comma, the domain 

1, , 02- 

3 This is a mere change of notations: The variables TI, r* are changed around to r s , TI. 

4 This is in harmony with footnote 1 on p. 105, as it should be. 



110 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

is unaffected, 1 and if F is strictly determined, it remains so, since this prop- 
erty is equivalent to A = 0. In this case v = Vi = v 2 becomes 

V = Vi = ~ V2. 

It is now easy to verify that all statements (14:C:a)-(14:C:f) in 14.5.1., 
14.5.2. remain the same when the players 1 and 2 are interchanged. 

14.7. N on -strictly Determined Games 

14.7.1. All this disposes completely of the strictly determined games, 
but of no others. For a game I which is not strictly determined we have 
A > i.e. in such a game it involves a positive advantage to "find out" 
one's adversary. Hence there is an essential difference between the 
results, i.e. the values in FI and in F 2 , and therefore also between the good 
ways of playing these games. The considerations of 14.3.1., 14.3.3. provide 
therefore no guidance for the treatment of F. Those of 14.5.1., 14.5.2. 
do not apply either, since they make use of the existence of saddle points 
of 3C(ri, r 2 ) and of the validity of 



Max Tj Min Tj JC(7 1, r 2 ) = Min Tj Max Ti 3C(ri, r 2 ), 



i.e. of F being strictly determined. There is, of course, some plausibility 
in the inequality at the beginning of 14.4.2. According to this, the value v 
of a play of F (for the player 1) if such a concept can be formed at all in 
this generality, for which we have no evidence as yet 2 is restricted by 

Vi g V g V2. 

But this still leaves an interval of length A = v 2 Vi > open to v; 
and, besides, the entire situation is conceptually most unsatisfactory. 

One might be inclined to give up altogether: Since there is a positive 
advantage in "finding out" one's opponent in such a game F, it seems 
plausible to say that there is no chance to find a solution unless one makes 
some definite assumption as to "who finds out whom," and to what extent. 3 

We shall see in 17. that this is not so, and that in spite of A > a solu- 
tion can be found along the same lines as before. But we propose first, 
without attacking that difficulty, to enumerate certain games F with A > 0, 
and others with A = 0. The first which are not strictly determined 
will be dealt with briefly now; their detailed investigation will be under- 
taken in 17.1. The second which are strictly determined will be ana- 
lyzed in considerable detail. 

14.7.2. Since there exist functions 3C(ri, r 2 ) without saddle points (cf. 
13.4.1., 13.4.2.; the 4>(x, y) there, is our 3C(ri, r 2 )) there exist not strictly 
determined games F. It is worth while to re-examine those examples i.e. 

1 This is in harmony with footnote 1 on p. 106, as it should be. 

2 Cf. however, 17.8.1. 

* In plainer language: A > means that it is not possible in this game for each player 
simultaneously to be cleverer than his opponent. Consequently it seems desirable to 
know just how clever each particular player is. 



STRICTLY DETERMINED GAMES 111 

the functions described by the matrices of Figs. 12, 13 on p. 94 in the 
light of our present application. That is, to describe explicitly the games 
to which they belong. (In each case, replace <t>(x, y) by our JC(TI, r a ), r 2 
being the column number and n the row number in every matrix. Cf. also 
Fig. 15 on p. 99). 

Fig. 12: This is the game of "Matching Pennies." Let for TI and for 
T 2 1 be "heads" and 2 be "tails," then the matrix element has the value 1 
if n, r 2 "match" i.e. are equal to each other and 1, if they do not. 
So player 1 "matches" player 2: He wins (one unit) if they "match" and 
he loses (one unit), if they do not. 

Fig. 13 : This is the game of "Stone, Paper, Scissors." Let for n and for 
r 2 1 be "stone," 2 be "paper," and 3 be "scissors." The distribution of 
elements 1 and 1 over the matrix expresses that "paper" defeats "stone," 
"scissors" defeat "paper," "stone" defeats "scissors." 1 Thus player 1 
wins (one unit) if he defeats player 2, and he loses (one unit) if he is defeated. 
Otherwise (if both players make the same choice) the game is tied. 

14.7.3. These two examples show the difficulties which we encounter 
in a not strictly determined game, in a particularly clear form; just because 
of their extreme simplicity the difficulty is perfectly isolated here, in vitro. 
The point is that in "Matching Pennies" and in "Stone, Paper, Scissors," 
any way of playing i.e. any TI or any T 2 is just as good as any other: 
There is no intrinsic advantage or disadvantage in "heads" or in "tails" 
per se, nor in "stone," "paper" or "scissors" per se. The only thing which 
matters is to guess correctly what the adversary is going to do; but how are 
we going to describe that without further assumptions about the players' 
"intellects"? 2 

There are, of course, more complicated games which are not strictly 
determined and which are important from various more subtle, technical 
viewpoints (cf. 18., 19.). But as far as the main difficulty is concerned, 
the simple games of "Matching Pennies" and of "Stone, Paper, Scissors" 
are perfectly characteristic. 

14.8. Program of a Detailed Analysis of Strict Determinateness 

14.8. While the strictly determined games T for which our solution 
is valid are thus a special case only, one should not underestimate the size 
of the territory they cover. The fact that we are using the normalized 
form for the game F may tempt to such an underestimation: It makes things 
look more elementary than they really are. One must remember that the 
TI, T 2 represent strategies in the extensive form of the game, which may be 
of a very complicated structure, as mentioned in 14.1.1. 

In order to understand the meaning of strict determinateness, it is 
therefore necessary to investigate it in relation to the extensive form of the 
game. This brings up questions concerning the detailed nature of the moves, 

1 " Paper covers the stone, scissors cut the paper, stone grinds the scissors." 

2 As mentioned before, we shall show in 17.1. that it can be done. 



112 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

chance or personal the state of information of the players, etc. ; i.e. we 
come to the structural analysis based on the extensive form, as mentioned 
in 12.1.1. 

We are particularly interested in those games in which each player who 
makes a personal move is perfectly informed about the outcome of the 
choices of all anterior moves. These games were already mentioned in 
6.4.1. and it was stated there that they are generally considered to be of a 
particular rational character. We shall now establish this in a precise 
sense, by proving that all such games are strictly determined. And this 
will be true not only when all moves are personal, but also when chance 
moves too are present. 

15. Games with Perfect Information 
15.1. Statement of Purpose. Induction 

15.1.1. We wish to investigate the zero-sum two-person games somewhat 
further, with the purpose of finding as wide a subclass among them as 
possible in which only strictly determined games occur; i.e. where the 
quantities 

vi = Max Tj Min Tt 3C(ri, r 2 ), 
v 2 = Min Tj Max Ti JC(TI, r 2 ) 

of 14.4.1. which turned out to be so important for the appraisal of the 
game fulfill 

Vi = V 2 = V. 

We shall show that when perfect information prevails in F i.e. when 
preliminarity is equivalent to anteriority (cf. 6.4.1. and the end of 14.8.) 
then F is strictly determined. We shall also discuss the conceptual sig- 
nificance of this result (cf. 15.8.). Indeed, we shall obtain this as a special 
case of a more general rule concerning vi, v 2 , (cf. 15.5.3.). 

We begin our discussions in even greater generality, by considering a 
perfectly unrestricted general n-person game T. The greater generality 
will be useful in a subsequent instance. 

15.1.2. Let T be a general n-person game, given in its extensive form. 
We shall consider certain aspects of F, first in our original pre-set-theoretical 
terminology of 6., 7., (cf. 15.1.), and then translate everything into the par- 
tition and set terminology of 9., 10. (cf. 15.2., et sequ.). The reader will 
probably obtain a full understanding with the help of the first discussion 
alone; and the second, with its rather formalistic machinery, is only under- 
taken for the sake of absolute rigor, in order to show that we are really 
proceeding strictly on the basis of our axioms of 10.1.1. 

We consider the sequence of all moves in F: SfTli, 3T1 2 , , 3TI,,. Let 
us fix our attention on the first move, 9Tli, and the situation which exists 
at the moment of this move. 

Since nothing is anterior to this move, nothing is preliminary to it 
either; i.e. the characteristics of this move depend on nothing, they are 
constants. This applies in the first place to the fact, whether 9fRi is a chance 



GAMES WITH PERFECT INFORMATION 113 

move or a personal move ; and in the latter case, to which player 9fTli belongs, 
i.e. to the value of fci = 0, 1, , n respectively, in the sense of 6.2.1. 
And it applies also to the number of alternatives a\ at 3fTCi and for a chance 
move (i.e. when fci = 0) to the values of the probabilities pi(l), , p\(ct\). 
The result of the choice at Sflli chance or personal is a <TI = 1, , a\. 

Now a plausible step suggests itself for the mathematical analysis 
of the game T, which is entirely in the spirit of the method of "complete 
induction" widely used in all branches of mathematics. It replaces, if 
successful, the analysis of T by the analysis of other games which contain 
one move less than T. 1 This step consists in choosing a *i = 1, , cm 
and denoting by T 9i a game which agrees with F in every detail except that 
the move 9Tli is omitted, and instead the choice <n is dictated (by the rules 
of the new game) the value ai = 9\* T 9i has, indeed, one move less than 
F : Its moves are 9TC 2 , * * , 3TI,. 3 And our " inductive " step will have been 
successful if we can derive the essential characteristics of F from those of 
all r fi , *i = 1, , i. 

15.1.3. It must be noted, however, that the possibilities of forming 
F i are dependent upon a certain restriction on F. Indeed, every player 
who makes a certain personal move in the game T 9i must be fully informed 
about the rules of this game. Now this knowledge consists of the knowledge 
of the rules of the original game F plus the value of the dictated choice at 
SfTli, i.e. 9 1. Hence T 9i can be formed out of F without modifying the rules 
which govern the player's state of information in F only if the outcome 
of the choice at SfTli, by virtue of the original rules F, is known to every 
player at any personal move of his 3TC2, , 9TI,; i.e. 9fRi must be prelim- 
inary to all personal moves 9dl 2 , , 311,. We restate this: 

(15:A) T 9i can be formed without essentially modifying the 

structure of F for that purpose only if F possess the following 
property : 

(15:A:a) SfTli is preliminary to all personal moves 9Tl2, * , 9Rr. 4 

1 I.e. have v I instead of v. Repeated application of this "inductive" step if 
feasible at all will reduce the game T to one with steps; i.e. to one of fixed, unalterable 
outcome. And this means, of course, a complete solution for r. (Cf. (15:C:a) in 15.6.1.) 

* E.g. F is the game of Chess, and a\ a particular opening move i.e. choice at Dili of 
"white," i.e. player 1. Then r^ is again Chess, but beginning with a move of the char- 
acter of the second move in ordinary Chess a "black," player 2 and in the position 
created by the "opening move" a\. This dictated "opening move" may, but need not, 
be a conventional one (like E2-E4). 

The same operation is exemplified by forms of Tournament Bridge where the 
"umpires" assign the players definite known and previously selected "hands." 
(This is done, e.g., in Duplicate Bridge.) 

In the first example, the dictated move 9TCi was originally personal (of "white," 
player 1); in the second example it was originally chance (the "deal"). 

In some games occasionally "handicaps" are used which amount to one or more 
such operations. 

* We should really use the indices 1, , v 1 and indicate the dependence on 9\\ 
e.g. by writing SJTlf 1 , , 3Hji,. But we prefer the simpler notation 3fRj, , STl*. 

4 This is the terminology of 6.3. ; i.e. we use the special form of dependence in the 
sense of 7.2.1. Using the general description of 7.2.1. we must state (15:A:a) like this: 
For every personal move 31k, * 2, , r, the set * contains the function <n. 



114 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

15.2. The Exact Condition (First Step) 

16.2.1. We now translate 15.1.2., 15.1.3. into the partition and set 
terminology of 9., 10., (cf. also the beginning of 15.1.2.). The notations of 
10.1. will therefore be used. 

di consists of the one set 12 ((10:1 :f) in 10.1.1.), and it is a subpartition 
of (&i ((10:1 :a) in 10.1.1.); hence (Bi too consists of the one set ft (the others 
being empty) . ** That is : 

12 for precisely one fc, say k = fci, 
for all fc ?^ fci. 

This fci = 0, 1, , n determines the character of OTij it is the fci of 6.2.1. 
If fci = 1, , n i.e. if the move is personal then &i is also a subpar- 
tition of a)i(fci), ((10:1 :d) in 10.1.1. This was only postulated within 5i(fci), 
but Bi(ki) = 12). Hence SDi(fci) too consists of the one set 12. 3 And for 
fc 7* fc], the >i(fc) which is a partition in Bi(fc) = ((10:A:g) in 10.1.1.) 
must be empty. 

So we have precisely one AI of Cti, which is 12, and for fci = 1, , n 
precisely one Di in all SDi(fc), which is also 12; while for fci = there are no 
Di in all >j(fc). 

The move 3TZi consists of the choice of a Ci from Ci(fcj); by chance if 
fci = 0; by the player fci if fci = 1, , n. C\ is automatically a subset 
of the unique A\( = 12) in the former case, and of the unique DI(= 12) 
in the latter. The number of these Ci is c*i (cf. 9.1.5., particularly footnote 2 
on p. 70); and since the AI or DI in question is fixed, this a\ is a definite 
constant, ai is the number of alternatives at 'JTli, the a\ of 6.2.1. and 15.1.2. 

These Ci correspond to the a\ = 1, , a\ of 15.1.2., and we denote 
them accordingly by Ci(l), , Ci(ai). 4 Now (10:1 :h) in 10.1.1. shows 
as is readily verified that Ct 2 is also the set of the Ci(l), , Ci(ai), i.e. 
equal to d. 

So far our analysis has been perfectly general, valid for m\ (and to a 
certain extent for ffil 2 ) of any game F. The reader should translate these 
properties into everyday terminology in the sense of 8.4.2. and 10.4.2. 

We pass now to iy. This should obtain from F by dictating the move 
Sflli as described in 15.1.2. by putting <j\ = 9\. At the same time the 
moves of the game are restricted to 9fTl2, ' , STC,. This means that the 

1 This (Bi is an exception from (8:B:a) in 8.3.1.; cf. the remark concerning this (8:B:a) 
in footnote 1 on p. 63, and also footnote 4 on p. 69. 

8 Proof: ft belongs to Q,\, which is a subpartition of (Bij hence ft is a subset of an 
element of (Bi. This element is necessarily equal to ft. All other elements of (Bi are 
therefore disjunct from (cf. 8.3.1.), i.e. empty. 

s Cli, S)i(fci) unlike i (cf. above) must fulfill both (8:B:a), (8:B:b) in 8.3.1.; hence 
both have no further elements besides ft. 

4 They represent the alternatives Cti(l), , Cli(ai) of 6.2. and 9.1.4., 9.1.5. 



GAMES WITH PERFECT INFORMATION 115 

element w which represents the actual play can no longer vary over all 
ft, but is restricted to Ci(ffi). And the partitions enumerated in 9.2.1. are 
restricted to those with * = 2, , v, 1 (and K - v + 1 for Ct). 

15.2.2. We now come to the equivalent of the restriction of 15.1.3. 

The possibility of carrying out the changes formulated at the end of 
15.2.1. is dependent upon a certain restriction on F. 

As indicated, we wish to restrict the play i.e. v within Ci(fri). There- 
fore all those sets which figured in the description of F and which were 
subsets of Q, must be made over into subsets of C}(9\) and the partitions 
into partitions within Ci(ffi) (or within subsets of Ci(frj)). How is this to 
be done? 

The partitions which make up the descriptions of F (cf. 9.2.1.) fall into 
two classes: those which represent objective facts the Ct c , the (B = (S(0), 
J3,(l), , B K (n)) and the C<(fc), k = 0, 1, , n and those which 
represent only the player's state of information, 2 the ><(&), k = 1, ,n. 
We assume, of course K ^ 2 (cf. the end of 15.2.1.). 

In the first class of partitions we need only replace each element by 
its intersection with Ci(frj). Thus (B* is modified by replacing its ele- 
ments B,(0), B,(l), , B K (n) by C,(*,) n B.(0), Ci(*i) n B.(l), , 
Ci(fri) n B K (ri). In Ct< even this is not necessary: It is a subpartition of 
& 2 (since K *t 2, cf. 10.4.1.), i.e. of the system of pairwise disjunct sets 
(Ci(l), , Ci(i)) (cf. 15.2.1.); hence we keep only those elements of a, 
which are subsets of Ci(fri), i.e. that part of ft* which lies in Ci(fri). The 
Q*(k) should be treated like (B, but we prefer to postpone this discussion. 

In the second class of partitions i.e. for the )*(&) we cannot do any- 
thing like it. Replacing the elements of 3)(fc) by their intersections with 
Ci(fri) would involve a modification of a player's state of information 3 and 
should therefore be avoided. The only permissible procedure would be 
that which was feasible in the case of Ct K : replacement of >(&) by that 
part of itself which lies in Ci(fri). But this is applicable only if 33<(fc) like 
& before is a subpartition of ($2 (for K ^ 2). So we must postulate this. 

Now e(fc) takes care of itself: It is a subpartition of ^> K (k) ((10:1 :c) 
in 10.1.1.), hence of dz (by the above assumption); and so we can replace 
it by that part of itself which lies in C i(fri). 

So we see: The necessary restriction of F is that every D^fc) (with 
K ^ 2) must be a subpartition of ($2. Recall now the interpretation of 
8.4.2. and of (10:A:d*), (10:A:g*) in 10.1.2. They give to this restriction 
the meaning that every player at a personal move 9n 2 , , 9TC r is fully 

1 We do not wish to change the enumeration to K = 1, , v 1, cf. footnote 3 
on p. 113. 

2 a represents the umpire's state of information, but this is an objective fact: the 
events up to that moment have determined the course of the play precisely to that 
extent (cf. 9.1.2.). 

3 Namely, giving him additional information. 



116 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

informed about the state of things after the move SfTli (i.e. before the move 
9Hlj) expressed by & 2 . (Cf. also the discussion before (10:B) in 10.4.2.) 
That is, 3Tli must be preliminary to all moves Sfll 2 , , 3TI,. 

Thus we have again obtained the condition (15:A:a) of 15.1.3. We 
leave to the reader the simple verification that the game T 9i fulfills the 
requirements of 10.1.1. 

15.3. The Exact Condition (Entire Induction) 

15.3.1. As indicated at the end of 15.1.2., we wish to obtain the char- 
acteristics of T from those of all F^, fri = 1, , i, since this if suc- 
cessful would be a typical step of a "complete induction." 

For the moment, however, the only class of games for which we possess 
any kind of (mathematical) characteristics consists of the zero-sum two- 
person games: for these we have the quantities Vi, v 2 (cf. 15.1.1.). Let us 
therefore assume that F is a zero-sum two-person game. 

Now we shall see that the Vi, v 2 of F can indeed be expressed with the 
help of those of the r fj , 9i = 1, , i (cf. 15.1.2.). This circumstance 
makes it desirable to push the "induction" further, to its conclusion: 

i.e., to form in the same way I\, s , F^.^,^, , r it s 9 ,. 1 The 

point is that the number of steps in these games decreases successively 

from v (for F), v - 1 (for F^), over v - 2, v - 3, to (for r fi , fi ,); 

i.e. F* jf f 9 , is a "vacuous" game (like the one mentioned in the 

footnote 2 on p. 76). There are no moves; the player k gets the fixed 
amount $*(fri, -,#). 

This is the terminology of 15.1.2., 15.1.3., i.e. of 6., 7. In that of 
15.2.1., 15.2.2. i.e. of 9., 10. we would say that ft (for F) is gradually 
restricted to a Ci(fri) of a 2 (for r f| ), a C 2 (fri, fr 2 ) of ft 8 (for F^,^), a C 8 (fri, fr 2 , 9*) 
of a 4 (for rf if f f , f| ), etc., etc., and finally to a C,(*i, fr 2 , , 9,) of a,+i (for 

rt |( f t 9,). And this last set has a unique element ((10:1 :g) in 10.1.1.), 

say it. Hence the outcome of the game r f 9, is fixed: The player k 

gets the fixed amount $*(*). 

Consequently, the nature of the game F^,^ , 9y is trivially clear; 

it is clear what this game's value is for every player. Therefore the process 
which leads from the F^ to F if established can be used to work back- 
wards from T 9l .9 t 9 , to F, ir , a 9 V _ t to r f|ffi 9 ,_ t etc., etc., to 

F, i ,, i to T 9l and finally to F. 

But this is feasible only if we are able to form all games of the sequence 

r V T'i'*i> *X.i t . $ , ' ' ' > r fi ,f t 9 V , i.e. if the final condition of 15.1.3. 

or 15.2.2. is fulfilled for all these games. This requirement may again be 
formulated for any general n-person game F; so we return now to those F. 

16.3.2. The requirement then is, in the terminology of 15.1.2., 15.1.3. 
(i.e. of 6., 7.) that 3Tli must be preliminary to all 9fR 2 , SflZa, , 9ffl,; that 

1, , on; 1 - 1, , a t where a> * a f (*i); *i - 1, , ai where 
*t); etc., etc. 



GAMES WITH PERFECT INFORMATION 117 

3TC2 must be preliminary to all STls, 3TZ 4 , , 3fTC,; etc., etc.; i.e. that pre- 
liminarity must coincide with anteriority. 

In the terminology of 15.2.1., 15.2.2. i.e. of 9., 10. of course the same 
is obtained: All > K (k), K ^ 2 must be subpartitions of a 2 ; all SD(fc), * ^ 3 
must be subpartitions of Ct$, etc., etc.; i.e. all 5)(fc) must be subpartitions 
of a\ if K ^ X. 1 Since Ot< is a subpartition of Q,\ in any case (cf. 10.4.1.), it 
suffices to require that all >(&) be subpartitions of a. However a, is a 
subpartition of >(/0 within & K (k) ((10:1 :d) in 10.1.1.); consequently our 
requirement is equivalent to saying that ) K (k) is that part of & K which lies in 
B(fe). 2 By (10:B) in 10.4.2. this means precisely that preliminarity and 
anteriority coincide in F. 

By all these considerations we have established this: 

(15 :B) In order to be able to form the entire sequence of games 

(15:1) F, ly, rf it f f> F^,,^, ' * ' > r j, t * 9 

of 

v, v - 1, v - 2, , 

moves respectively, it is necessary and sufficient that in the game 
F preliminarity and anteriority should coincide, i.e. that per- 
fect information should prevail. (Cf. 6.4.1. and the end of 14.8.) 
If F is a zero-sum two-person game, then this permits the 
elucidation of F by going through the sequence (15:1) back- 
wards from the trivial game F^,^, . . . , r to the significant 
game F performing each step with the help of the device which 
leads from the T 9i to F as will be shown in 15.6.2. 

15.4. Exact Discussion of the Inductive Step 

15.4.1. We now proceed to carry out the announced step from the T 9g 9 
to F, the "inductive step." F need therefore fullfill only the final condition 
of 15.1.3. or 15.2.2., but it must be a zero-sum two-person game. 

Hence we can form all F^ , <r i = 1 , , a \ , and they also are zero-sum two- 
person games. We denote the two players' strategies in F by Sj, , S? 1 
and 2' 2 , , 2?; and the "mathematical expectation" of the outcome of 
the play for the two players, if the strategies SJi, 2j are used, by 

3Ci(n, rt) s OC(TI, TI), 3Ci(T,, TI) s -3C(r!, T 2 ) 

(cf. 11.2.3. and 14.1.1.). We denote the corresponding quantities in F, , 
by z; t/1> , S^r and s; i/2 , , zj^ 1 , and if the strategies S^ 1 , 
S^/2* are used, by 

flCfj/lOlVj/lj Te^/l) s 30^(^/1, T^/j), ^Crj/aCTcj/l, T^/j) S JC^^/i, T^/|). 

1 We stated this above for X = 2, 3, ; for X = 1 it is automatically true: every 
partition is a subpartition of Oti since Cti consists of the one set ((10:1 :f) in 10.1.1.). 

1 For the motivation if one is wanted cf . the argument of footnote 3 on p. 63. 

1 From now on we write <n, **, , <r* instead of 9\, ft, , S 9 because no mis- 
understandings will be possible. 



118 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

We form the vi, v 2 of 14.4.1. for T and for F^ denoting them in the latter 
case by v^/i, v, i/2 . So 

Vi = Max T| Min T| 3C(ri, 7 2 ), 
v 2 = Min Tf Max Ti 3C(n, r 2 ), 



and 



v, /2 



Our aim is to express the vi, v 2 in terms of the v r /i, v^/j. 

The fcj of 15.1.2., 15.2.1. which determine the character of the move 3Ej 
will play an essential role. Since n = 2, its possible values are k\ = 0, 1, 2. 
We must consider these three alternatives separately. 

15.4.2. Consider first the case k\ = 0; i.e. let 3Tli be a chance move. The 
probabilities of its alternatives <TI =!, , i are the pi(l), , PI(I) 
mentioned in 15.1.2. (pi(<n) is thepi(Ci) of (10:A:h) in 10.1.1. withCi = Ci(<7i) 
in 15.2.1.). 

Now a strategy of player 1 in T, S^, consists obviously in specifying a 

strategy of player 1 in F^, S^// for every value of the chance variable 

ai = 1, , i, 1 i.e., the 2I correspond to the aggregates 21/7, , Z^ 1 // 
for all possible combinations TI/I, , r ai /i. 

Similarly a strategy of player 2 in F, 2J consists in specifying a strategy 

of player 2 in F^, 2^/2 for every value of the chance variable <TI = 1, , 

ij i.e. the 2 2 correspond to the aggregates 2V/ 2 , ' * ' , ^a" 1 ^ for all possi- 
ble combinations TI/ Z , , r aj /2. 

Now the " mathematical expectations" of the outcomes in F and in F ff| 
are connected by the obvious formula 

i 
JC(TI, T 2 ) = J 

r t -l 

Therefore our formula for vi gives 
Vi = Max Ti Min Tj 3C(n, ? 2 ) 

= Max vi ..... ',/, Min v, 



r,-l 

The <ri-term of the sum V on the extreme right-hand side 



1 This is clear intuitively. The reader may verify it from the formal is tic point of 
view by applying the definitions of 11.1.1. and (11:A) in 11.1.3. to the situation described 
in 15.2.1. 



GAMES WITH PERFECT INFORMATION 119 

contains only the two variables r^/i, T, i/2 . Thus the variable pairs 

TI/I, Ti/ 2 ; ; T ai /i, r ttj / 2 
occur separately, in the separate o-i-terms 

Hence in forming the Min Vj Ta ,, we can minimize each <ri-term sep- 
arately, and in forming the Max Vi r<x /v we can again maximize each 

<ri-term separately. Accordingly, our expression becomes 

<*t <*i 

pi(cri) Max T<Vi Min rvt JC ri (T r|/ i, r V2 ) = pi(n)v ri /i. 

Thus we have shown 

(15:2) Vi = piOrOv^/i. 

If the positions of Max and Min are interchanged, then literally the 
same argument yields 

(15:3) v 2 = pi(cri)v <rj/2 . 

15.4.3. The case of fci = 1 comes next, and in this case we shall have 
to make use of the result of 13.5.3. Considering the highly formal character 
of this result, it seems desirable to bring it somewhat nearer to the reader's 
imagination by showing that it is the formal statement of an intuitively 
plausible fact concerning games. This will also make it clearer why this 
result must play a role at this particular juncture. 

The interpretation which we are now going to give to the result of 13.5.3. 
is based on our considerations of 14.2.-14.5. particularly those of 14.5.1., 
14.5.2. and for this reason we could not propose it in 13.5.3. 

For this purpose we shall consider a zero-sum two-person game F in its 
normalized form (cf. 14.1.1.) and also its minorant and majorant games Fi, 
F 2 (cf. 14.2.). 

If we decided to treat the normalized form of F as if it were an extensive 
form, and introduced strategies etc. with the aim of reaching a (new) 
normalized form by the procedure of 11.2.2., 11.2.3. then nothing would 
happen, as described in 11.3. and particularly in footnote 1 on p. 84. The 
situation is different, however, for the majorant and minorant games FI, Fa; 
these are not given in the normalized form, as mentioned in footnotes 2 and 3 
on p. 100. Consequently it is appropriate and necessary to bring them into 
their normalized forms which we are yet to find by the procedure of 
11.2.2., 11.2.3. 



120 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

Since complete solutions of FI, F 2 were found in 14.3.1., 14.3.3., it is to 
be expected that they will turn out to be strictly determined. 1 

It suffices to consider FI (cf. the beginning of 14.3.4.), and this we now 
proceed to do. 

We use the notations TI, r 2 , 3C(n, r 2 ) and vi, v 2 for F and we denote the 
corresponding concepts for FI by r(, r 2 , 3C'( r i> r i) and vi, v 2 . 

A strategy of player 1 in FI consists in specifying a (fixed) value 
TI(= 1, , 0i) while a strategy of plaj r er 2 in FI consists in specifying a 
value of r 2 (= 1, , 2) depending on TI for every value of TI( = !,-, 
0i). 2 So it is a function of TI: TI = 3 2 (ri). 

Thus T'J is TI, while T Z corresponds to the functions 3 2 , andSC'^i, rj) to 
3C(ri, 3 2 (ri)). Accordingly 



Tj Min 3| 3C(Ti, 3 2 (rj)), 
v a = Min 3f Max T| 3C(Ti, 3 2 (ri)). 

Hence the assertion that FI is strictly determined, i.e. the validity of 
vi = vi coincides precisely with (13 :E) in 13.5.3. ; there we need only replace 
the X, U, /(*), ifr(x, f(x)) by our n, T 2 , 3 2 (r,), JC(TI, 3 2 (ri)). 

This equivalence of the result of 13.5.3. to the strictly determined 
character of Fi makes intelligible why 13.5.3. will play an essential role 
in the discussion which follows. FI is a very simple example of a game in 
which perfect information prevails, and these are the games which are the 
ultimate goal of our present discussions (cf. the end of 15.3.2.). And the 
first move in Fi is precisely of the kind which is coming up for discussion 
now: It is a personal move of player 1, i.e. ki = 1. 

15.5. Exact Discussion of the Inductive Step (Continuation) 

15.6.1. Consider now the case fci = 1; i.e. let 3Tli be a personal move 
of the player 1. 

A strategy of player 1 in F, 2{i consists obviously in specifying a (fixed) 

value <rj( = 1, , on) and a (fixed) strategy of player 1 in F,, Zj 1 /^ 1 8 ; i.e. 
the Z5> correspond to the pairs <rj, T^/I. 

1 This is merely a heuristic argument, since the principles on which the "solutions" 
of 14.3.1., 14.3.3. are based are not entirely the same as those by which we disposed of the 
strictly determined case in 14.5.1., 14.5.2., although the former principles were a stepping 
stone to the latter. It is true that the argument could be made pretty convincing by an 
"unmathematical," purely verbal, amplification. We prefer to settle the matter 
mathematically, the reasons being the same as given in a similar situation in 14.3.2. 

* This is clear intuitively. The reader may verify it from the formalistic point of 
view, by reformulating the definition of r } as given in 14.2. in the partition and set 
terminology, and then applying the definitions of 11.1.1. and (11:A) in 11.1.3. 

The essential fact is, at any rate, that in Ti the personal move of player 1 is pre- 
liminary to that of player 2. 

1 Cf. footnote 1 on p. 118 or footnote 2 above. 



GAMES WITH PERFECT INFORMATION 121 

A strategy of player 2 in F, 2^, on the other hand, consists in specifying 
a strategy of player 2 in IV, 2^' /2 f , for every value of the variable <rj = 
1, , ai. 1 So r^/2 is a function of <r J : r^ /2 = 3s(<7j); i.e. the S5 correspond 
to the functions 3 2 and clearly 



Therefore our formula for Vi gives: 

vi = Max,;. TrJ/1 Min^OC^r,;,!, 3 2 (or)) 

= Max r<r?/i Max,j Min^JC^j/i, 3 2 (<rJ)). 
Now 

Max,,; Min^JC^Ovj/i, 3 s (<rJ)) = Max,; Min^SC,;^,;/!, r,;/i) 

owing to (13 :G) in 13.5.3.; there we need only replace the x, u, f(x), \l/(x, u) 
by our erj, r,; /2 , 3 2 (cr?), 3C,;(T,j/i, r ff j/ 2 ). 2 Consequently 



vi = Max T<rJ/l Max ff ; Min Tr , /t JC^r,;/!, T,; /t ) 
= Max^j Max T<r0/i Min v/t JC r j(r r j/i, r c j/t) 
= Max,; v r j/i 

And our formula for v 2 gives: 8 

v 2 = Min 3j Max^o/^ajCraJ/i, 

= Min 3j Max,; Max rr;/1 JC,;(r r j/ 
Now 
Min 3l Max^j Max rr!/I JC^j/i, 3 t (aJ)) 

= Max,j Min 3j Max r<r;/l ^jKj/i, 3 2 (<r5)) 

= Max a j Min Tff;/1 Max^o/.X^^j/i, T r j/,) 

owing to (13 :E) and (13 :G) in 13.5.3.; there we need only replace the x, u, 
f(x), \fr(x, u) by our a\, r,;/ 2 , 3 2 (<r?), Max v/i ac r j(r r j/i,r^/). 4 Consequently 

v 2 = 



Summing up (and writing <n instead of crj) : 

1 Cf. footnote 1 on p. 118 or footnote 2 on p. 120. 
1 TrJ/i must be treated in this case as a constant. 

This step is of course a rather trivial one, cf . the argument loc. cit. 
8 In contrast to 15.4.2., there is now an essential difference between the treatments of 
vi and vj. 

4 rrj/i is killed in this case by the operation Maxr a0/1 . 

This step is not trivial. It makes use of (13:E) in 13.5.3., i.e. of the essential result 
of that paragraph, as stated in 15.4.3. 



122 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

(15:4) vi = Max,, v^/i, 

(15:5) v 2 = Max^ v, i/2 . 



16.6.2. Consider finally the case fci = 2; i.e. let SfTli be a personal move of 
player 2. 

Interchanging players 1 and 2 carries this into the preceding case (fci = 1). 

As discussed in 14.6., this interchange replaces Vi, v 2 by v 2 , Vi 
and hence equally v^/i, v, i/2 by v^/j, v^/i. Substituting these changes 
into the above formulae (15:4), (15:5), it becomes clear that these formulae 
must be modified only by replacing Max in them by Min. So we have: 

(15:6) vi = Min^ v, t/ i, 

(15:7) v 2 = Min < r i v ri /i. 

16.6.3. We may sum up the formulae (16:2)-(15:7) of 15.4.2., 15.5.1., 
15.5.2., as follows: 

For all functions /(<TI) of the variable <TI(= 1, , i) define three 
operations Mjj, fci = 0, 1, 2 as follows: 

for fci = 0, 

(15:8) 

for 



for fci = 2. 
Then 

v* = M k \\ 9i/k for fc = 1, 2. 

We wish to emphasize some simple facts concerning these operations 
M".\. 

First, M*\ kills the variable a\ ; i.e. M 9 \f(ai) no longer depends on <n. 
For fci = 1, 2 i.e. for Max^, Min^ this was pointed out in 13.2.3. For 
fci = it is obvious; and this operation is, by the way, analogous to the 
integral used as an illustration in footnote 2 on p. 91. 

Second, M k \ depends explicitly on the game F. This is evident since 
fci occurs in it and <r\ has the range 1, , a\. But a further dependence 
is due to the use of the pi(l), , PI(I), in the case of fci = 0. 

Third, the dependence of v* on v ff /k is the same for fc = 1, 2 for each 
value of fci. 

We conclude by observing that it would have been easy to make these 

formulae involving the average ] PI(^I)/(^I) for a chance move, the 

maximum for a personal move of the first player, and the minimum for 
one of his opponent plausible by a purely verbal (unmathematical) 
argument. It seemed nevertheless necessary to give an exact mathematical 
treatment in order to do full justice to the precise position of Vi and of v 2 . 
A purely verbal argument attempting this would unavoidably become so 
involved if not obscure as to be of little value. 



GAMES WITH PERFECT INFORMATION 123 

16.6. The Result in the Case of Perfect Information 

15.6.1. We return now to the situation described at the end of 15.3.2. 

and make all the hypotheses mentioned there; i.e. we assume that perfect 
information prevails in the game F and also that it is a zero-sum two-person 
game. The scheme indicated loc. cit., together with the formula (15:8) of 
15.5.3. which takes care of the "inductive" step, enable us to determine the 
essential properties of F. 

We prove first without going any further into details that such a F 
is always strictly determined. We do this by " complete induction " with 
respect to the length v of the game (cf. 15.1.2.). This consists of proving 
two things : 

(15:C:a) That this is true for all games of minimum length; i.e. for 

v = 0. 
(15:C:b) That if it is true for all games of length v 1, for a given 

v = 1, 2, , then it is also true for all games of length v. 

Proof of (15:C:a) : If the length v is zero, then the game has no moves at 
all; it consists of paying fixed amounts to the players 1, 2, say the amounts 
w, w. 1 Hence 0i = 2 = 1 so TI = T Z = 1, 3C(n, r 2 ) = w, 2 and so 

vi = v 2 = w; 

i.e. F is strictly determined, and its v = w. 3 

Proof of (15:C:b): Let F be of length v. Then every F, t is of length 
v 1; hence by assumption every F^ is strictly determined. Therefore 
v 9i/ i ss v^/2. Now the formula (15:8) of 15.5.3. shows 4 that Vi = v t . 
Hence F is also strictly determined and the proof is completed. 

15.6.2. We shall now go more into detail and determine the Vi = V2 = v 
of F explicitly. For this we do not even need the above result of 15.6.1. 

We form, as at the end of 15.3.2., the sequence of games 

(15:9) r, r v r, rv - ,r, it , ...... ,/ 

of the respective lengths 

v, v - 1, v - 2, , 0. 
Denote the Vi, v 2 of these games by 



1 Cf. the game in footnote 2 on p. 76 or F^,^ ..... i v in 15.3.1. In the partition and 
set terminology: For v = (10:1 :f), (10:1 :g) in 10.1.1. show that 12 has only one ele- 
ment, say TT : ft = (TT). So w = $I(TT), w = 5i(ir) play the role indicated above. 

8 I.e. each player has only one strategy, which consists of doing nothing. 

* This is, of course, rather obvious. The essential step is U5:C:b). 

4 I.e. the fact mentioned at the end of 15.5.3., that the formula is the same for A; = 1,2 
for each value of k\. 

5 Cf. footnote 3 on p. 117. 



124 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

Let us apply (15:8) of 15.5.3. for the " inductive " step described at 

the end qf 15.3.2.; i.e. let us replace the <TI, T, T^of 15.5.3. by<r, r, t ^_ if 

T 9i , K _ itt , K for each * = !,, v. The ki of 15.5.3. then refers 

to the first move of T 0i OK j i.e. to the move 311* in F. It is therefore 

convenient to denote it by fc(*i, * * ' , ow). (Cf. 7.2.1.) Accordingly 

we form the operation M k * K (ffl '"- 1 ', replacing the M k \ of 15.5.3. In this 

way we obtain 

(15:10) v., w * = M*,f " ' ' ' ' ^ v, t , K/ * for fc = 1, 2. 

Consider now the last element of the sequence (15:9), the game F^ v 

This falls under the discussion of (15:C:a) in 15.6.1.; it has no moves at all. 
Denote its unique play 1 by if = ff(<ri, , <? v ). Hence its fixed w 2 is 
equal to (Fi(((ri, , <r,)). So we have: 

(15:11) v^ % /i = v^ ,,/t = ffi(ir(<ri, , <r,)). 

Now apply (15:10) with K = v to (15:11) and then to the result, with 
K =s v l t - ,2, 1 successively. In this manner 

(15:12) v, = v 2 = v = M k 9 \M k ^ M** 9 * "'*Si(*(ffi, , O). 

obtains. 

This proves once more that T is strictly determined, and also gives an 
explicit formula for its value. 

15.7. Application to Chess 

15.7.1. The allusions of 6.4.1. and the assertions of 14.8. concerning 
those zero-sum two-person games in which preliminarity and anteriority 
coincide i.e. where perfect information prevails are now established. We 
referred there to the general opinion that these games are of a particularly 
rational character, and we have now given this vague view a precise meaning 
by showing that the games In question are strictly determined. And we 
have also shown a fact much less founded on any " general opinion" 
that this is also true when the game contains chance moves. 

Examples of games with perfect information were already given in 6.4.1. : 
Chess (without chance moves) and Backgammon (with chance moves). 
Thus we have established for all these games the existence of a definite 
value (of a play) and of definite best strategies. But we have established 
their existence only in the abstract, while our method for their construction 
is in most cases too lengthy for effective use. 3 

In this connection it is worth while to consider Chess in a little more 
detail. 

1 Cf. the remarks concerning r^ ^ in 15.3.1. 

1 Cf. (15:C:a) in 15.6.1., particularly footnote 1 on p. 123. 

8 This is due mainly to the enormous value of v. For Chess, cf . the pertinent part of 
footnote 3 on p. 59. (The v* there is our K, cf. the end of 7.2.3.) 



GAMES WITH PERFECT INFORMATION 125 

The outcome of a play in Chess i.e. every value of the functions SF* of 
6.2.2. or 9.2.4. is restricted to the numbers 1,0, I. 1 Thus the functions 
9* of 11.2.2. have the same values, and since there are no chance moves in 
Chess, the same is true for the function OC* of 11.2.3. 2 In what follows we 
shall use the f unction 3C = 3Ci of 14.1.1. 

Sincere has only the values, 1,0, 1, the number 

(15:13) v = Max Ti Mm Tj 3C(n, r 2 ) = Min Tj Max Tj 3C(r,, r 2 ) 

has necessarily one of these values 

v- 1,0, -1. 
We leave to the reader the simple discussion that (15:13) means this: 

(15:D:a) If v = 1 then player 1 (" white ") possesses a strategy with 

which he "wins," irrespective of what player 2 ("black") 

does. 
(15:D:b) If v = then both players possess a strategy with which 

each one can "tie" (and possibly "win"), irrespective of 

what the other player does. 
(15:D:c) If v = 1 then player 2 ("black") possesses a strategy 

with which he "wins," irrespective of what player 1 ("white") 

does. 8 

15.7.2. This shows that if the theory of Chess were really fully known 
there would be nothing left to play. The theory would show which of the 
three possibilities (15:D:a), (15:D:b), (15:D:c) actually holds, and accord- 
ingly the play would be decided before it starts: The decision would be in 
case (15:D:a) for "white," in case (15:D:b) for a "tie," in case (15:D:c) 
for "black." 

But our proof, which guarantees the validity of one (and only one) 
of these three alternatives, gives no practically usable method to determine 
the true one. This relative, human difficulty necessitates the use of those 
incomplete, heuristic methods of playing, which constitute "good" Chess; 
and without it there would be no element of "struggle" and "surprise" in 
that game. 

1 This is the simplest way to interpret a "win," "tie," or "loss" of a play by the 
player k. 

* Every value of 9* is one of ff *; every value of 3C* in the absence of chance moves is 
one of 9*> ^ l c - cit. If there were chance moves, then the value of 3C* would be the 
probability of a "win" minus that of a "loss," i.e. a number which may lie anywhere 
between 1 and 1. 

8 When there are chance moves, then 3C(ri, r 2 ) is the excess probability of a "win" 
over a "loss," cf. footnote 2 above. The players try to maximize or to minimize this 
number, and the sharp trichotomy of (15:D:a) (15:D:c) above does not, in general, 
obtain. 

Although Backgammon is a game in which complete information prevails, and which 
contains chance moves, it is not a good example for the above possibility; Backgammon 
is played for varying payments, and not for simple "win," "tie" or "loss," i.e. the 
values of the $* are not restricted to the numbers 1,0, 1. 



126 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

15.8. The Alternative, Verbal Discussion 

16.8.1. We conclude this chapter by an alternative, simpler, less forma 
istic approach to our main result, that all zero-sum two-person games, i 
which perfect information prevails, are strictly determined. 

It can be questioned whether the argumentation which follows is reall 
a proof; i.e., we prefer to formulate it as a plausibility argument by which 
value can be ascribed to each play of any game F of the above type, but thi 
is still open to criticism. It is not necessary to show in detail how thos 
criticisms can be invalidated, since we obtain the same value v of a play c 
T as in 15.4.-15.6., and there we gave an absolutely rigorous proc 
using precisely defined concepts. The value of the present plausibilit 
argument is that it is easier to grasp and that it may be repeated for othe 
games, in which perfect information prevails, which are not subject to th 
zero-sum two-person restriction. The point which we wish to bring on 
is that the same criticisms apply in the general case too, and that they ca 
no longer be invalidated there. Indeed, the solution there will be foun 
(even in games where perfect information prevails) along entirely differen 
lines. This will make clearer the nature of the difference between th 
zero-sum two-person case and the general case. That will be rathe 
important for the justification of the fundamentally different method 
which will* have to be used for the treatment of the general cas 
(cf. 24.). 

16.8.2. Consider a zero-sum two-person game F in which perfect informa 
tion prevails. We use the notations of 15.6.2. in all respects: For th 
STCi, 3TC 2 , , 311,; the <n, cr 2 , , a,] the fci, fc 2 (<n), , k,(<n, **, , <r,_0 
the probabilities; the operators M h .\, Af*; (<ri> , , M*?' 1 ' 9 ' ..... ''-''j th 
sequence (15:9) of games derived from F; and the function &I(*(<TI, - - ,0-,)) 

We proceed to discuss the game F by starting with the last move 3M 
and then going backward from there through the moves 9fTC,_i, 3TC,_ 2 , 
Assume first that the choices <TI, o- 2 , , <r -\ (of the moves 9Tli, 3fE 2 , ' 
3fll,_i) have already been made, and that the choice <r, (of the move 9TC,) i 
now to be made. 

If 9TC, is a chance move, i.e. if k,(<n, 0- 2 , , <r,_i) = 0, then v v wil 
have the values 1, 2, , a,,(<ri, , v v -\) with the respective probabili 
ties p,(l), p*(2), ,p 9 (cL 9 ((r\, , o-,_i)). So the mathematical expec 
tation of the final payment (for the player 1) 9 r i(*(o-i, , <r,_i, <7,)) i 



*- 

If 3TI, is a personal move of players 1 or 2, i.e. if k 9 (<r\, , <r v -\) = 
or 2, then that player can be expected to maximize or to minimize 
$i(*(<n, * * * , <r,-i, <r*)) by his choice of <r,; i.e. the outcome 
Max,, 2Fi(lf(<ri, , <r,-i, <r,)) or Min^ $i(ff(<ri, , <r,_i, <r,)), respec 
tively is to be expected. 



GAMES WITH PERFECT INFORMATION 127 

I.e., the outcome to be expected for the play after the -choices <TI, 
v -\ have been made is at any rate 



Assume next that only the choices <n, , a r _2 (of the moves 
, 9TC,_i) have been made and that the choice <r,_i (of the move 9K,_i) 
is now to be made. 

Since a definite choice of <r,_i entails, as we have seen, the outcome 
Afjj (r| ..... *'~ l) &i(*(<ri, . , 0v)) which is a function of <n, , a,-i 
only, since the operation Mj v (ffl ..... '"** kills cr, we can proceed as above. 
We need only replace F; <n, ,*,; M k .*' 1 ..... '"- l} friOKn, , or,)) by 
v- 1; en, , a,_ i; Mj; : ; ( '> ..... "-'> Atf'/' ..... "-> *,(*(, , a,)). 
Consequently the outcome to be expected for the play after the choices 
<n, * * , cr,_ 2 have been made is 



Similarly the outcome to be expected for the play after the choices 
<n, , <r,_s have been made is 



Finally, the outcome to be expected for the play outright before it 
has begun is 



And this is precisely the v of (15:12) in 15.6.2. 1 

15.8.3. The objection against the procedure of 15.8.2. is that this 
approach to the "value" of a play of T presupposes "rational" behavior 
of all players; i.e. player 1's strategy is based upon the assumption that 
player 2's strategy is optimal and vice-versa. 

Specifically: Assume fc,_i(<n, , <r,_ 2 ) = 1, k,(*i, , <r,_i) = 2. 
Then player 1, whose personal move is 9H v _i chooses his <r,_i in the convic- 
tion that player 2, whose personal move is 9fR, chooses his <r, "rationally." 
Indeed, this is his sole excuse for assuming that his choice of <r v -\ entails 
the outcome Min,,SiOr(en, ,O), i.e. M^' 1 ..... '"-'^i^^i, ,*,)), 
of the play. (Cf. the discussion of 3TC,_i in 15.8.2.) 

1 In imagining the application of this procedure to any specific game it must be remem- 
bered that we assume the length v of T to be fixed. If v is actually variable and it is 
so in most games (cf. footnote 3 on p. 58) then we must first make it constant, by 
the device of adding "dummy moves" to T as described at the end of 7.2.3. It is only 
after this has been done that the above regression through 3TC,, 9M*-i, , 9Ri becomes 
feasible. 

For practical construction this procedure is of course no better than that of 15.4.- 
15.6. 

Possibly some very simple games, like Tit-tat-toe, could be effectively treated in 
either manner. 



128 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

Now in the second part of 4.1.2. we came to the conclusion that the 
hypothesis of " rationality " in others must be avoided. The argumentation 
of 15.8.2. did not meet this requirement. 

It is possible to argue that in a zero-sum two-person game the rationality 
of the opponent can be assumed, because the irrationality of his opponent 
can never harm a player. Indeed, since there are only two players and 
since the sum is zero, every loss which the opponent irrationally inflicts 
upon himself, necessarily causes an equal gain to the other player. 1 As it 
stands, this argument is far from complete, but it could be elaborated con- 
siderably. However, we do not need to be concerned with its stringency: 
We have the proof of 15.4. -15.6. which is not open to these criticisms. 2 

But the above discussion is probably nevertheless significant for an 
essential aspect of this matter. We shall see how it affects the modified 
conditions in the more general case not subject to the zero-sum two-person 
restriction referred to at the end of 15.8.1. 

16. Linearity and Convexity 
16.1. Geometrical Background 

16.1.1. The task which confronts us next is that of finding a solution 
which comprises all zero-sum two-person games, i.e. which meets the 
difficulties of the non-strictly determined case. We shall succeed in doing 
this with the help of the same ideas with which we mastered the strictly 
determined case : It will appear that they can be extended so as to cover all 
zero-sum two-person games. In order to do this we shall have to make 
use of certain possibilities of probability theory (cf. 17.1., 17.2.). And 
it will be necessary to use some mathematical devices which are not quite 
the usual ones. Our analysis of 13. provides one part of the tools; for the 
remainder it will be most convenient to fall back on the mathematico- 
geometrical theory of linearity and convexity. Two theorems on convex 
bodies 3 will be particularly significant. 

For these reasons we are now going to discuss to the extent to which 
they are needed the concepts of linearity and convexity. 

16.1.2. It is not necessary for us to analyze in a fundamental way the 
notion of n-dimensional linear (Euclidean) space. All we need to say is 
that this space is described by n numerical coordinates. Accordingly we 
define for each n = 1, 2, , the n-dimensional linear space L n as the 
set of all n-uplets of real numbers [x\, - - ,x n }. These n-uplets can also 
be looked upon as functions i of the variable i, with the domain (1, , n) 

1 This is not necessarily true if the sum is not constantly zero, or if there are more 
than two players. For details cf. 20.1., 24.2.2., 58.3. 

Cf. in this respect particularly (14:D:a), (14:D:b), (14:C:d), (14:C:e) in 14.5.1. 
and (14:C:a), (H:C:b) in 14.5.2. 

1 Cf. T. Bonessen and W. Fenchel: Theorie der konvexen Korper, in Ergebnisse der 
Mathematik und ihrer Grenzgebiete, Vol. III/l, Berlin 1934. Further investigations in 
H. Weyl: Elementare Theorie der konvexen Polyeder. Commentarii Mathematici JGEelve- 
tici, Vol. VII, 1935, pp. 290-306. 



LINEARITY AND CONVEXITY 129 

in the sense of 13.1.2., 13.1.3. 1 We shall in conformity with general 
usage call i an index and not a variable; but this does not alter the nature 
of the case. In particular we have 

{xi, , x n } = jtfi, , y n ] 

if and only if x = yi for all i = 1, , n (cf. the end of 13.1.3.). One 
could even take the view that L n is the simplest possible space of (numerical) 
functions, where the domain is a fixed finite set the set (1, , n). 2 

We shall also call these n-uplets or functions of L n points or vectors of 
L n and write 

(16:1) "? = {xi, - - ,x*\. 

The Xi for the specific i = 1, , n the values of the function x are 

the components of the vector x. 

16.1.3. We mention although this is not essential for our further work 
that L n is not an abstract Euclidean space, but one in which a frame of 
reference (system of coordinates) has already been chosen. 3 This is due 
to the possibility of specifying the origin and the coordinate vectors of L n 
numerically (cf. below) but we do not propose to dwell upon this aspect 
of the matter. 

The zero vector or origin of L n is 

0*= {0, - - ,0}. 
The n coordinate vectors of L n are the 

7= {0, ,1, ,0) = {!,, ,6 n ,l j = 1, , n, 

where 

for i = j, 4 - 5 
for i ? j. 

After these preliminaries we can now describe the fundamental oper- 
ations and properties of vectors in L n . 

16.2. Vector Operations 

16.2.1. The main operations involving vectors are those of scalar 

> 
multiplication, i.e. the multiplication of a vector x by a number t, and of 

1 I.e. the rMiplets [x\, , x n \ are not merely sets in the sense of 8.2.1. The 
effective enumeration of the x, by means of the index i = 1, , n is just as essential 
as the aggregate of their values. Cf . the similar situation in footnote 4 on p. 69. 

1 Much in modern analysis tends to corroborate this attitude. 

8 This at least is the orthodox geometrical standpoint. 

4 Thus the zero vector has all components 0, while the coordinate vectors have all 
components but one that one component being 1, and its index j for thej-th coordinate 
vector. 

6 in is the "symbol of Kronecker and Weierstrass," which is quite useful in many 
respects. 



130 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

vector addition, i.e. addition of two vectors. The two operations are defined 
by the corresponding operations, i.e. multiplication and addition, on the 
components of the vector in question. More precisely: 

Scalar multiplication: t{x\, - - , x n } = [txi, , tx n }. 
Vector addition : 

{zi, , x n } + [yi, - , y n ] = [xi + t/i, , x n + y n \. 

The algebra of these operations is so simple and obvious that we forego 
its discussion. We note, however, that they permit the expression of any 

vector x = [x\, - - , x n ] with the help of its components and the coordi- 
nate vectors of L n 



Some important subsets of L n : 
(16:A:a) Consider a (linear, inhomogeneous) equation 

n 

(16:2:a) a > x > = l 

i-i 

(ai, , a n , b are constants). We exclude 

ai = = a = 
since in that case there would be no equation at all. All 

points (vectors) x = {zi, , x n \ which fulfill this equation, 
form a hyperplane. 2 

(16:A:b) Given a hyperplane 

n 

(16:2:a) X a '*' = b > 

-i 

it defines two parts of L n . It cuts L n into these two parts: 

n 

(16:2:b) J) OM > 6, 

t-i 
and 

(16:2:c) ^ a l x i < b. 

t-i 

These are the two half-spaces produced by the hyperplane. 

> n 

1 The x, are numbers, and hence they act mx } 8 'as scalar multipliers. 2^ is a vector 

y-i 

summation. 

* For n 3, i.e. in ordinary (3-dimensional Euclidean) space, these are just the 
ordinary (2-dimensional) planes. In our general case they are the ((n 1 )-dimensional) 
analogues; hence the name. 



LINEARITY AND CONVEXITY 



131 



Observe that if we replace a i, , a n , b by ai, , a n , 6, then 
the hyperplane (16:2 :a) remains unaffected, but the two half-spaces (16:2:b), 
(16:2:c) are interchanged. Hence we may always assume a half space to 
be given in the form (16:2:b). 

> > 
(16:A:c) Given two points (vectors) x , y andaJ ^ Owithl t ^ 0; 

then the center of gravity of x, y with the respective weights 
I, 1 t in the sense of mechanics is / x + (1 - t) y. 

The equations 

> 

X = {Xl, , X n ), y = (2/1, ' , 2/n), 

*7 + (1 - 07 = Itei + (1 - Ol/i, - - , ten + (1 - t)y n ] 

should make this amply clear. 

A subset, C, of L n which contains all centers of gravity of all its points 

i.e. which contains with x, y all x + (1 f) y , Q t 1 is convex. 

The reader will note that for n = 2, 
3 i.e. in the ordinary plane or space 
this is the customary concept of con- 
vexity. Indeed, the set of all points 

t x + (1 y , ^ t ^ 1 is precisely 
the linear (straight) interval connect- 

ing the points x and y , the interval 
[ x , y]. And so a convex set is one 

which, with any two of its points x , x interval i* i 

> Figure 16. 

y , also contains their interval [ x , y ]. 

Figure 16 shows the conditions for n = 2, i.e. in the plane. 

16.2.2. Clearly the intersection of any number of convex sets is again 

> > 

convex. Hence if any number of points (vectors) x ', , x p is given, 

there exists a smallest convex set containing them all: the intersection of 

all convex sets which contain x ', , x p . This is the convex set .spanned 

> 

by x ',, x p . It is again useful to visualize the case n = 2 (plane). 
Cf. Fig. 17, where p = 6. It is easy to verify that this set consists of all 
points (vectors) 




(16:2:d) 



(/ *''f orally ^ 0, , t p ^ with 



/, = 1. 



Proof: The points (16:2:d) form a set containing all x ', 
x ' is such a point: put tj = 1 and all other ti 0. 



132 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

> * > 
The points (16:2 :d) form a convex set : If x = 2} J/ * ; and y = 

p 

then * z + (1 - y = t*v x ' with w/ = **,-+ (1 - O*/- 

y-i 

Any convex set, D, containing a; ',, z p contains also all "points 
of (16:2:d): We prove this by induction for all p = 1, 2, . 

Proof: For p = 1 it is obvious; since then ti = 1 and so x ' is the only 
point of (16:2:d). 

P-I 
Assume that it is true for p 1. Consider p itself. If 2) <; = then 

jj = = < p _ 1 = 0, the point of (16:2 :d) is x p and thus belongs to D. If 




Shaded area: Convex spanned by 7-,....,? 
Figure 17. 



p-i 



P-I p-l p 

2 *, > 0, then put * = 5) *,,sol -J^JJ^-S^ 5 " 8 ^. HenceO < ^ 1. 
y-i y-i y-i y-i 

P-I 
Put 5, = < 7 /< for j = 1, , p 1. So 2) Sj ? = 1. Hence, by our 

y-i 

P-I _ 

assumption for p - 1, % 8jX > is in D. D is convex, hence 
y-i 



y-i 



is also in D; but this vector is equal to 



which thus belongs to Z>. 



5; 

y-i 



LINEARITY AND CONVEXITY 



133 



The proof is therefore completed. 

The h, , t p of (16:2:d) may themselves be viewed as the com- 


ponents of a vector t = {t\, , t p ] inL p . It is therefore appropriate 

to give a name to the set to which they are restricted, defined by 
ti ^ 0, - - , t p 0, 



and 



r,-txit 



- 1. 




Zt-axis 



Figure 18. 

n ? 



Figure 19. 




Figure 20. Figure 21. 

We shall denote it by S p . It is also convenient to give a name to the set 
which is described by the first line of conditions above alone, i.e. by t\ ^ 0, 
* , tp ^ 0. We shall denote it by P p . Both sets S p , P P are convex. 

Let us picture the cases p = 2 (plane) and p = 3 (space). P 2 is the 
positive quadrant, the area between the positive x\ and x* axes (Figure 18). 
P 8 is the positive octant, the space between the positive x\, x* and x 8 axes, 
i.e. between the plane quadrants limited by the pairs x\, # 2 ; x\, x 8 ; x 2 , x 8 of 
these (Fig. 19). /S 2 is a linear interval crossing P 2 (Figure 18). 5 8 is a plane 
triangle, likewise crossing P 8 (Figure 19). It is useful to draw Si, Si sep- 



134 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

arately, without the Pa, P 8 (or even the La, L 8 ) into which they are naturally 
immersed (Figures 20, 21). We have indicated on these figures those dis- 
tances which are proportional to Xi, Xa or x\, x 2 , x 8 , respectively. 

(We re-emphasize: The distances marked x\, x 2 , x 8 in Figures 20, 21 are 
not the coordinates x\, xa, x 8 themselves. These lie in La or L 8 outside of 
Sa or S 8 , and therefore cannot be pictured in Sz or 83 } but they are easily 
seen to be proportional to those coordinates.) 

16.2.3. Another important notion is the length of a vector. The length 

of x = {xi, , x n } is 



1*1 = A 

' t-i 



The distance of two points (vectors) is the length of their difference : 



Thus the length of x is the distance from the origin . l 

16.3. The Theorem of the Supporting Hyperplanes 

16.3. We shall now establish an important general property of convex 
sets: 

(16:B) Let p vectors x l , - - - , x p be given. Then a vector y 

> 

either belongs to the convex C spanned by x ',, x p (cf. 

(16:A:c) in 16.2.1.), or there exists a hyperplane which contains 

y (cf. (16:2:a) in 16.2.1.) such that all of C is contained in 
one half-space produced by that hyperplane (say (16:2:b) in 
16.2.1. ;cf. (16:A:b) id.). 

This is true even if the convex spanned by x ', , x p is replaced by 
any convex set. In this form it is a fundamental tool in the modern theory 
of convex sets. 

A picture in the case n = 2 (plane) follows: Figure 22 uses the convex 
set C of Figure 17 (which is spanned by a finite number of points, as in 
the assertion above), while Figure 23 shows a general convex set C. 2 

Before proving (16 :B), we observe that the second alternative clearly 

excludes the first, since y belongs to the hyperplane, hence not to the half 
space. (I.e. it fulfills (16:2:a) and not (16:2:b) in (16:A:b) above.) 
We now give the proof: 

Proof: Assume that y does not belong to C. Then consider a point of 
C which lies as near to y as possible, i.e. for which 

1 The Euclidean Pythagorean meaning of these notions is immediate. 

*For the reader who is familiar with topology, we add: To be exact, this sentence 
should be qualified the statement is meant for closed convex sets. This guarantees 
the existence of the minimum that we use in the proof that follows. Regarding these 



LINEARITY AND CONVEXITY 

|7 - 7l 2 = ( - ViY 



135 



assumes its minimum value. 



The hyperplane 



t-l 



The half space 




Figure 22. 



The hyperplane 



The half space 




Figure 23. 

Consider any other points u of C. Then for every t with ^ t ^ 1, 
tu + (I t) z also belongs to the convex C. By virtue of the minimum 
property of z (cf. above) this necessitates 



i.e. 



i.e. 



- y)+t(u - 



By elementary algebra this means 

2 <* 



^ 0. 



t-l 



136 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

So f or t > (but of course t ^ 1) even 

2 5) (ft ~ Vi)(Ui - ft) + t (Ui - z<)*t * 0. 
t-i t-i 

n 

If t converges to 0, then the left-hand side converges to 2 J) (ft ~~ & 
Hence 

(16:3) (* - y,)(t*< - ft) ^ 0. 

As w, yi = (w t - Zi) + (ft ~ 2/.), this means 



ft). 



- i 2 . 



t'-l 



t-1 



Now 2; 7^ y (as z belongs to C, but y does not); hence \ z y | 2 > 0. 
So the left-hand side above is > 0. I.e. 



(16:4) 



(ft - t/)2/. 



-i 



Put a< = y, then ai 




Figure 24. 



= = a n = is excluded by z j* y (cf. 

n 

above). Put also b = a^,. Thus 



(16:2 *) 



defines a hyperplane, to which y clearly be- 
1 ;s. Next 



<z, > 



(16:2:b*) 



is a half space produced by this hyperplane, and (16:4) states precisely 
that u belongs to this half space. 

Since u was an arbitrary element of C this completes the proof. 
This algebraic proof can also be stated in the geometrical language. 
Let us do this for the case n = 2 (plane) first. The situation is pictured 

in Figure 24: z is a point of C which is as near to the given point y as possible; 
i.e. for which the distance of y and z , | z y\ assumes its minimum value. 



LINEARITY AND CONVEXITY 137 

_* > _+ 

Since y , 2 are fixed, and w is a variable point (of C), therefore (16:3) defined 
a hyperplane and one of the half spaces produced by it. And it is easy 

to verify that z belongs to this hyperplane, and that it consists of those 



points u for which the angle formed by the three points is a right-angle 
(i.e. for which the vectors z y and u z are orthogonal). This means, 



Interval ( x , u J 
Part of the interval nearer to y than * 




^ Hyperplane of (1 3) 

Figure 25. 




Hyperplane of (16:4) 
Hyperplane of (16:3) 



Figure 26. 
n 

indeed, that JJ (zi yi)(ui z>) = 0. Clearly all of C must lie on this 
-i 

hyperplane, or on that side of it which is away from y . If any point u 
of C did lie on the y side, then some points of the interval [ z , u ] would be 

nearer to y than z is. (Cf. Figure 25. The computation on pp. 135-136 

> 
properly interpreted shows precisely this.) Since C contains z and u , 

and so all of [ z , u], this would contradict the statement that z is as near 

to y as possible in C. 

Now our passage from (16:3) to (16:4) amounts to a parallel shift of 

this hyperplane from z to y (parallel, because the coefficients a = y 



138 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 



of Uiy i = 1, , n are unaltered). Now y lies on the hyperplane, and 
all of C in one half-space produced by it (Figure 26). 

The case n = 3 (space) could be visualized in a similar way. 

It is even possible to account for a general n in this geometrical manner. 
If the reader can persuade himself that he possesses n-dimensional "geo- 
metrical intuition " he may accept the above as a proof which is equally 
valid in n dimensions. It is even possible to avoid this by arguing as 
follows: Whatever n, the entire proof deals with only three points at once, 

namely y , z , u . Now it is always possible to lay a (2-dimensional) plane 
through three given points. If we consider only the situation in this 
plane, then Figures 24-26 and the associated argument can be used without 
any re-interpretation. 

Be this as it may, the purely algebraic proof given above is absolutely 
rigorous at any rate. We gave the geometrical analogies mainly in the 
hope that they may facilitate the understanding of the algebraic operations 
performed in that proof. 

16.4. The Theorem of the Alternative for Matrices 

16.4.1. The theorem (16 :B) of 16.3. permits an inference which will be 
fundamental for our subsequent work. 

We start by considering a rectangular matrix in the sense of 13.3.3. 
with n rows and m columns, and the matrix element a(t, j). (Cf. Figure 11 
in 13.3.3. The <, z, y, t, s there correspond to our a, i, j, n, m.) I.e. 
a(t, j) is a perfectly arbitrary function of the two variables i = 1, , n\ 
j 1, , m. Next we form certain vectors in L n : For each j' = 1, , 

m the vector x 1 = {x\, , x' n ] with x{ = a(i, j) and for each I = 1, 


, n the coordinate vector 5 l = {B l i}. (Cf. for the latter the end of 

16.1.3.; we have replaced the j there by our 1.) Let us now apply the 
theorem (16 :B) of 16.3. for p = n + m to these n + m vectors x ',, 
x m , d ',, 6 n . (They replace the x ',, x p loc. cit.) We put 

7=7. 

> 

The convex C spanned by x ',, x m , 6 ',, 6 n may contain 0. 

If this is the case, then we can conclude from (16:2:d) in 16.2.2. that 

*/7;>-+ i>7< =K 

; - 1 f-1 

with 

(16:5) *! ^ 0, , t m ^ 0, 81 ^ 0, - , s n ^ 0. 

(16:6) t, : + Sl = 1. 



LINEARITY AND CONVEXITY 139 

<!,* , Jm, i, * ' , s n replace the t\ t , t p (loc. cit.). In terms of the 
components this means 

m n 

2) *x*> j) + 2} */** = o. 
y=i j-i 

The second term on the left-hand side is equal to s, so we write 

(16:7) a(i,j)ti= -,. 

y-i 

m 

If we had % tj = 0, then ti = = t m = 0, hence by (16:7) s l = = 
y-i 

m 

s n = 0, thus contradicting (16:6). Hence 2) */ > - We replace (16:7) 

y-i 

by its corollary 

(16:8) aftJH-SO. 



2^ ^ for j = 1, , m. Then we have 2} */ = 1 
j-i y-i 

(16:5) gives x\ ^ 0, , x m ^ 0. Hence 

(16:9) x = jxi, , x m \ belongs to S m 

and (16:8) gives 

m 

U6:10) 2 *(*'/)*/ ^ for f = 1, , n. 



Consider, on the other hand, the possibility that C does not contain . 
Then the theorem (16:B) of 16.3. permits us to infer the existence of a 

hyperplane which contains y (cf. (16:2:a) in 16.2.1.), such that all of C 
is contained in one half-space produced by that hyperplane (cf. (16:2:b) in 
16.2.1.). Denote this hyperplane by 

n 

2} a t Xi = 6. 
t-i 

Since belongs to it, therefore 6 = 0. So the half space in question is 

n 

(16:11) o,^ > 0. 



140 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

x ',*, x m , d ',*, 6 n belong to this half space. Stating this for 

- n 

5 ', (16:11) becomes o t $,j > 0, i.e. ai > 0. So we have 
-i 

(16:12) ai > 0, , a n > 0. 

Stating it for x J , (16:11) becomes 

n 

(16:13) J) a(t,j)a< > 0. 

i-i 

/n n 

2) 0* for i = 1, , n. Then we have ti\ = 1 and 

-i t-i 

(16:12) gives wi > 0, , w n > 0. Hence 

(16:14) w = {wi, , w n \ belongs to S n . 

And (16:13) gives 

m 

(16:15) a(i t j)Wi ^ for j = 1, , m. 

% - i 

Summing up (16:9), (16:10), (16:14), (16:15), we may state: 

(16 :C) Let a rectangular matrix with n rows and m columns be 

given. Denote its matrix element by a(i, j), i = 1, , n; 

j = 1, , m. Then there exists either a vector x = 

[xi, - - - , x m ] inS m with 

m 

(16:16:a) a(t, j>, ^0 for i = 1, , n, 

/-i 


or a vector w = {101, , w n ] in <S n with 

n 

(16:16:b) a(i, j)w< > for j = 1, , m. 

-i 

We observe further: 

The two alternatives (16:16:a), (16:16:b) exclude each other. 

Proof: Assume both (16:16:a) and (16:16:b). Multiply each (16:16:a) by 

n m 

Wi and sum over i = 1, ,n; this gives % a(i, j)w&j ^ 0. Multiply 



LINEARITY AND CONVEXITY 141 

each (16:16:b) by x, and sum over j = 1, , w; this gives 



t-iy-i 

Thus we have a contradiction. 

16.4.2. We replace the matrix a(i, j) by its negative transposed matrix; 
i.e. we denote the columns (and not, as before, the rows) by i = 1, , n 
and the rows (and not, as before, the columns) by j = 1, , m. And 
we let the matrix element be a(t, j) (and not, as before a(i, j)). (Thus 
n, m too are interchanged.) 

We restate now the final results of 16.4.1. as applied to this new matrix. 

But in formulating them, we let x ' = {x\, , x' m \ play the role which 

w = [wi, , w n ] had, and w' = {w(, - - , w' n \ the role which x =* 
[x\y - , m } had. And we announce the result in terms of the original 
matrix. 

Then we have: 

(16 :D) Let a rectangular matrix with n rows and m columns be 

given. Denote its matrix element by a(i, j), i = 1, , n; 

j = 1, , m. Then there exists either a vector x' = 
(x'j, , x'J in S m with 

m 

(16:17:a) a(i, j)x' ; < for t = 1, - , n, 

y-i 

or a vector w' = {w(, - - - , u^) in S n with 

n 

(16:17 :b) & JX ^0 f r 



i-l 

And the two alternatives exclude each other. 

16.4.3. We now combine the results of 16.4.1. and 16.4.2. They imply 
that we must have (16:17:a), or (16:16:b), or (16:16:a) and (16:17:b) 
simultaneously; and also that these three possibilities exclude each other. 

Using the same matrix a(t, j) but writing x , w , x\ w ' for the vectors 
x', w y x , w' in 16.4.1., 16.4.2. we obtain this: 

1 > and not only < 0. Indeed, would necessitate x\ = x m * which 

m 
it impossible since J) *, 1. 



142 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

(16:E) There exists either a vector x = \x\, - - - , z m j in S m with 

m 

(16:18:a) a(t, ;>, < for t = 1, , n, 

>-i 

or a vector w = [wi, - , w n j in S n with 

n 

(16:18:b) a(i, j)wi > for j = 1, , m, 

; = i 

ortwo vectors x' = [x(, - - ,x' m \ inS m and w f = \w' lt - ,u/ n j 
in & with 



for i = 1, , n, 
(16:18:c) '"' 

2) a(i, j)^ ^0 for j = 1, , m. 
t-i 

The three alternatives (16:18:a), (16:8:b), (16:8:c) exclude each 
other. 

By combining (16:18:a) and (16:18:c) on one hand and (16:18:b) and 
(16:18:c) on the other, we get this simpler but weaker statement. 1 ' 2 

(16:F) There exists either a vector x = [xi, - - - , x m \ in S m with 

m 

(16:19:a) % a(i, j)x f ^0 for i = 1, , n, 

y-i 

or a vector w = {wi, - - , w n \ in S n with 

n 

(16:19:b) J) a(ij)w, ^0 for j = 1, , m. 

i-i 

16.4.4. Consider now a skew symmetric matrix a(i, j), i.e. one which 
coincides with its negative transposed in the sense of 16.4.2. ; i.e. n = m and 

ofe j) = -aQ', for i, j = 1, , n. 

1 The two alternatives (16:19:a), (16:19:b) do not exclude each other: Their conjunc- 
tion is precisely (16:18:c). 

8 This result could also have been obtained directly from the final result of 16.4.1.: 
(16:19:a) is precisely (16:16:a) there, and (16:19:b) is a weakened form of (16:16:b) 
there. We gave the above more detailed discussion because it gives a better insight 
into the entire situation. 



MIXED STRATEGIES. THE SOLUTION 143 

Then the conditions (16:19:a) and (16:19:b) in 16.4.3. express the same 
thing: Indeed, (16:19:b) is 

n 

2) a(i,j)w< ^ 0; 
this may be written 

n n 

n 

We need only write jf, i for i, j l so that this becomes ^ a(i, j)Wj ^ 0, and 

._ ^ ^ n 

then x for 10, l so that we have V a(i, j)xj g 0. And this is precisely 



Therefore we can replace the disjunction of (16:19:a) and (16:19:b) 
by either one of them, say by (16:19:b). So we obtain: 

(16 :G) If the matrix a(i, j) is skew-symmetric (and therefore n = m 


cf. above), then there exists a vector w = {wi, , w n } in 

S n with 



2) a(i,j)wi ^0 for j = 1, , n. 

t-i 

17. Mixed Strategies. The Solution for All Games 
17.1. Discussion of Two Elementary Examples 

17.1.1. In order to overcome the difficulties in the non-strictly determined 
case which we observed particularly in 14.7. it is best to reconsider the 
simplest examples of this phenomenon. These are the games of Matching 
Pennies and of Stone, Paper, Scissors (cf. 14.7.2., 14.7.3.). Since an 
empirical, common-sense attitude with respect to the "problems" of these 
games exists, we may hope to get a clue for the solution of non-strictly 
determined (zero-sum two-person) games by observing and analyzing these 
attitudes. 

It was pointed out that, e.g. in Matching Pennies, no particular way 
of playing i.e. neither playing "heads" nor playing "tails" is any 
better than the other, and all that matters is to find out the opponent's inten- 
tions. This seems to block the way to a solution, since the rules of the 
game in question explicitly bar each player from the knowledge about the 
opponent's actions, at the moment when he has to make his choice. But 

1 Observe that now, with n = m this is only a change in notation ! 



144 ZERO SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

the above observation does not correspond fully to the realities of the case: 
In playing Matching Pennies against an at least moderately intelligent 
opponent, the player will not attempt to find out the opponent's intentions 
but will concentrate on avoiding having his own intentions found out, by 
playing irregularly "heads" and " tails" in successive games. Since we 
wish to describe the strategy in one play indeed we must discuss the course 
in one play and not that of a sequence of successive plays it is preferable 
to express this as follows: The player's strategy consists neither of playing 
"tails" nor of playing "heads," but of playing "tails" with the probability 
of i and "heads" with the probability of . 

17.1.2. One might imagine that in order to play Matching Pennies in a 
rational way the player will before his choice in each play decide by 
some 50:50 chance device whether to play "heads" or "tails." 1 The 
point is that this procedure protects him from loss. Indeed, whatever 
strategy the opponent follows, the player's expectation for the outcome 
of the play will be zero. 2 This is true in particular if with certainty the 
opponent plays "tails," and also if with certainty he plays "heads"; and 
also, finally, if he like the player himself may play both "heads" and 
"tails," with certain probabilities. 3 

Thus, if we permit a player in Matching Pennies to use a "statistical" 
strategy, i.e. to "mix" the possible ways of playing with certain proba- 
bilities (chosen by him), then he can protect himself against loss. Indeed, 
we specified above such a statistical strategy with which he cannot lose, 
irrespective of what his opponent does. The same is true for the opponent, 
i.e. the opponent can use a statistical strategy which prevents the player 
from winning, irrespective of what the player does. 4 

The reader will observe the great similarity of this with the discussions of 
14.5. 5 In the spirit of those discussions it seems legitimate to consider 
zero as the value of a play of Matching Pennies and the 50 : 50 statistical 
mixture of "heads" and "tails" as a good strategy. 

The situation in Paper, Stone, Scissors is entirely similar. Common 
sense will tell that the good way of playing is to play all three alternatives 
with the probabilities of | each. 6 The value of a play as well as the inter- 

1 E.g. he could throw a die of course without letting the opponent see the result 
and then play "tails" if the number of spots showing is even, and "heads" if that num- 
ber is odd. 

1 I.e. his probability of winning equals his probability of losing, because under these 
conditions the probability of matching as well as that of not matching will be J, what- 
ever the opponent's conduct. 

3 Say p, I p. For the player himself we used the probabilities J, J. 

4 All this, of course, in the statistical sense: that the player cannot lose, means that 
his probability of losing is his probability of winning. That he cannot win, means 
that the former is 2 to the latter. Actually each play will be won or lost, since Matching 
Pennies knows no ties. 

We mean specifically (14:C:d), (14:C:e) in 14.5.1. 

A chance device could be introduced as before. The die mentioned in footnote 1, 
above, would be a possible one. E.g. the player could decide "stone" if 1 or 2 spots 
show, "paper" is 3 or 4 spots show, "scissors" if 5 or 6 show. 



MIXED STRATEGIES. THE SOLUTION 145 

pretation of the above strategy as a good one can be motivated as before, 
again in the sense of the quotation there, 1 

17.2. Generalization of This Viewpoint 

17.2.1. It is plausible to try to extend the results found for Matching 
Pennies and Stone, Paper, Scissors to all zero-sum two-person games. 

We use the normalized form, the possible choices of the two players 
being n = 1, , Pi and r 2 = 1, , 2 , and the outcome for player 1 
3C(ri, r 2 ), as formerly. We make no assumption of strict determinateness. 

Let us now try to repeat the procedure which was successful in 17.1. ; i.e. 
let us again visualize players whose "theory" of the game consists not in 
the choice of definite strategies but rather in the choice of several strategies 
with definite probabilities. 2 Thus player 1 will not choose a number 
TI = 1, , pi i.e. the corresponding strategy 2^ but 0i numbers 
i, , iflj the probabilities of these strategies Si, , 2J?, respec- 
tively. Equally player 2 will not choose a number TJ = 1, , 2 i.e. 
the corresponding strategy S but /9 2 numbers iji, , ifo s the proba- 
bilities of these strategies 2' 2 , * ' * > 2|, respectively. Since these prob- 
abilities belong to disjoint but exhaustive alternatives, the numbers T| , *?r, 
are subject to the conditions 

(17:l:a) all ^ fe 0, { T| = 1; 

ri-i 

(17:1 :b) all^^O, ^ = 1. 

r,-l 

and to no others. 



We form the vectors = {1, , &J and ty = {771, , J?0 t }. 

> 

Then the above conditions state that { must belong to Sp^ and rj to S0 t 

in the sense of 16.2.2. 

In this setup a player does not, as previously, choose his strategy, but 
he plays all possible strategies and chooses only the probabilities with which 
he is going to play them respectively. This generalization meets the major 
difficulty of the not strictly determined case to a certain point: We have 
seen that the characteristic of that case was that it constituted a definite 
disadvantage 3 for each player to have his intentions found out by his 

1 In Stone, Paper, Scissors there exists a tie, but no loss still means that the probability 
of losing is ^ the probability of winning, and no gain means the reverse. Cf . footnote 
4 on p. 144. 

8 That these probabilities were the same for all strategies (i, 1 or J, |, i in the exam- 
ples of the last paragraph) was, of course accidental. It is to be expected that this 
equality was due to the symmetric way in which the various alternatives appeared in 
those games. We proceed now on the assumption that the "appearance of probabilities 
in formulating a strategy was the essential thing, while the particular values -were 
accidental. 

'The A > Oof 14.7.1. 



146 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

opponent. Thus one important consideration 1 for a player in such a game 
is to protect himself against having his intentions found out by his opponent. 
Playing several different strategies at random, so that only their probabili- 
ties are determined, is a very effective way to achieve a degree of such 
protection: By this device the opponent cannot possibly find out what the 
player's strategy is going to be, since the player does not know it himself. 2 
Ignorance is obviously a very good safeguard against disclosing information 
directly or indirectly. 

17.2.2. It may now seem that we have incidentally restricted the 
player's freedom of action. It may happen, after all, that he wishes to 
play one definite strategy to the exclusion of all others; or that, while desir- 
ing to use certain strategies with certain probabilities, he wants to exclude 
absolutely the remaining ones. 3 We emphasize that these possibilities are 
perfectly within the scope of our scheme. A player who does not wish to 
play certain strategies at all will simply choose for them the probabilities 
zero. A player who wishes to play one strategy to the exclusion of all 
others will choose for this strategy the probability 1 and for all other 
strategies the probability zero. 

Thus if player 1 wishes to play the strategy 2\i only, he will choose for 
the coordinate vector 6 T i (cf. 16.1.3.). Similarly for player 2, the strategy 

2 and the vectors T? and 6 T . 

> 
In view of all these considerations we call a vector of S$ i or a vector 

ry of S/3 t a statistical or mixed strategy of player 1 or 2, respectively. The 

> 
coordinate vectors 5 T i or 6 T * correspond, as we saw, to the original strategies 

TI or r 2 i.e. 2^i or S^ of player 1 or 2, respectively. We call them strict 
or pure strategies. 

17.3. Justification of the Procedure As Applied to an Individual Play 

17.3.1. At this stage the reader may have become uneasy and perceive 
a contradiction between two viewpoints which we have stressed as equally 
vital throughout our discussions. On the one hand we have always insisted 
that our theory is a static one (cf. 4.8.2.), and that we analyze the course 

1 But not necessarily the only one. 

2 If the opponent has enough statistical experience about the player's " style, " or if 
he is very shrewd in rationalizing his expected behavior, he may discover the probabilities 
frequencies of the various strategies. (We need not discuss whether and how this 
may happen. Cf. the argument of 17.3.1.) But by the very concept of probability 
and randomness nobody under any conditions can foresee what will actually happen in 
any particular case. (Exception must be made for such probabilities as may vanish; 
cf. below.) 

8 In this case he clearly increases the danger of having his strategy found out by the 
opponent. But it may be that the strategy or strategies in question have such intrinsic 
advantages over the others as to make this worth while. This happens, e.g. in an 
extreme form for the "good" strategies of the strictly determined case (cf. 14.5., particu- 
larly (14:C:a), (14:C:b) in 14.5.2.). 



MIXED STRATEGIES. THE SOLUTION 147 

of one play and not that of a sequence of successive plays (cf. 17.1.). But 
on the other hand we have placed considerations concerning the danger of 
one's strategy being found out by the opponent into an absolutely central 
position (cf. 14.4., 14.7.1. and again the last part of 17.2.). How can 
the strategy of a player particularly one who plays a random mixture of 
several different strategies be found out if not by continued observation! 
We have luled out that this observation should extend over many plays. 
Thus it would seem necessary to carry it out in a single play. Now even 
if the rules of the game should be such as to make this possible i.e. if they 
lead to long and repetitious plays the observation would be effected only 
gradually and successively in the course of the play. It would not be avail- 
able at the beginning. And the whole thing would be tied up with various 
dynamical considerations, while we insisted on a static theory ! Besides, 
the rules of the game may not even give such opportunities for observation; 1 
they certainly do not in our original examples of Matching Pennies, and 
Stone, Paper, Scissors. These conflicts and contradictions occur both in the 
discussions of 14. where we used no probabilities in connection with the 
choice of a strategy and in our present discussions of 17. where probabilities 
will be used. 

How are they to be solved? 

17.3.2. Our answer is this: 

To begin with, the ultimate proof of the results obtained in 14. and 17. 
i.e. the discussions of 14.5. and of 17.8. do not contain any of these con- 
flicting elements. So we could answer that our final proofs are correct 
even though the heuristic procedures which lead to them are questionable. 

But even these procedures can be justified. We make no concessions: 
Our viewpoint is static and we are analyzing only a single play. We are 
trying to find a satisfactory theory, at 'this stage for the zero-sum two- 
person game. Consequently we are not arguing deductively from the firm 
basis of an existing theory which has already stood all reasonable tests 
but we are searching for such a theory. 2 Now in doing this, it is perfectly 
legitimate for us to use the conventional tools of logics, and in particular 
that of the indirect proof. This consists in imagining that we have a satis- 
factory theory of a certain desired type, 3 trying to picture the consequences 
of this imaginary intellectual situation, and then in drawing conclusions 
from this as to what the hypothetical theory must be like in detail. If this 
process is applied successfully, it may narrow the possibilities for the hypo- 
thetical theory of the type in question to such an extent that only one 

1 I.e. "gradual," "successive" observations of the behavior of the opponent within 
one play. 

1 Our method is, of course, the empirical one: We are trying to understand, formalize 
and generalize those features of the simplest games which impress us as typical. This is, 
after all, the standard method of all sciences with an empirical basis. 

3 This is full cognizance of the fact that we do not (yet) possess one, and that we 
cannot imagine (yet) what it would be like, if we had one. 

All this is in its own domain no worse than any other indirect proof in any part of 
science (e.g. the per absurdum proofs in mathematics and in physics). 



148 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

possibility is left, i.e. that the theory is determined, discovered by this 
device. 1 Of course, it can happen that the application is even more " suc- 
cessful," and that it narrows the possibilities down to nothing i.e. that it 
demonstrates that a consistent theory of the desired kind is inconceivable. 2 

17.3.3. Let us now imagine that there exists a complete theory of the 
zero-sum two-person game which tells a player what to do, and which is 
absolutely convincing. If the players knew such a theory then each player 
would have to assume that his strategy has been " found out" by his oppo- 
nent. The opponent knows the theory, and he knows that a player would be 
unwise not to follow it. 8 Thus the hypothesis of the existence of a satis- 
factory theory legitimatizes our investigation of the situation when a play- 
er's strategy is " found out" by his opponent. And a satisfactory theory 4 
can exist only if we are able to harmonize the two extremes FI and F 2 , 
strategies of player 1 "found out" or of player 2 "found out." 

For the original treatment free from probability (i.e. with pure strate- 
gies) the extent to which this can be done was determined in 14.5. 

We saw that the strictly determined case is the one where there exists a 
theory satisfactory on that basis. We are now trying to push further, by 
using probabilities (i.e. with mixed strategies). The same device which 
we used in 14.5. when there were no probabilities will do again, the analysis 
of "finding out" the strategy of the other player. 

It will turn out that this time the hypothetical theory can be determined 
completely and in all cases (not merely for the strictly determined case 
cf. 17.5.1., 17.6.). 

After the theory is found we must justify it independently by a direct 
argument. 6 This was done for the strictly determined case in 14.5., and 
we shall do it for the present complete theory in 17.8. 

1 There are several important examples of this performance in physics. The succes- 
sive approaches to Special and to General Relativity or to Wave Mechanics may be 
viewed as such. Cf. A. D'Abro: The Decline of Mechanism in Modern Physics, New 
York 1939. 

1 This too occurs in physics. The N. Bohr-Heisenberg analysis of "quantities which 
are not simultaneously observable " in Quantum Mechanics permits this interpretation. 
Cf . N. Bohr: Atomic Theory and the Description of Nature, Cambridge 1934 and P. A.M. 
Dirac: The Principles of Quantum Mechanics, London 1931, Chap. I. 

8 Why it would be unwise not to follow it is none of our concern at present; we have 
assumed that the theory is absolutely convincing. 

That this is not impossible will appear from our final result. We shall find a theory 
which is satisfactory ; nevertheless it implies that the player's strategy is found out by his 
opponent. But the theory gives him the directions which permit him to adjust himself 
so that this causes no loss. (Cf. the theorem of 17.6. and the discussion of our complete 
solution in 17.8.) 

4 I.e. a theory using our present devices only. Of course we do not pretend to be 
able to make "absolute" statements. If our present requirements should turn out to be 
unfulfillable we should have to look for another basis for a theory. We have actually 
done this once by passing from 14. (with pure strategies) to 17. (with mixed strategies). 

* The indirect argument, as outlined above, gives only necessary conditions. Hence 
it may establish absurdity (per absurdum proof), or narrow down the possibilities to one; 
but in the latter case it is still necessary to show that the one remaining possibility is 
satisfactory. 



MIXED STRATEGIES. THE SOLUTION 149 

17.4. The Minorant and the Majorant Games (For Mixed Strategies) 

17.4.1. Our present picture is then that player 1 chooses an arbitrary 
element from S$ and that player 2 chooses an arbitrary element i? from 

s f , 

Thus if player 1 wishes to play the strategy 2^ only, he will choose for 
the coordinate vector d T i (cf. 16.1.3.) ; similarly for player 2, the strategy 
ZS and the vectors rj and 6 T . 



We imagine again that player 1 makes his choice of in ignorance of 

player 2's choice of y and vice versa. 

The meaning is, of course, that when these choices have been made 
player 1 will actually use (every) TI = 1, , ft\ with the probabilities 
TI and the player 2 will use (every) TI = 1, , 0i with the probabilities 
iy v Since their choices are independent, the mathematical expectation 
of the outcome is 

- > 0i 0t 
(17:2) K( , n ) = 3C(n, n)^,. 

n-lr.-l 

In other words, we have replaced the original game T by a new one of 
essentially the same structure, but with the following formal differencei: 
The numbers n, r 2 the choices of the players are replaced by the vectors 

, q . The function 5C(ri, r 2 ) the outcome, or rather the " mathematical 

> 

expectation " of the outcome of a play is replaced by K( , 17 ). All these 
considerations demonstrate the identity of structure of our present view 
of T with that of 14.1.2., the sole difference being the replacement of 

TI, T 2 , 3C(n, TJ) by , t\ , K( , t\ ), described above. This isomorphism 
suggests the application of the same devices which we used on the original 
T, the comparison with the majorant and minorant games FI and F* as 
described in 14.2., 14.3.1., 14.3.3. 

17.4.2. Thus in TI player 1 chooses his first and player 2 chooses his ij 

afterwards in full knowledge of the chosen by his opponent. In Tj the 

order of their choices is reversed. So the discussion of 14.3.1. applied 


literally. Player 1, choosing a certain , may expect that player 2 will 

choose his /j , so as to minimize K( , 17 ) ; i.e. player Ts choice of leads to 

> 

the value Min~* K( , 17 ). This is a function of alone; hence player 1 

should choose his so as to maximize Min-+ K( , ij ). Thus the value of 
a play of TI is (for player 1) 



150 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

vj = Max- Min-> K(T, 7). 

Similarly the value of a play of F 2 (for player 1) turns out to be 



v' 2 = Min-> Max-* K( , rj ). 

*? f 

(The apparent assumption of rational behavior of the opponent does not 
really matter, since the justifications (14:A:a)-(14:A:e), (14:B:a)-(14:B:e) 
of 14.3.1. and 14.3.3. again apply literally.) 

As in 14.4.1. we can argue that the obvious fact that FI is less favorable 
for player 1 than F 2 constitutes a proof of 



vi 



and that if this is questioned, a rigorous proof is contained in (13 :A*) in 

13.4.3. The x, y, there correspond to our , 17 , K. l If it should happen 
that 



v'i 



then the considerations of 14.5. apply literally. The arguments (14:C:a)- 
(14:C:f), (14:D:a), (14:D:b) loc. cit., determine the concept of a " good" { 
and i? and fix the "value" of a play of (for the player 1) at 

v' = v { = v' 2 . 2 

All this happens by (13:B*) in 13.4.3. if and only if a saddle point of K 

> 
exists. (The x, y, </> there correspond to our , rj , K.) 

17.5. General Strict Determinateness 

17.5.1. We have replaced the YI, v 2 of (14:A:c) and (14:B:c) by our 
present v{, v' 2 , and the above discussion shows that the latter can perform 
the functions of the former. But we are just as much dependent upon 
v[ = v 2 as we were then upon v l = v 2 . It is natural to ask, therefore, 
whether there is any gain in this substitution. 

Evidently this is the case if, as and when there is a better prospect 
of having vj = v' 2 (for any given F) than of having vi = v 2 . We called F 
strictly determined when Vi = v 2 ; it now seems preferable to make a dis- 
tinction and to designate F for Vi = v 2 as specially strictly determined, and 
for vi = v 2 as generally strictly determined. This nomenclature is justified 
only provided we can show that the former implies the latter. 

> -> 
1 Although , 17 are vectors, i.e. sequences of real numbers (1, ,$ and 

'nit ' ' ' 1 10 ) it is perfectly admissible to view each as a single variable in the maxima and 
minima which we are now forming. Their domains are, of course, the sets 8ft , Sft 
which we introduced in 17.2. 

8 For an exhaustive repetition of the arguments in question cf. 17.8. 



MIXED STRATEGIES. THE SOLUTION 151 

This implication is plausible by common sense : Our introduction of mixed 
strategies has increased the player's ability to defend himself against having 
his strategy found out; so it may be expected that vj, v 2 actually lie between 
Vi, v 2 . For this reason one may even assert that 

(17:3) V! ^ vl g v' 2 g v 2 . 

(This inequality secures, of course, the implication just mentioned.) 

To exclude all possibility of doubt we shall give a rigorous proof of 

(17:3). It is convenient to prove this as a corollary of another lemma. 
17.5.2. First we prove this lemma: 

(17:A) For every { in S^ 

-* - ft * 

Min- K( f , r, ) = Min- 3C(n, 



= Min Tj JC(n, 

r^l 


For every 77 in Sp t 

> 0i ft 

Max- K( , 77 ) = Max- 

n-lr.-l 

/5i 
= Max Ti ^ JC(TI, r 2 )r/ Tj . 

r z -l 

Proof: We prove the first formula only ; the proof of the second is exactly 
the same, only interchanging Max and Min as well as ^ and ^ . 

> > , 
Consideration of the special vector r? = 6 T i (cf. 16.1.3. and the end of 

17.2.) gives 

0! ft 01 ft ^1 

Min- rcd^rOfc^g S^i>^)Mv;= Z X ( T1 > r ')k'- 

rj-l T t -l T!-! T 2 = l r, = l 

Since this is true for all r' 2 , so 

01 ft 01 

(17:4:a) Min- ^ JC(n, njfc^ g Min r ; ^ 3C(n, r;)f v 
1 



On the other hand, for all r 2 
ft 



ac(n, 





Given any 77 in S0 8 , multiply this by r\ T ^ and sum over r 2 = 1, 

a 
Since ^ y Ta = 1, therefore 

r.-l 



152 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

ti f t fi 

3C(r,, r t )^ r , Min,, JC(n f r,){ r , 

T!-! r,-l fi-1 

results. Since this is true for all i; , so 

0i 0t fti 

(17:4:b) Min- 3C(n, r.)^*, ^ Min r , % OC(n, r) v 



(17:4:a), (17:4:b) yield together the desired relation. 

If we combine the above formulae with the definition of v'^ v' 2 in 17.4., 
then we obtain 

0i 

(17:5:a) vi = Max- Min Tt K(r l9 T,) V 

(17:5:b) v = Min- Max T ? 






These formulae have a simple verbal interpretation: In computing v' t we 
need only to give player 1 the protection against having his strategy found 

out which lies in the use of (instead of TI) ; player 2 might as well proceed 

in the old way and use r 2 (and not 17 ). In computing vj the roles are inter- 
changed. This is plausible by common-sense: v{ belongs to the game FI 
(cf. 17.4. and 14.2.); there player 2 chooses after player 1 and is fully 
informed about the choice of player 1, hence he needs no protection against 
having his strategy found out by player 1. For vi which belongs to the 
game Tj (cf. id.) the roles are interchanged. 

Now the value of v( becomes ^ if we restrict the variability of in 
the Max of the above formula. Let us restrict it to the vectors = d r '\ 
(rj = !,-,/>!, cf. 16.1.3. and the end of 17.2.). Since 

0i 

X fri, ri)*r/i = 3e(r' lf ri), 
TI-I 

this replaces our expression by 

Max/ Min Tj $(/!, T Z ) = VL 

So we have shown that 

vi ^ v;. 

Similarly (cf . the remark at the beginning of the proof of our lemma above) 
restriction of 77 to the rj = 8 T establishes 

v vj. 



MIXED STRATEGIES. THE SOLUTION 163 

Together with v{ ^ v (cf. 17.4.), these inequalities prove 
(17:3) Vl g v; ^ vi g v f , 

as desired. 

17.6. Proof of the Main Theorem 

17.6. We have established that general strict determinateness (v( = vj) 
holds in all cases of special strict determinateness (vi = v 2 ) us is to be 
expected. That it holds in some further cases as well i.e. that we can 
have Vi = v' 2 but not Vi = v 2 is clear from our discussions of Matching 
Pennies and Stone, Paper, Scissors. 1 Thus we may say, in the sense of 
17.5.1. that the passage from special to general strict determinateness does 
constitute an advance. But for all we know at this moment this advance 
may not cover the entire ground which should be controlled; it could hap- 
pen that certain games F are not even generally strictly determined, i.e. 
we have not yet excluded the possibility 

vl < v 2 . 

If this possibility should occur, then all that was said in 14.7.1. would 
apply again and to an increased extent : finding out one's opponent's strategy 
would constitute a definite advantage 

A' = v 2 - vj > 0, 

and it would be difficult to see how a theory of the game should be con- 
structed without some additional hypotheses as to "who finds out whose 
strategy." 

The decisive fact is, therefore, that it can be shown that this never 
happens. For all games F 

v; = v 2 

i.e. 

(17:6) Max- Min- K(7, "7 ) = Min- Max- K(7, 7), 

or equivalently (again use (13:B*) in 13.4.3. the x, y, <t> there corresponding 

to our , q , K) : A saddle point of K( ( , rj ) exists. 


This is a general theorem valid for all functions K( { , ?? ) of the form 

(17:2) K(7, 7) = | W(TI, r,) r>i . 

Ti-lT,-! 

The coefficients 3C(ri, r t ) are absolutely unrestricted; they form, as described 

* * 
in 14.1.3. a perfectly arbitrary matrix. The variables $ , 17 are really 

1 In both games YI 1, vi 1 (cf. 14.7.2., 14.7.3.), while the discussion of 17.1. 
can be interpreted as establishing v{ vj 0. 



154 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

sequences of real numbers {i, , ^ and rji, , <]^\ their domains 

> 

being the sets S^, S0 t (cf. footnote 1 on p. 150). The functions K( , 1? ) 

of the form (17:2) are called bilinear forms. 

With the help of the results of 16.4.3. the proof is easy. 1 This is it: 
We apply (16:19:a), (16:19:b) in 16.4.3. replacing the i, j, n, m, a(i y j) 

there by our TI, r 2 , 0i, 2, 3C(ri, r 2 ) and the vectors w , x there by our , ry . 


If (16:19:b) holds, then we have a in Sp i with 

0i 

2j 3C(Ti, TI){ TI ^ for r 2 = 1, , |8,, 
n-i 
i.e. with 

0i 

Min Tj J JC(n, r 2 ) T ^ 0. 



Therefore the formula (17:5:a) of 17.5.2. gives 

vl ^ 0. 

If (16:1 9 :a) holds, then we have an rj in Sp 2 with 

0* 
2) 3C(ri, rz)^ ^ for n = 1, , 0,, 

r,-l 

1 This theorem occurred and was proved first in the original publication of one of the 
authors on the theory of games: /. von Neumann: "Zur Theorie der Gesellschaftsspiele," 
Math. Annalen, Vol. 100 (1928), pp. 295-320. 

A slightly more general form of this Min-Max problem arises in another question of 
mathematical economics in connection with the equations of production : 

J. von Neumann: "tlber ein okonomisches Gleichungssystem und eine Verall- 
gemeinerung des Brouwer'schen Fixpunktsatzes," Ergebnisse eines Math. Kolloquiums, 
Vol. 8 (1937), pp. 73-83. 

It seems worth remarking that two widely different problems related to mathe- 
matical economics although discussed by entirely different methods lead to the same 
mathematical problem, and at that to one of a rather uncommon type: The " Min-Max 
type." There may be some deeper formal connections here, as well as in some other 
directions, mentioned in the second paper. The subject should be clarified further. 

The proof of our theorem, given in the first paper, made a rather involved use of 
some topology and of functional calculus. The second paper contained a different proof, 
which was fully topological and connected the theorem with an important device of 
that discipline: the so-called " Fixed Point Theorem" of L. E. J. Brouwer. This aspect 
was further clarified and the proof simplified by S. Kakutani: "A Generalization of 
rtrouwer's Fixed Point Theorem," Duke Math. Journal, Vol. 8 (1941), pp. 457-459. 

All these proofs are definitely non-elementary. The first elementary one was given 
by J. Ville in the collection by E. Borel and collaborators, "Trait6 du Calcul des Prob- 
abilit& et de ses Applications," Vol. IV, 2: "Applications aux Jeux de Hasard," Paris 
(1938), Note by J. Ville: "Sur la Theorie G6ne>ale des Jeux ou intervient THabilete* des 
Joueurs," pp. 105-113. 

The proof which we are going to give carries the elementarization initiated by 
/. Ville further, and seems to be particularly simple. The key to the procedure is, of 
course, the connection with the theory of convexity in 16. and particularly with the 
results of 16.4.3. 



MIXED STRATEGIES. THE SOLUTION 155 

i.e. with 

ft* 
Max T 3e(n, r 2 )i7 T ^ 0. 



Therefore the formula (17:5:b) of 17.5.2. gives 

v' 2 ^ 0. 

So we see: Either vi ^ or v' 2 ^ 0, i.e. 
(17:7) Never vi < < v' 2 . 

Now choose an arbitrary number w and replace the function 3C(ri, r 2 ) 
byJC(n, r 2 ) - w. 1 

- _ > 0i 0* > > 

This replaces K( , T; ) by K( , T; ) w ^ ] TI TJ V that is as , 17 

r, = l r, = l 
01 02 _ _ 

lie in S^, fi^ and so TI = ^ 77^ = 1 by K( , TJ ) w. Consequently 

T!-! r,-l 

vj, v 2 are replaced by vi w, v' 2 w. 2 Therefore application of (17:7) to 
these vi w, v' 2 w gives 

(17:8) Never vi < w < v' 2 . 

Now w was perfectly arbitrary. Hence for vi < v' 2 it would be possible 
to choose w with vi < w < v' 2 thus contradicting (17:8). So vi < v' 2 is 
impossible, and we have proved that vi = v 2 as desired. This completes 
the proof. 

17.7. Comparison of the Treatments by Pure and by Mixed Strategies 

17.7.1. Before going further let us once more consider the meaning of 
the result of 

The essential feature of this is that we have always v{ = v 2 but not always 
Vi = v 2 , i.e. always general strict determinateness, but not always special 
strict determinateness (cf. the beginning of 17.6.). 

Or, to express it mathematically : 

We have always 

(17:9) Max- Min- K(7, 7) = Min- Max- K(7, 7), 

, 6 v n 

1 I.e. the game T is replaced by a new one which is played in precisely the same way as 
T except that at the end player 1 gets less (and player 2 gets more) by the fixed amount w 
than in T. 

2 This is immediately clear if we remember the interpretation of the preceding 
footnote. 



156 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

i.e. 

(17:10) Max-Min- SC^rj)^ - 

0i ft* 
Min-+Max-> V T 

n * ^ ^ 

Using (17:A) we may even write for this 

(17:11) Max^Min rt ^ 3C(n,r 2 ) ri = Min^ Max, t % 3C(n,T 2 )i? v 

But we do not always have 

(17:12) Max T| Min^^COn, r 2 ) = Min Ti Max Tj 3C(ri, r 2 ). 

Let us compare (17:9) and (17:12): (17:9) is always true and (17:12) 


is not. Yet the difference between these is merely that of , ij , K and n, n, 

3C. Why does the substitution of the former for the latter convert the 
untrue assertion (17:12) into the true assertion (17:9)? 

The reason is that the5C(ri, r a ) of (17:12) is a perfectly arbitrary func- 
tion of its variables n, r 2 (cf. 14.1.3.), while the K( , rj ) of (17:9) is an 

> > 
extremely special function of its variables , ij i.e. of the i, , & 

Vi; ' * * t *?/v name ly a bilinear form. (Cf. the first part of 17.6.) Thus 
the absolute generality of JC(TI, r 2 ) renders any proof of (17:12) impossible, 

while the special bilinear form nature of K( , rj ) provides the basis for 
the proof of (17:9), as given in 17.6. l 


17.7.2. While this is plausible it may seem paradoxical that K( , q) 

should be more special than 3C(ri, r 2 ), although the former obtained from 
the latter by a process which bore all the marks of a generalization: We 
obtained it by the replacement of our original strict concept of a pure 
strategy by the mixed strategies, as described in 17.2.; i.e. by the replace- 
ment of n, r 2 by , 17 . 

But a closer inspection dispels this paradox. K( , i\ ) is a very special 
function when compared with 3C(ri, r 2 ) ; but its variables have an enormously 

1 That the K( , 17 ) is a bilinear form is due to our use of the " mathematical expecta- 
tion " wherever probabilities intervene. It seems significant that the linearity of this 
concept is connected with the existence of a solution, in the sense in which we found one. 
Mathematically this opens up a rather interesting perspective: One might investigate 
which other concepts, in place of "mathematical expectation, 1 ' would not interfere with 
our solution, i.e. with the result of 17.6. for zero-sum two-person games. 

The concept of "mathematical expectation " is clearly a fundamental one in many 
ways. Its significance from the point of view of the theory of utility was brought forth 
particularly in 3.7.1. 



MIXED STRATEGIES. THE SOLUTION 157 

wider domain than the previous variables n, r 2 . Indeed T\ had the finite 

set (1, , pi) for its domain, while varies over the set S^, which is a 

(Pi l)-dimensional surface in the 0i-dimensional linear space S^ (cf. the 

> 
end of 16.2.2. and 17.2.). Similarly for r 2 and rj . l 

There are actually among the in S fti special points which correspond 
to the various TI in (1, , 0i). Given such a r\ we can form (as in 

16.1.3. and at the end of 17.2.) the coordinate vector = 6 T i, expressing 
the choice of the strategy S^ to the exclusion of all others. We can corre- 

late special rj in S^ with the r 2 in (1, , fit) in the same way: Given such 

> 
a T 2 we can form the coordinate vector rj = 6 r , expressing the choice of the 

strategy 2 2 to the exclusion of all others. 
Now clearly: 



SCW, T'I) *,**, 

I /-I 

, r 2 ). 2 


Thus the function K( , T; ) contains, in spite of its special character, the 

entire function 3C(ri, r 2 ) and it is therefore really the more general concept 
of the two, as it ought to be. It is actually more than 3C(ri, r 2 ) since not all 

, 77 are of the special form 6 r , 5 %, not all mixed strategies are pure.* 
One could say that K( , 17 ) is the extension of 3C(ri, r 2 ) from the narrower 

domain of the ri,r 2 i.e.ofthe 5 T i, 6 r to the wider domain of the , rj i.e. 
to all of Sp , Sp t from the pure strategies to the mixed strategies. The fact 

that K( , TJ ) is a bilinear form expresses merely that this extension is carried 
out by linear interpolation. That it is this process which must be used, is 
of course due to the linear character of " mathematical expectation/* 4 

1 Observe that = | i, , t l with the components TI , n = !, , 0i, also 
contains r\ ; but there is a fundamental difference. In 3C(n, TJ), r\ itself is a variable. In 

K( , 17 ), is a variable, while n is, so to say, a variable within the variable. is 
actually a function of TI (cf. the end of 16.1.2.) and this function as such is the variable 

of K( , q ). Similarly for r 2 and T; . 

> 

Or, in terms of n, r 2 : 3C(n, r*) is a function of n, TJ while K( , 17 ) is a function 
of functions of n, * 2 (in the mathematical terminology : a functional). 

2 The meaning of this formula is apparent if we consider what choice of strategies 
> > 

d r i, 5 r represent. 

8 I.e. several strategies may be used effectively with positive probabilities. 
4 The fundamental connection between the concept of numerical utility and the linear 
" mathematical expectation" was pointed out at the end of 3.7.1. 



158 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

17.7.3, Reverting to (17:9)-(17:12), we see now that we can express the 
truth of (17:9)-(17-11) and the untruth of (17:12) as follows: 

(17:9), (17:10) express that each player is fully protected against having 
his strategy found out by his opponent if he can use the mixed strategies 

, ij instead of the pure strategies n, r 2 . (17:11) states that this remains 
true if the player who finds out his opponent's strategy uses the T\, r 2 
while only the player whose strategy is being found out enjoys the pro- 
tection of the , r; . The falsity of ( 1 7 : 1 2) , finally, shows that both players 

and particularly the player whose strategy happens to be found out may 

> > 
not forego with impunity the protection of the { , rj . 

17.8. Analysis of General Strict Determinateness 

17.8.1. We shall now reformulate the contents of 14.5. as mentioned 
at the end of 17.4. with particular consideration of the fact established 
in 17.6. that every zero-sum two-person game F is generally strictly deter- 
mined. Owing to this result we may define: 

v' = Max- Min- K(7,7) = Min- Max- K(7, 7) 
= Sa-|-K(7, 7). 

(Cf. also (13 :C*) in 13.5.2. and the end of 13.4.3.) 

Let us form two sets A, B subsets of S^, S/^, respectively in analogy 
to the definition of the sets A, B in (14:D:a), (14:D:b) of 14.5.1. These 
are the sets A+, B+ of 13.5.1. (the </> corresponding to our K). We define: 

(17:B:a) A is the set of those (in Sp ) for which Min- K( , y ) 

*> 

assumes its maximum value, i.e. for which 

Min- K(7, 7) = Max- Min- K(7, 7) = V. 
* { * 

(17:B:b) B is the set of those 77 (in Sp t ) for which Max- K( , 7) 

assumes its minimum value, i.e. for which 

Max-^ K(7, 7) = Min- Max- K(7, 7) = V. 

It is now possible to repeat the argumentation of 14.5. 

In doing this we shall use the homologous enumeration for the assertions 
(14:C:a)-(14:C:f)asinl4.5. 1 

1 (a)-(f) will therefore appear in an order different from the natural one. This was 
equally true in 14.5., since the enumeration there was based upon that of 14.3.1., 14.3.3., 
and the argumentation in those paragraphs followed a somewhat different route. 



MIXED STRATEGIES. THE SOLUTION 159 

We observe first: 

(17:C:d) Player 1 can, by playing appropriately, secure for himself 

a gain ^ v', irrespective of what player 2 does. 

Player 2 can, by playing appropriately, secure for himself 
a gain ^ v', irrespective of what player 1 does. 

Proof: Let player 1 choose { from A ; then irrespective of what player 2 

does, i.e. for every T; we have K( , y ) ^ Min->K( { , rj ) = v'. Let player 

i? 

2 choose rj from B. Then irrespective of what player 1 does, i.e. for every 


, we have K( , 77 ) g Max-> K( { , rj ) = v'. This completes the proof. 

Second, (17:C:d) is clearly equivalent to this: 

(17:C:e) Player 2 can, by playing appropriately, make it sure that 

the gain of player 1 is ^ v', i.e. prevent him from gaining 

> v', irrespective of what player 1 does. 

Player 1 can, by playing appropriately, make it sure that 
the gain of player 2 is ^ v', i.e. prevent him from gaining 

> v', irrespective of what player 2 does. 

17.8.2. Third, we may now assert on the basis of (17:C:d) and (17:C:e) 
and of the considerations in the proof of (17:C:d) that: 

(17:C:a) The good way (combination of strategies) for 1 to play 

the game F is to choose any belonging to A, A being the set 
of (17:B:a) above. 
(17:C:b) The good way (combination of strategies) for 2 to play 

the game F is to choose any rj belonging to 5, B being the set 
of (17:B:b) above. 

Fourth, combination of the assertions of (17:C:d) or equally well 
of those of (17:C:e) gives: 

(17:C:c) If both players 1 and 2 play the game F well i.e. if { 

belongs to A and ij belongs to B then the value of K( , rj ) 
will be equal to the value of a play (for 1), i.e. to v'. 

We add the observation that (13:D*) in 13.5.2. and the remark concerning 
the sets A, B before (17:B:a), (17:B:b) above give together this: 


(17:C:f) Both players 1 and 2 play the game F well i.e. { belongs 

to A and t; belongs to B if and only if , rj is a saddle point 
of K(7, 7)-! 



160 



ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 



All this should make it amply clear that v' may indeed be interpreted 
as the value of a play of F (for 1), and that A, B contain the good ways of 
playing T for 1, 2, respectively. There is nothing heuristic or uncertain 
about the entire argumentation (17:C:a)-(17:C:f). We have made no 
extra hypotheses about the " intelligence " of the players, about "who 
has found out whose strategy" etc. Nor are our results for one player 
based upon any belief in the rational conduct of the other, a point the 
importance of which we have repeatedly stressed. (Cf. the end of 4.1.2.; 
also 15.8.3.) 

17.9. Further Characteristics of Good Strategies 

17.9.1. The last results (17 :C:c) and (17:C:f) in 17.8.2. give also a 
simple explicit characterization of the elements of our present solution, 
i.e. of the number v' and of the vector sets A and B. 

By (17:C:c) loc. cit., A, B determine v'; hence we need only study A, 
B, and we shall do this by means of (17:C:f) id. 

According to that criterion, belongs to A, and t\ belongs to B if and 
only if , i? is a saddle point of K( , rj ). This means that 

Max- K(7', 7 

Min- K(T, 7' 

We make this explicit by using the expression (17:2) of 17.4.1. and 
17.6. for K( , 17 ), and the expressions of the lemma (17:A) of 17.5.2. for 
Max-*, K( ', if) and Min- K( , y ') Then our equations become: 

I' V 



Max T 



r.-lr.-l 



ac(r lf 



Considering that ^ TI = 

r,-! ' 





Tj 1 



[Max r ; 
[-Min r ; { ^ 



X 

T t 1 



Min T ' 

, we can also write for these 
* _ 

. ^^ fin t \ It ^s 

r,-l 



r, - 1 r t - 1 

Now on the left-hand side of these equations the v tj Tf have coefficients 
which are all ^ O. 1 The TI , T7 Tf themselves are also ^ 0. Hence these 
1 Observe how the Max and Min occur there! 



MIXED STRATEGIES. THE SOLUTION 181 

equations hold only when all terms of their left hand sides vanish separately. 
I.e. when for each n = 1,. , $\ for which the coefficient is not zero, we 
have r = 0; and for each r* = 1, , fa for which the coefficient is not 
zero, we have T/ TI = 0. 
Summing up; 

(17 :D) belongs to A and rj belongs to B if and only if these 

are true: 

0t 

For each n = 1, , 0i, for which JC(TI, T Z )rj Tl does 

r,-l 

not assume its maximum (in n) we have TI = 0. 

0i 
For each r 2 = 1, , ft, for which OC(ri, T 2 ) ri does 

n-i 
not assume its minimum (in r 2 ) we have r; Tj = 0. 

It is easy to formulate these principles verbally. They express this: If 
, 77 are good mixed strategies, then excludes all strategies T\ which are 
not optimal (for player 1) against t\ , and rj excludes all strategies r 2 which 

are not optimal (for player 2) against ; i.e. , rj are as was to be 
expected optimal against each other. 

17.9.2. Another remark which may be made at this point is this: 

(17 :E) The game is specially strictly determined if and only if there 

exists for each player a good strategy which is a pure strategy. 

In view of our past discussions, and particularly of the process of gen- 
eralization by which we passed from pure strategies to mixed strategies, 
this assertion may be intuitively convincing. But we shall also supply a 
mathematical proof, which is equally simple. This is it : 

We saw in the last part of 17.5.2. that both Vi and v\ obtain by applying 

fe -* 

Max-> to Min Tj 2) & ( T I> T*)^* only with different domains for : The set 

* \-i 

of all 5 T i (TI = 1, , 00 for YI, and all of 8^ for vi; i.e. the pure strategies 
in the first case, and the mixed ones in the second. Hence Vi = v\, i.e. 
the two maxima are equal if and only if the maximum of the second domain 
is assumed (at least once) within the first domain. This means by (17 :D) 
above that (at least) one pure strategy must belong to A, i.e. be a good one. 
I.e. 

(17:F:a) Vi = vi if and only if there exists for player 1 a good 

strategy which is a pure strategy. 



162 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

Similarly: 

(17:F:b) V2 = v if and only if there exists for player 2 a good 

strategy which is a pure strategy. 

Now vj = v' 2 v' and strict determinateness means Vi = V2 = v', 
i.e. vi = v; and v 2 = v. So (17:F:a), (17:F:b) give together (17:E). 

17.10. Mistakes and Their Consequences. Permanent Optimality 

17.10.1. Our past discussions have made clear what a good mixed 
strategy is. Let us now say a few words about the other mixed strategies. 
We want to express the distance from " goodness" for those strategies (i.e. 

vectors { , rj ) which are not good; and to obtain some picture of the conse- 
quences of a mistake i.e. of the use of a strategy which is not good. How- 
ever, we shall not attempt to exhaust this subject, which has many intriguing 
ramifications. 

For any in S0 i and any ?? in S0 2 we form the numerical functions 
(17:13:a) a(7) = V - Min- K(T, 7), 






(17:13:b) 0() = Max- K(, ) - V. 

By the lemma (17 :A) of 17.5.2. equally 

-> * 

(17:13**) ( O V - Min Tj % 3C(n, T,)$ TI> 

T t -l 
- * 

(17:13:b*) ft( *) = Max,, V jc(n, r^ - v ; . 

r,-l 

The definition 

v' = Max- Min- K(7, 7) = Min- Max- K(7, 7) 
guarantees that always 

(7) ^ 0, 0(7) ^ 0. 

And now (17:B:a), (17:B:b) and (17:C:a), (17:C:b) in 17.8. imply that 7 

is good if and only if a( ) =0, and ij is good if and only if 0( 77 ) =0. 

> > > 

Thus a( ^)jft(r)) are convenient numerical measures for the general { , 77 

expressing their distance from goodness. The explicit verbal formulation 

> 
of what a( ), 0( t\ ) are, makes this interpretation even more plausible: The 

formulae (17:13:a), (17:13:b) or (17:13:a*), (17:13:b*) above make clear 



MIXED STRATEGIES. THE SOLUTION 163 

how much of a loss the player risks relative to the value of a play for him 1 
by using this particular strategy. We mean here "risk" in the sense 

of the worst that can happen under the given conditions. 2 

> 

It must be understood, however, that a( ( ), 0( i? ) do not disclose which 
strategy of the opponent will inflict this (maximum) loss upon the player who 

> 
is using { or rj . It is, in particular, not at all certain that if the opponent 

uses some particular good strategy, i.e. an 17 in 5 or a o in A, this in itself 

> 
implies the maximum loss in question. If a (not good) or rj is used by the 


player, then the maximum loss will occur for those 17 ' or { ' of the opponent, 

for which 



K(, ') = Min 7 K(, ), 
K(7, 7) = Max K(7, 7), 



i.e. if 17 ' is optimal against the given , or ' optimal against the given 17 . 

> 
And we have never ascertained whether any fixed 17 o or { can be optimal 

^ 
against all or 77 . 



17.10.2. Let us therefore call an TJ ' or a ' which is optimal against all 

7 or 7 i.e. which fulfills (17:14:a), or (17:14:b) in 17.10.1. for all 7, 7~ 

permanently optimal. Any permanently optimal 17 ' or ' is necessarily 
good; this should be clear conceptually and an exact proof is easy. 8 But 

1 I.e. we mean by loss the value of the play minus the actual outcome: v' K( , q ) 

> > > 

for player 1 and (-v') - (~K( , 77 )) = K( , 17 ) - v' for player 2. 
' 2 Indeed, using the previous footnote and (17:13:a), (17:13:b) 

(7) - V - Min-. K(T, 7) = Max- (v' - K(7, 7)1, 

1? 1 

3(7) = Max- K(7, 7) - V = Max- |K(7, 7) - v'|. 

I.e. each is a maximum loss. 



8 Proof: It suffices to show this for rj ' ; the proof for ' is analogous. 

Let 77 'be permanently optimal. Choose a * which is optimal against 17', i.e. with 

K(T',V) = Max-K(7, 7) 
By definition 

K(7*. 7) = Min- K(7*. 7). 

If 
> 

Thus | *, 17' is a saddle point of K( , 17 ) and therefore V belongs to B i.e. it is good 
by (17:C:f) in 17.8.2. 



164 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

the question remains: Are all good strategies also permanently optimal? 
And even: Do any permanently optimal strategies exist? 

In general the answer is no. Thus in Matching Pennies or in Stone, 

Paper, Scissors, the only good strategy (for player 1 as well as for player 2) is 
^ 
f = rj = (i, i) or {i, |, i} , respectively. 1 If player 1 played differently 

e.g. always " heads " 2 or always " stone" 2 then he would lose if the oppo- 
nent countered by playing " tails" 3 or "paper." 3 But then the opponent's 
strategy is not good i.e. {, ?} or (i, i, }, respectively either. If the 
opponent played the good strategy, then the player's mistake would not 
matter. 4 

We shall get another example of this in a more subtle and complicated 
way in connection with Poker and the necessity of " bluffing," in 19.2 and 
19.10.3. 

All this may be summed up by saying that while our good strategies 
are perfect from the defensive point of view, they will (in general) not get 
the maximum out of the opponent's (possible) mistakes, i.e. they are not 
calculated for the offensive. 

It should be remembered, however, that our deductions of 17.8. are 
nevertheless cogent; i.e. a theory of the offensive, in this sense, is not 
possible without essentially new ideas. The reader who is reluctant to 
accept this, ought to visualize the situation in Matching Pennies or in 
Stone, Paper, Scissors once more; the extreme simplicity of these two 
games makes the decisive points particularly clear. 

Another caveat against overemphasizing this point is: A great deal 
goes, in common parlance, under the name of "offensive," which is not at 
all "offensive" in the above sense, i.e. which is fully covered by our pres- 
ent theory. This holds for all games in which perfect information prevails, 
as will be seen in 17. 10.3. 6 Also such typically "aggressive" operations (and 
which are necessitated by imperfect information) as "bluffing" in Poker. 6 

17.10.3. We conclude by remarking that there is an important class of 
(zero-sum two-person) games in which permanently optimal strategies 
exist. These are the games in which perfect information prevails, which 
we analyzed in 15. and particularly in 15.3.2., 15.6., 15.7. Indeed, a small 
modification of the proof of special strict determinateness of these games, as 
given loc. cit., would suffice to establish this assertion too. It would give 
permanently optimal pure strategies. But we do not enter upon these con- 
siderations here. 

1 Cf. 17.1. Any other probabilities would lead to losses when " found out." Cf. below. 
'This is = * ' (1, 0) or (1, 0, 0), respectively. 

* This is i? - S" - (0, 1) or {0, 1, 0), respectively. 

4 I.e. the bad strategy of " heads " (or "stone 1 ') can be defeated only by "tails" (or 
"paper"), which is just as bad in itself. 

1 Thus Chess and Backgammon are included. 

The preceding discussion applies rather to the failure to "bluff." Cf. 19.2. and 
19.10.3. 



MIXED STRATEGIES. THE SOLUTION 165 

Since the games in which perfect information prevails are always spe- 
cially strictly determined (cf. above), one may suspect a more fundamental 
connection between specially strictly determined games and those in which 
permanently optimal strategies exist (for both players). We do not intend 
to discuss these things here any further, but mention the following facts 
which are relevant in this connection: 

(17 :G :a) It can be shown that if permanently optimal strategies exist 

(for both players) then the game must be specially strictly 

determined. 

(17:G:b) It can be shown that the converse of (17:G:a) is not true. 

(17:G:c) Certain refinements of the concept of special strict deter- 

minateness seem to bear a closer relationship to the existence 

of permanently optimal strategies. 

17.11. The Interchange of Players. Symmetry 

17.11.1. Let us consider the role of symmetry, or more generally the 
effects of interchanging the players 1 and 2 in the game F. This will 
naturally be a continuation of the analysis of 14.6. 

As was pointed out there, this interchange of the players replaces the 

function OC(T!, r 2 ) by -3C(r 2 , n). The formula (17:2) of 17.4.1. and 17.G. 

> 

shows that the effect of this for K( { , TJ ) is to replace it by K( r; , { ). In 

the terminology of 16.4.2., we replace the matrix (of 5C(ri, r 2 ) cf. 14.1.3.) by 
its negative transposed matrix. 

Thus the perfect analogy of the considerations in 14. continues; again 
we have the same formal results as there, provided that we replace 

TI, r 2 , 3C(ri, T 2 ) by , rj , K( f , T; ). (Cf. the previous occurrence of this 
in 17.4. and 17.8.) 

We saw in 14.6. that this replacement of 3C(ri, r 2 ) by 3C(r 2 , n) carries 
Vi, v 2 into v 2 , VL A literal repetition of those considerations shows 

now that the corresponding replacement of K( , 77 ) by K( 17 , ) 
carries vj, v 2 into v' 2 , vj. Summing up: Interchanging the players 1, 2, 
carries Vi, v 2 , v' lt v' 2 into v 2 , Vi, v' 2 , v' t . 

The result of 14.6. established for (special) strict determinateness was 
that v = Vi = v 2 is carried into v = Vi = v 2 . In the absence of 
that property no such refinement of the assertion was possible. 

At the present we know that we always have general strict deter- 
minateness, so that v' = v'i = v 2 . Consequently this is carried into 



Verbally the content of this result is clear: Since we succeeded in defining 
a satisfactory concept of the value of a play of F (for the player 1), v', it is 
only reasonable that this quantity should change its sign when the roles 
of the players are interchanged. 

17.11.2. We can also state rigorously when the game F is symmetric. 
This is the case when the two players 1 and 2 have precisely the same 



166 ZERO SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

role in it, i.e. if the game F is identical with that game which obtains 
from it by interchanging the two players 1, 2. According to what was said 
above, this means that 

JC(n, TI) = -JC(r, TI), 
or equivalently that 

K(T,7) = -x(7,7). 

This property of the matrix 3C(ri, r 2 ) or of the bilinear form K( { , rj ) was 
introduced in 16.4.4. and called skew-symmetry. 1 ' 2 

In this case Vi, v 2 must coincide with v 2 , Vi; hence Vi = v 2 , 
and since Vi ^ v 2 , so Vi ^ 0. But v' must coincide with v'; therefore 
we can even assert that 

v' = O. 8 

So we see: The value of each play of a symmetrical game is zero. 

It should be noted that the value v' of each play of a game F could be 
zero without F being symmetric. A game in which v' = will be called 
fair. 

The examples of 14.7.2., 14.7.3. illustrate this: Stone, Paper, Scissors is 
symmetric (and hence fair); Matching Pennies is fair (cf. 17.1.) without 
being symmetric. 4 

> 

1 For a matrix 3C(n, r 2 ) or for the corresponding bilinear form K( , 77 ) symmetry 
is defined by 

3C(n, T j) = X(r 2 , TI), 
or equivalently by 



It is remarkable that symmetry of the game F is equivalent to skew-symmetry, and not to 
symmetry, of its matrix or bilinear form. 

1 Thus skew-symmetry means that a reflection of the matrix scheme of Fig. 15 in 
14.1.3. on its main diagonal (consisting of the fields (1, 1), (2, 2), etc.) carries it into its 
own negative. (Symmetry, in the sense of the preceding footnote, would mean that it 
carries it into itself.) 

Now the matrix scheme of Fig. 15 is rectangular; it has 2 columns and /3i rows. In 
the case under consideration its shape must be unaltered by this reflection. Hence it 
must be quadratic, i.e. 0i = # 2 . This is so, however, automatically, since the players 
1, 2 are assumed to have the same role in r. 

3 This is, of course, due to our knowing that v\ = v 2 . Without this i.e. without 
the general theorem (16:F) of 16.4.3. we should assert for the vj, v 2 only the same which 
we obtained above for the Vi, v 2 :vj = vj and since vj ^ v^, sov\ ^ 0. 

4 The players 1 and 2 have different roles in Matching Pennies: 1 tries to match, 
and 2 tries to avoid matching. Of course, one has a feeling that this difference is inessen- 
tial and that the fairness of Matching Pennies is due to this inessentiality of the assyme- 
try. This could be elaborated upon, but we do not wish to do this on this occasion. A 
better example of fairness without symmetry would be given by a game which is grossly 
unsymmetric, but in which the advantages and disadvantages of each player are so 
judiciously adjusted that a fair game i.e. value v' = results. 

A not altogether successful attempt at such a game is the ordinary way of " Rolling 
Dice." In this game player 1 the " player " rolls two dice, each of which bear the 
numbers 1, , 6. Thus at each roll any total 2, ,12 may result. These totals 



MIXED STRATEGIES. THE SOLUTION 167 

In a symmetrical game the sets A, S of (17:B:a), (17:B:b) in 17.8. are 

obviously identical. Since A = B we may put = T\ in the final criterion 
(17:D) of 17.9. We restate it for this case: 

(17:H) In a symmetrical game, belongs to A if and only if this is 

(*i 

true: For each r 2 = 1, 0* for which ^ 3C(ri, T 2 ) ri does 

r,-l 

not assume its minimum (in r 2 ) we have T = 0. 
Using the terminology of the concluding remark of 17.9., we see that the 

above condition expresses this: { is optimal against itself . 

17.11.3. The results of 17.11.1., 17.11.2. that in every symmetrical 
game v' = can be combined with (17:C:d) in 17.8. Then we obtain 
this: 

(17:1) In a symmetrical game each player can, by playing appropri- 

ately, avoid loss 1 irrespective of what the opponent does. 

We can state this mathematically as follows : 

If the matrix 3C(n, r 2 ) is skew-symmetric, then there exists a vector 



n 



with 



for 



r 2 = 



This could also have been obtained directly, because it coincides with 
the last result (16 :G) in 16.4.4. To see this it suffices to introduce there 
our present notations: Replace the i, j, a(i, j) there by our r\ t r 2 , X(n, r 2 ) 

and the w there by our { . 
have the following probabilities: 



Total ..... 


2 


3 


4 


5 


6 


7 


8 


9 


10 


11 


12 


Chance out of 36 


1 


2 


3 


4 


5 


6 


5 


4 


3 


2 


1 


Probability 


A 


A 


A 


A 


A 


A 


A 


A 


A 


A 


A 



The rule is that if the " player " rolls 7 or 11 (''natural") he wins. If he rolls 2, 3, or 12 
he loses. If he rolls anything else (4, 5, 6, or 8, 9, 10) then he rolls again until he rolls 
either a repeat of the original one (in which case he wins), or a 7 (in which case he loses). 
Player 2 (the "house") has no influence on the play. 

In spite of the great differences of the rules as they affect players 1 and 2 (the 
"player" and the "house") their chances are nearly equal: A simple computation, which 
we do not detail, shows that the "player" has 244 chances against 251 for the "house," 
out of a total of 495; i.e. the value of a play played for a unit stake is 



244 - 251 
495 



--- 1.414%. 



Thus the approximation to fairness is reasonably good, and it may be questioned whether 
more was intended. 

1 I.e. secure himself a gain * 0. 



168 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: THEORY 

It is even possible to base our entire theory on this fact, i.e. to derive 
the theorem of 17.6. from the above result. In other words: The general 
strict determinateness of all F can be derived from that one of the symmetric 
ones. The proof has a certain interest of its own, but we shall not discuss 
it here since the derivation of 17.6. is more direct. 

The possibility of protecting oneself against loss (in a symmetric game) 

exists only due to our use of the mixed strategies , ij (cf. the end of 17.7.). 
If the players are restricted to pure strategies TI, r 2 then the danger of having 
one's strategy found out, and consequently of sustaining losses, exists. 
To see this it suffices to recall what we found concerning Stone, Paper, 
Scissors (cf. 14.7. and 17.1.1.). We shall recognize the same fact in con- 
nection with Poker and the necessity of "bluffing" in 19.2.1. 



CHAPTER IV 
ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 

18. Some Elementary Games 
18.1. The Simplest Games 

18.1.1. We have concluded our general discussion of the zero-sum two- 
person game. We shall now proceed to examine specific examples of such 
games. These examples will exhibit better than any general abstract 
discussions could, the true significance of the various components of our 
theory. They will show, in particular, how some formal steps which are 
dictated by our theory permit a direct common-sense interpretation. It 
will appear that we have here a rigorous formalization of the main aspects 
of such "practical" and "psychological" phenomena as those to be men- 
tioned in 19.2., 19.10. and 19.16. 1 

18.1.2. The size of the numbers 0i, 2 i.e. the number of alternatives 
confronting the two players in the normalized form of the game gives a 
reasonable first estimate for the degree of complication of the game F. 
The case that either, or both, of these numbers is 1 may be disregarded: This 
would mean that the player in question has no choice at all by which he can 
influence the game. 2 Therefore the simplest games of the class which 
interests us are those with 

(18:1) 0i = fa = 2. 

We saw in 14.7. that Matching Pennies is such a game; its matrix scheme 
was given in Figure 12 in 13.4.1. Another instance of such a game is Figure 
14, id. 





1 


2 


1 


3C(1, 1) 


3C(1,2) 


2 


3C(2, 1) 


3C(2, 2) 



Figure 27. 

Let us now consider the most general game falling under (18:1), i.e. 
under Figure 27. This applies, e.g., to Matching Pennies if the various ways 
of matching do not necessarily represent the same gain (or a gain at all), 

1 We stress this because of the widely held opinion that these things are congenitally 
unfit for rigorous (mathematical) treatment. 

1 Thus the game would really be one of one person; but then, of course, no longer of 
zero sum. Cf. 12,2. 

169 



170 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 

nor the various ways of not matching the same loss (or a loss at all). 1 We 
propose to discuss for this case the results of 17.8., the value of the game F 
and the sets of good strategies 4, 5. These concepts have been established 
by the general existential proof of 17.8. (based on the theorem of 17.6.); 
but we wish to obtain them again by explicit computation in this special 
case, and thereby gain some further insight into their functioning and their 
possibilities. 

18.1.3. There are certain trivial adjustments which can be made on 
a game given by Figure 27, and which simplify an exhaustive discussion 
considerably. 

First it is quite arbitrary which of the two choices of player 1 we denote 
by TI = 1 and by TI = 2; we may interchange these, i.e. the two rows of 
the matrix. 

Second, it is equally arbitrary which of the two choices of player 2 we 
denote by TI = 1 and by r 2 = 2; we may interchange these, i.e. the two 
columns of the matrix. 

Finally, it is also arbitrary which of the two players we call 1 and which 
2; we may interchange these, i.e. replace 5C(ri, r 2 ) by 3C(ri, r 2 ) (cf. 14.6. 
and 17.11.). This amounts to interchanging the rows and the columns 
of the matrix, and changing the sign of its elements besides. 

Putting everything together, we have here 2X2X2 = 8 possible 
adjustments, all of which describe essentially the same game. 

18.2. Detailed Quantitative Discussion of These Games 

18.2.1. We proceed now to the discussion proper. This will consist 
in the consideration of several alternative possibilities, the "Cases" to be 
enumerated below. 

These Cases are distinguished by the various possibilities which exist 
for the positions of those fields of the matrix where X(TI, r 2 ) assumes its 
maximum and its minimum for both variables n, r 2 together. Their 
delimitations may first appear to be arbitrary; but the fact that they 
lead to a quick cataloguing of all possibilities justifies them ex post. 

Consider accordingly Max VTj 3C(ri, r 2 ) and Min VTj JC(ri, r 2 ). Each 
one of these values will be assumed at least once and might be assumed more 
than once; 2 but this does not concern us at this juncture. We begin now 
with the definition of the various Cases : 

18.2.2. Case (A): It is possible to choose a field where Max VTj is 
assumed and one where Min Ti , Tj is assumed, so that the two are neither in 
the same row nor in the same column. 

By interchanging TI = 1, 2 as well as r 2 = 1, 2 we can make the first- 
mentioned field (of Max Ti , Tj ) to be (1, 1). The second-mentioned field 

1 Comparison of Figs. 12 and 27 shows that in Matching Pennies 3C(1, 1) - 3C(2, 2) - 1 
(gain on matching) ;3C(1, 2) - 3C(2, 1) - -1 (loss on not matching). 

2 In Matching Pennies (cf. footnote 1 above) the Max Tj , ri is 1 and is assumed at 
(1, 1) and (2, 2), while the Min V r f is -1 and is assumed at (1, 2) and (2, 1). 



SOME ELEMENTARY GAMES 171 

(of Min ri . r) ) must then be (2, 2). Consequently we have 

(18:2) 



Therefore (1, 2) is a saddle point. 1 

Thus the game is strictly determined in this case ajid 

(18:3) v' = v = 3C(1, 2). 

18.2.3. Case (B): It is impossible to make the choices as prescribed 
above: 

Choose the two fields in question (of Max Ti , Tj and Min ri , Tj ); then they 
are in the same row or in the same column. If the former should be the case, 
then interchange the players 1, 2, so that these two fields are at any rate 
in the same column. 2 

By interchanging TI = 1, 2 as well as r 2 = 1, 2 if necessary, we can again 
make the first-mentioned field (of Max VT2 ) to be (1, 1). So the column in 
question is r 2 = 1. The second-mentioned field (of Min ri , Tj ) must then be 
(2, I). 3 Consequently we have: 



Actually 3C(1, 1) = JC(1, 2) or JC(2, 2) = 3C(2, 1) are excluded because 
for the Max Tj , rj and Min T , Tj fields they' would permit the alternative choices 
of (1, 2), (2, 1) or (1, 1), (2, 2), thus bringing about Case (A). 4 

So we can strengthen (18:4) to 

(18:5) 

We must now make a further disjunction: 
18.2.4. Case(Bi): 

(18:6) 3C(1, 2) OC(2, 2) 

Then (18:5) can be strengthened to 

(18:7) 3C(1, 1) > 3C(1, 2) ^ OC(2, 2) > 3C(2, 1). 

Therefore (1, 2) is again a saddle point. 

Thus the game is strictly determined in this case too; and again 

(18:8) V = v =3C(1, 2). 

1 Recall 13.4.2. Observe that we had to take (1, 2) and not (2, 1). 

2 This interchange of the two players changes the sign of every matrix element (cf . 
above), hence it interchanges Max Ti ,T 2 and Min Ti>Tj . But they will nevertheless be in 
the same column. 

3 To be precise: It might also be (1, 1). But then 3C(n, r,) has the same Max Tl , Ts and 
Min r .T , and so it is a constant. Then we can use (2, 1) also for Min rj>Tj . 

<3C(1, 1) - 3C(2, 2) and JC(1, 2) - 3C(2, 1) are perfectly possible, as the example of 
Matching Pennies shows. Cf. footnote 1 on p. 170 and footnote 1 on p. 172. 



172 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 

18.2.6. Case (B 2 ): 

(18:9) 3C(1, 2) < 3C(2, 2) 

Then (18:5) can be strengthened to 

(18:10) 3C(1, 1) ^ 3C(2, 2) > 3C(l, 2) JC(2, I). 1 

The game is not strictly determined. 2 

It is easy however, to find good strategies, i.e. a { in A and an rj in B, by 
satisfying the characteristic condition (17 :D) of 17.9. We can do even more : 

-> 2 - 

We can choose 77 so that ^ 3C(ri, TJ)T; TI is the same for all r\ and so that 

r,-l 
2 

2} 3C(fi, T 2 ) ri is the same for all r*. For this purpose we need: 



- 
U *' 11; (30(1, l){i +3C(2, 1){, =5C(1, 2){i +3C(2, 2) fa. 

This means 



) - 3C(2, 1 

) -3C(1,2):OC(1, 1)-JC(2, 1). 

We must satisfy these ratios, subject to the permanent requirements 

fa 0, fa ^ fa + fa = 1 
i?i S 0, r/2 ^ r?i + 172 = 1 

This is possible because the prescribed ratios (i.e. the right-hand sides in 
(18:12)) are positive by (18:10). We have 

, _ 3C(2, 2) - 3C(2, 1) _ 



_ _ 

" 3C(1, 1) + 5C(2, 2) - 3C(1, 2) - 3C(2, 1)' 
> ^ _ X(l, 1) -30(1, 2) _ 
** 3C(1, 1) + 3C(2, 2) - 3C(1, 2) - JC(2, 1)* 
and further 

_ OC(2, 2) - 3C(1, 2) _ 
171 3C(1, 1) + 3C(2, 2) - 3C(1, 2) - 3C(2, 1)' 

_ _ ge(i, i)-ae(2, i) _ 

772 5C(1, 1) + 3C(2, 2) - 3C(1, 2) - JC(2, 1)' 

We can even show that these , 17 are unique, i.e. that A, B possess no other 
elements. 

1 This is actually the case for Matching Pennies. Cf . footnotes i on p. 170 and 4 
on p. 171. 

* Clearly vi - Max Ti Min f| 5C(n, r t ) - 3C(1, 2), v, - Mm Tj Max Tl 3C(r,, r t ) - JC(2, 2), 

80 V t < Vj. 



SOME ELEMENTARY GAMES 173 

Proof : If either or rj were something else than we found above, then 

77 or respectively must have a component 0, owing to the characteristic 


condition (17 :D) of 17.9. But then rj or { would differ from the above 

values since in these both components are positive. So we see: If either 
> > 
or 77 differs from the above values, then both do. And then both must 

have a component 0. For both the other component is then 1, i.e. both are 

coordinate vectors. 1 Hence the saddle point of K( , T; ) which they repre- 
sent is really one of 3C(ri, r 2 ), cf. (17 :E) in 17.9. Thus the game would be 
strictly determined; but we know that it is not in this case. 
This completes the proof. 

All four expressions in (18:11) are now seen to have the same value, 
namely 

3C(1, 1)3C(2, 2) - 3C(1, 2)3C(2, 1) 
JC(1, 1) + 3C(2, 2) - JC(1, 2) - X(2, 1) 

and by (17:5:a), (17:5:b) in 17.5.2. this is the value of v'. So we have 

na-nn v' - 3C(1, 1)3C(2, 2) - 3C(1, 2)OC(2, 1) 

^10. 10, v x( ^ ^ + ^ 2) _ ^ 2) _ ^ l y 

18.3. Qualitative Characterizations 

18.3.1. The formal results in 18.2. can be summarized in various ways 
which make their meaning clearer. We begin with this criterion: 

The fields (1, 1), (2, 2) form one diagonal of the matrix scheme of Fig. 27, 
the fields (1, 2), (2, 1) form the other diagonal. 

We say that two sets of numbers E and F are separated either if every 
element of E is greater than every element of F, or if every element of E 
is smaller than every element of F. 

Consider now the Cases (A), (Si), (B 2 ) of 18.2. In the first two cases 
the game is strictly determined and the elements on one diagonal of the 
matrix are not separated from those on the other. 2 In the last case the 
game is not strictly determined, and the elements on one diagonal of the 
matrix are separated from those on the other. 8 

Thus separation of the diagonals is necessary and sufficient for the game 
not being strictly determined. This criterion was obtained subject to 
the use made in 18.2. of the adjustments of 18.1.3. But the three processes 
of adjustment described in 18.1.3. affect neither strict determinateiiess 
nor separation of the diagonals. 4 Hence our first criterion is always valid. 
We restate it: 

Ml, 0| or (0,1). 

2 Case (A):3C(1, 1) OC(1, 2) ^ 3C(2, 2) by (18:2). Case (Bi): JC(1, 1) > JC(1, 2) 
^ 3C(2, 2) by (18:7). 

8 Case (Bi) : 3C(1, 1) JC(2, 2) > 3C(1, 2) OC(2, 1) by (18:10). 

4 The first is evident since these are only changes in notation, inessential for the game. 
The second is immediately verified. 



174 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 

(18 :A) The game is not strictly determined if and only if the elements 

on one diagonal of the matrix are separated from those on the 
other. 

18.3.2. In case (# 2 ), i.e. when the game is not strictly determined, both 

the (unique) { of A and the (unique) iy of B which we found, have both com- 
ponents 5** 0. This, as well as the statement of uniqueness, is unaffected 
by adjustments described in 18.1.3. 1 So we have: 

(18:B) If the game is not strictly determined, then there exists only 

> - 

one good strategy { (i.e. in A) and only one good strategy 77 

(i.e. in 5), and both have both their components positive. 
I.e. both players must really resort to mixed strategies. 

According to (18 :B) no component of or rj ( in A, vj in B) is zero. 
Hence the criterion of 17.9. shows that the argument which preceded 
(18:11) which was then sufficient without being necessary is now 
necessary (and sufficient). Hence (18:11) must be satisfied, and therefore 
all of its consequences are true. This applies in particular to the values 
$1, {2, i?i, 772 given after (18:11), and to the value of v' given in (18:13). 
All these formulae thus apply whenever the game is not strictly determined. 

18.3.3. We now formulate another criterion: 

In a general matrix 3C(ri, r 2 ) cf. Fig. 15 on p. 99 (we allow for a 
moment any 0i, 2 ) we say that a row (say T() or a column (say r' 2 ) majorizes 
another row (say r") or column (say r' 2 '), respectively, if this is true for their 
corresponding elements without exception. I.e. if 3C(rJ, r 2 ) ^ 3C(r7, r 2 ) 
for all T 2 , or if 3C(n, T{) ^ 3C(rj, /,') for all r*. 

This concept has a simple meaning: It means that the choice of r( 
is at least as good for player 1 as that of r" or that the choice of r( is at 
most as good for player 2 as that of r' 2 ' and that this is so in both cases 
irrespective of what the opponent does. 2 

Let us now return to our present problem (/?i = 2 = 2). Consider 
again the Cases (A), (J5 t ), (/? 2 ) of 18.2. In the first two cases a row or a 
column majorizes the other. 8 In the last case neither is true. 4 

Thus the fact that a row or a column majorizes the other is necessary and 
sufficient for T being strictly determined. Like our first criterion this is 
subject to the use made in 18.2. of the adjustments made in 18. 1.3. And, as 
there, those processes of adjustment affect neither strict determinateness 
nor majorization of rows or columns. Hence our present criterion too is 
always valid. We restate it: 

(18 :C) The game r is strictly determined if and only if a row or a 

column majorizes the other. 

1 These too are immediately verified. 

'This is, of course, an exceptional occurrence: In general the relative merits of two 
alternative choices will depend on what the opponent does. 

'Case (A): Column 1 majorizes column 2, by (18:2) Case (Bi): Row 1 majorizes 
row 2 by (18:7). 

4 Case (J?t): (18:10) excludes all four possibilities, as is easily verified. 



SOME ELEMENTARY GAMES 



175 



18.3.4. That the condition of ( 18 :C) is sufficient for strict determinateness 
is not surprising: It means that for one of the two players one of his possible 
choices is under all conditions at least as good as the other (cf. above). Thus 
he knows what to do and his opponent knows what to expect, which is likely 
to imply strict determinateness. 

Of course these considerations imply a speculation on the rationality 
of the behavior of the other player, from which our original discussion is 
free. The remarks at the beginning and at the end of 15.8. apply to a 
certain extent to this, much simpler, situation. 

What really matters in this result (18 :C) however is that the necessity 
of the condition is also established; i.e. that nothing more subtle than 
outright majorization of rows or columns can cause strict determinateness. 

It should be remembered that we are considering the simplest possible 
case: 0i = 2 = 2. We shall see in 18.5. how conditions get more involved 
in all respects when pi, fa increase. 

18.4. Discussion of Some Specific Games. (Generalized Forms of Matching Pennies) 

18.4.1. The following are some applications of the results of 18.2. and 
18,3. 

(a) Matching Pennies in its ordinary form, where the JC matrix of Figure 
27 is given by Figure 12 on p. 94. We know that this game has the value 

v' = 
and the (unique) good strategies 

7=7= {*,*} 

(Cf. 17.1. The formulae of 18.2. will, of course, give this immediately.) 

18.4.2. (b) Matching Pennies, where matching on heads gives a double 
premium. Thus the matrix of Figure 27 differs from that of Figure 12 by 
the doubling of its (1, 1) element: 





1 


2 


1 


(\ 


-1 


2 


-1 


1 



Figure 28o. 

The diagonals are separated (1 and 2 are > than 1), hence the good strate- 
gies are unique and mixed (cf. (18: A), (18:B)). By using the pertinent 
formulae of case (#2) in 18.2.5., we obtain the value 

and the good strategies 



It will be observed that the premium put on matching heads has increased 
the value of a play for player 1 who tries to match. It also causes him to 



176 



ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 



choose heads less frequently, since the premium makes this choice plausible 
and therefore dangerous. The direct threat of extra loss by being matched 
on heads influences player 2 in the same way. This verbal argument has 
some plausibility but is certainly not stringent. Our formulae which yielded 
this result, however, were stringent. 

18.4.3. (c) Matching Pennies, where matching on heads gives a double 
premium but failing to match on a choice (by player 1) of heads gives a 
triple penalty. Thus the matrix of Figure 27 is modified as follows: 





1 


2 


1 


2 


-3 


2 


-1 


1 



Figure 286. 

The diagonals are separated (1 and 2, are > than 1, 3), hence the good 
strategies are unique and mixed (cf. as before). The formulae used before 
give the value 



v = - 



and the good strategies 



We leave it to the reader to formulate a verbal interpretation of this 
result, in the same sense as before. The construction of other examples 
of this type is easy along the lines indicated. 

18.4.4. (d) We saw in 18.1.2. that these variants of Matching Pennies 
are, in a way, the simplest forms of zero-sum two-person games. By this 
circumstance they acquire a certain general significance, which is further 
corroborated by the results of 18.2. and 18.3.: indeed we found there that 
this class of games exhibits in their simplest forms the conditions under 
which strictly and not-strictly determined cases alternate. As a further 
addendum in the same spirit we point out that the relatedness of these 
games to Matching Pennies stresses only one particular aspect. Other 
games which appear in an entirely different material garb may, in reality, 
well belong to this class. We shall give an example of this: 

The game to be considered is an episode from the Adventures of Sherlock 
Holmes. 1 - 2 

1 Conan Doyle: The Adventures of Sherlock Holmes, New York, 1938, pp. 550-551. 
1 The situation in question is of course again to be appraised as a paradigm of many 
possible conflicts in practical life. It was expounded as such by 0. Morgenstern: Wirt- 
schaftsprognose, Vienna, 1928, p. 98. 

The author does not maintain, however, some pessimistic views expressed id. or in 
" Vollkommene Voraussicht und wirtschaftliches Gleichgewicht," Zeitschrift fur Nation- 
alokonomie, Vol. 6, 1934. 

Accordingly our solution also answers doubts in the same vein expressed by K. 
Menger: Neuere Fortschritte in den exacten Wissenschaften, "Einige neuere Fort- 
schritte in der exacten Behandlung Socialwissenschaftlicher Probleme," Vienna, 1936, 
pp. 117 and 131. 



SOME ELEMENTARY GAMES 



177 



Sherlock Holmes desires to proceed from London to Dover and hence 
to the Continent in order to escape from Professor Moriarty who pursues 
him. Having boarded the train he observes, as the train pulls out, the 
appearance of Professor Moriarty on the platform. Sherlock Holmes 
takes it for granted and in this he is assumed to be fully justified that 
his adversary, who has seen him, might secure a special train and overtake 
him. Sherlock Holmes is faced with the alternative of going to Dover or 
of leaving the train at Canterbury, the only intermediate station. His 
adversary whose intelligence is assumed to be fully adequate to visualize 
these possibilities has the same choice. Both opponents must choose the 
place of their detrainment in ignorance of the other's corresponding decision. 
If, as a result of these measures, they should find themselves, in fine, on 
the same platform, Sherlock Holmes may with certainty expect to be killed 
by Moriarty. If Sherlock Holmes reaches Dover unharmed he can make 
good his escape. 

What are the good strategies, particularly for Sherlock Holriies? This 
game has obviously a certain similarity to Matching Pennies, Professor 
Moriarty being the one who desires to match. Let him therefore be 
player 1, and Sherlock Holmes be player 2. Denote the choice to proceed to 
Dover by 1 and the choice to quit at the intermediate station by 2. (This 
applies to both r\ and T2.) 

Let us now consider the X matrix of Figure 27. The fields (1, 1) and 
(2, 2) correspond to Professor Moriarty catching Sherlock Holmes, which it 
is reasonable to describe by a very high value of the corresponding matrix 
element, say 100. The field (2, 1) signifies that Sherlock Holmes suc- 
cessfully escaped to Dover, while Moriarty stopped at Canterbury. This is 
Moriarty 's defeat as far as the present action is concerned, and* should be 
described by a big negative value of the matrix element in the order of 
magnitude but smaller than the positive value mentioned above say, 50. 
The field (1, 2) signifies that Sherlock Holmes escapes Moriarty at the 
intermediate station, but fails to reach the Continent. This is best viewed 
as a tie, and assigned the matrix element 0. 

The 5C matrix is given by Figure 29: 





1 


2 


1 


100 





2 


-50 


100 



Figure 29. 

As in (b), (c) above, the diagonals are separated (100 is > than 0, 50); 
hence the good strategies are again unique and mixed. The formulae 
used before give the value (for Moriarty) 



40 



178 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 

and the good strategies ( for Moriarty, rj for Sherlock Holmes) : 

7 = {*,!}, 7 = {*,D. 

Thus Moriarty should go to Dover with a probability of 60%, while 
Sherlock Holmes should stop at the intermediate station with a probability 
of 60 %, the remaining 40 % being left in each case for the other alternative. l 

18.5. Discussion of Some Slightly More Complicated Games 

18.6.1. The general solution of the zero-sum two-person game which we 
obtained in 17.8. brings certain alternatives and concepts particularly 
into the foreground: The presence or absence of strict determinateness, the 
value v' of a play, and the sets A, S of good strategies. For all these we 
obtained very simple explicit characterizations and determinations in 18.2. 
These became even more striking in the reformulation of those results in 
18.3. 

This simplicity may even lead to some misunderstandings. Indeed, 
the results of 18.2., 18.3. were obtained by explicit computations of the most 
elementary sort. The combinatorial criteria of (18 :A), (18:C) in 18.3. 
for strict determinateness were at least in their final form also consider- 
ably more straightforward than anything we have experienced before. 
This may give occasion to doubts whether the somewhat involved consider- 
ations of 17.8. (and the corresponding considerations of 14.5. in the case 
of strict determinateness) were necessary, particularly since they are 
based on the mathematical theorem of 17.6. which necessitates our analysis 
of linearity and convexity in 16. If all this could be replaced by discussions 
in the style of 18.2., 18.3. then our mode of discussion of 16. and 17. would be 
entirely unjustified. 2 

This is not so. As pointed out at the end of 18.3., the great simplicity 
of the procedures and results of 18.2. and 18.3. is due to the fact that they 
apply only to the simplest type of zero-sum two-person games: the Matching 
Pennies class of games, characterized by ft\ = 2 = 2. For the general 
case the more abstract machinery of 16. and 17. seems so far indispensable. 

1 The narrative of Conan Doyle excusably disregards mixed strategies and states 
instead the actual developments. According to these Sherlock Holmes gets out at the 
intermediate station and triumphantly watches Moriarty 's special train going on to 
Dover. Conan Doyle's solution is the best possible under his limitations (to pure 
strategies), insofar as he attributes to each opponent the course which we found to be the 
more probable one (i.e. he replaces 60% probability by certainty). It is, however, 
somewhat misleading that this procedure leads to Sherlock Holmes's complete victory, 
whereas, as we saw above, the odds (i.e. the value of a play) are definitely in favor of 

Moriarty. (Our result for { , 17 yields that Sherlock Holmes is as good as 48% dead 
when his train pulls out from Victoria Station. Compare in this connection the sugges- 
tion in Morgenstern, loc. cit., p. 98, that the whole trip is unnecessary because the loser 
could be determined before the start.) 

'Of course it would not lack rigor, but it would be an unnecessary use of heavy 
mathematical machinery on an elementary problem. 



SOME ELEMENTARY GAMES 



179 



It may help to see these things in their right proportions if we show by 
some examples how the assertions of 18.2., 18.3. fail for greater values 
of 18. 

18.5.2. It will actually suffice to consider games with 0i = fa = 3. 
In fact they will be somewhat related to Matching Pennies, more general 
only by introduction of a third alternative. 

Thus both players will have the alternative choices 1, 2, 3 (i.e. the values 
for TI, r 2 ). The reader will best think of the choice 1 in terms of choosing 
"heads," the choice 2 of choosing "tails" and the choice 3 as something like 
"calling off." Player 1 again tries to match. If either player "calls off," 
then it will not matter whether the other player chooses "heads" or "tails," 
the only thing of importance is whether he chooses one of these two at 
all or whether he "calls off" too. Consequently the matrix has now the 
appearance of Figure 30: 



\ 


1 


2 


3 


1 


1 


-1 


7 


2 


-1 


1 


y 


3 


a 


a 


ft 



Figure 30. 

The four first elements i.e. the first two elements of the first two rows 
are the familiar pattern of Matching Pennies (cf. Fig. 12). The two fields 
with a are operative when player 1 "calls off" and player 2 does not. The 
two elements with 7 are operative in the opposite case. The element with 
|8 refers to the case where both players " call off." By assigning appropriate 
values (positive, negative or zero) we can put a premium or a penalty 
on any one of these occurrences, or make it indifferent. 

We shall obtain all the examples we need at this juncture by specializing 
this scheme, i.e. by choosing the above a, 0, y appropriately. 

18.5.3. Our purpose is to show that none of the results (18:A), (18:B), 
(18 :C) of 18.3. is generally true. 

Ad (18:A): This criterion of strict determinateness is clearly tied to the 
special case $\ = fa = 2: For greater values of 0i, 2 the two diagonals do 
not even exhaust the matrix rectangle, and therefore the occurrence on the 
diagonal alone cannot be characteristic as before. 

Ad (18 :B): We shall give an example of a game which is not strictly 
determined, but where nevertheless there exists a good strategy which is 
pure for one player (but of course not for the other). This example has the 
further peculiarity that one of the players has several good strategies, while 
the other has only one. 



180 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 

We choose in the game of Figure 30 , ft, y as follows: 



\ 


1 


2 


3 


1 


1 


-1 





2 


-1 


1 





3 


a 


a 


-a 



Figure 31. 

a > 0, 6 > 0. The reader will determine for himself which combinations of 
" calling off" are at a premium or are penalized in the previously indicated 
sense. 

This is a complete discussion of the game, using the criteria of 17.8. 

For = {i, i, 0} always K( { , rj ) = 0, i.e. with this strategy player 1 

cannot lose. Hence v' jg 0. For t\ = 6 8 = {0, 0, 1} always K( , rj ) 
^ O; 1 i.e. with this strategy player 2 cannot lose. Hence v' g 0. Thus we 
have 

v' = 

Consequently is a good strategy if and only if always K( { , rj ) ^ and TJ 

is a good strategy if and only if always K( , rj ) ^ O. 2 The former is easily 
seen to be true if and only if 

* i = {2 = i {3 = 0, 
and the latter if and only if 

5 



172 



2(a 



Thus the set A of all good strategies contains precisely one element, 

and this is not a pure strategy. The set B of all good strategies 77 , on the 
other hand, contains infinitely many strategies, and one of them is pure: 

namely rj = d 8 = {0, 0, 1}. 

The sets A, B can be visualized by making use of the graphical repre- 
sentation of Figure 21 (cf . Figures 32, 33) : 

Ad (18 :C): We shall give an example of a game which is strictly deter- 
mined but in which no two rows and equally no two columns majorize each 
other. We shall actually do somewhat more. 

18.5.4. Allow for a moment any 0i, /3 2 . The significance of the majoriza- 
tion of rows or of columns by each other was considered at the end of 18.3. 
It was seen to mean that one of the players had a simple direct motive 

1 It is actually equal to 3 . 

* We leave to the reader the simple verbal interpretation of these statements. 



SOME ELEMENTARY GAMES 



181 



for neglecting one of his possible choices in favor of another, and this 
narrowed the possibilities in a way which could be ultimately connected 
with strict determinateness. 

Specifically: If the row T" is majorized by the row r\ i.e. if 
3( T "> T S) ^ 3CM, T 2 ) for all r 2 then player 1 need never consider the 
choice Tit since T\ is at least as good for him in every contingency. And: 
If the column r 2 ' majorizes the column / 2 i.e. if JC(TI, r' 2 ') ^ 3C(n, r 2 ) for all 
n then player 2 need never consider the choice r' 2 ', since r' 2 is at least as good 
for him in every contingency. (Cf. loc. cit., particularly footnote 2 on 
p. 174. These are of course only heuristic considerations, cf. footnote 1, 
p. 182.) 





Figure 33. 

Now we may use an even more general set-up: If the row r", i.e. 
the player 1's pure strategy corresponding to r" is majorized by an average 


of all rows T\ j T" i.e. by a mixed strategy with the component 

T " = then it is still plausible to assume that player 1 need never con- 
sider the choice of r", since the other T\ are at least as good for him in every 
contingency. The mathematical expression of this situation is this: 

0i 

it T 2 ) ^ y 3C(ri, r 2 ) T for all T 2 



n 



0. 



The corresponding situation for player 2 arises if the column rj' i.e. 
player 2 ; s pure strategy corresponding to r 2 ' majorizes an average of all 

> 
columns r' 2 ^ //, i.e. a mixed strategy ?? with the component t\ r " = 0. 

The mathematical expression of this situation is this: 

0* 
(n, r 2 ; ) Y JC(n, rj)^ for all n 



in 8^ 



= 0. 



The conclusions are the analogues of the above. 



182 



ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 



Thus a game in which (18:14:a) or (18:14:b) occurs, permits of an 
immediate and plausible narrowing of the possible choices for one of the 
players. 1 

18.5.5. We are now going to show that the applicability of (18:14:a), 
(18:14:b) is very limited: We shall specify a strictly determined game in 
which neither (18:14:a) nor (18:14:b) is ever valid. 

Let us therefore return to the class of games of Figure 30. (0i = /3 2 = 3). 
We choose < a < 1, = 0, y = -a: 













1 


2 


3 










1 


1 


-1 


a 


2 


1 


i 


a 


3 


a 


a 






Figure 34. 

The reader will determine for himself which combinations of " calling off" 
are at a premium or are penalized in the previously indicated sense. 

This is a discussion of the game : 

The element (3, 3) is clearly a saddle point, so the game is strictly 
determined and 

v = v' = 0. 

It is not difficult to see now (with the aid of the method used in 18.5.3.), 

that the set A of all good strategies as well as the set B of all good strate- 



gies 17 , contains precisely one element: the pure strategy d 8 = {0, 0, 1). 

On the other hand, the reader will experience little trouble in verifying 
that neither (18:14:a) nor (18:14:b) is ever valid here, i.e. that in Figure 34 
no row is majorized by any average of the two other rows, and that no 
column majorizes any average of the other two columns. 

18.6. Chance and Imperfect Information 

18.6.1. The examples discussed in the preceding paragraphs make it 
clear that the role of chance more precisely, of probability in a game is 
not necessarily the obvious one, that which is directly provided for in the 
rules of the game. The games described in Figures 27 and 30 have rules 

1 This is of course a thoroughly heuristic argument. We do not need it, since we have 
the complete discussions of 14.5. and of 17.8. But one might suspect that it can be used 
to replace or at least to simplify those discussions. The example which we are going to 
give in the text seems to dispel any such hope. 

There is another course which might produce results: If (18:14:a) or (18:14:b) holds, 
then a combination of it with 17.8. can be used to gain information about the sets of good 
strategies, A and B. We do not propose to take up this subject here. 



SOME ELEMENTARY GAMES 183 

which do not provide for chance; the moves are personal without excep- 
tion. l Nevertheless we found that most of them are not strictly determined, 
i.e. that their good strategies are mixed strategies involving the explicit 
use of probabilities. 

On the other hand, our analysis of those games in which perfect informa- 
tion prevails showed that these are always strictly determined, i.e. that 
they have good strategies which are pure strategies, involving no probabili- 
ties at all. (Cf. 15.) 

Thus from the point of view of the players' behavior i.e. of the strate- 
gies to be used the important circumstance is whether the game is strictly 
determined or not, and not at all whether it contains any chance moves. 

The results of 15. on games in which perfect information prevails 
indicate that there exists a close connection between strict determinateness 
and the rules which govern the players' state of information. To establish 
this point quite clearly, and in particular to show that the presence of 
chance moves is quite irrelevant, we shall now show this: In every (zero- 
sum two-person) game any chance move can be replaced by a combination 
of personal moves, so that the strategical possibilities of the game remain 
exactly the same. It will be necessary to allow for rules involving imperfect 
information of the players, but this is just what we want to demonstrate: 
That imperfect information comprises (among other things) all possible 
consequences of explicit chance moves. 2 

18.6.2. Let us consider, accordingly, a (zero-sum two-person) game F, 
and in it a chance move 3TC*. 3 Enumerate the alternatives as usual by 
a K = 1, , a K and assume that their probabilities p ( K l) , , p ( ?** are 
all equal to l/ex<. 4 Now replace 3TI, by two personal moves 2fTl^, 9TC". 

1 The reduction of all games to the normalized form shows even more: It proves that 
every game is equivalent to one without chance moves, since the normalized form con- 
tains only personal moves. 

2 A direct way of removing chance moves exists of course after the introduction of the 
(pure) strategies and the umpire's choice, as described in 11.1. Indeed as the last 
step in bringing a game into its normalized form we eliminated the remaining chance 
moves by the explicit introduction of expectation values in 11.2.3. 

But we now propose to eliminate the chance moves without upsetting the structure 
of the game so radically. We shall replace each chance move individually by personal 
moves (by two moves, as will be seen), so that their respective roles in determining the 
players' strategies will always remain differentiated and individually appraisable. This 
detailed treatment is likely to give a clearer idea of the structural questions involved than 
the summary procedure mentioned above. 

3 For our present purposes it is irrelevant whether the characteristics of 9Tl depend 
upon the previous course of the play or not. 

4 This is no real loss of generality. To see this, assume that the probabilities in 
question have arbitrary rational values, say r\/t, , r a /t (r\, , r a and / 
integers). (Herein lies an actual restriction but an arbitrary small one since any 
probabilities can be approximated by rational ones to any desired degree.) 

Now modify the chance move 9fR so that it has r\ + - -f r ajc t alternatives 
(instead of a,), designated by </ K 1, , t (instead of <r 1, - , a); and so that 
each of the first n values of J n has the same effect on the play as <r = 1, each of the 
next rj values of a' K the same as * K 2, etc., etc. Then giving all *' K 1, , t the 
same probability l/l, has the same effect as giving <r 1, , a K the original prob- 
abilities Ti/t, ' ' , Tat. 



184 



ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 



Wl( and 9(Tl" are personal moves of players 1 and 2 respectively. Both have 
a, alternatives; we denote the corresponding choices by o-^ = 1, - , a K 
and <r" = 1, , a K . It is immaterial in which order these moves are 
made, but we prescribe that both moves must be made without any infor- 
mation concerning the outcome of any moves (including the other move 
3fl, 9TC")- We define a function S(<r', <r") by this matrix scheme. (Cf. 
Figure 35. The matrix element is 5(a', a")- 1 )- The influence of 3ffl^, 9TC" 
i.e. of the corresponding (personal) choices a, <r" on the outcome of the 
game is the same as that of STl* would have been with the corresponding 
(chance) choice a* = 6(<r, <r"). We denote this new game by F*. We 
claim that the strategical possibilities of F* are the same as those of F. 




a* 



a 



-2 



- 1 



Figure 35. 

18.6.3. Indeed: Let player 1 use in F* a given mixed strategy of F with 
the further specification concerning the move 9Tl^ 2 to choose all a' K = 1, 
-,, with the same probability 1 /a*. Then the game F* with this 
strategy of player 1 will be from player 2's point of view the same as F. 
This is so because any choice of his at 9Tl^ (i.e. any cr" = 1, , a) 
produces the same result as the original chance move 9R,: One look at 
Figure 35 will show that the a" = cr" column of that matrix contains every 
number <r = 6(a', <r") = !,,, precisely once, i.e. that 5(er', <r") 
will assume every value !,, (owing to player 1's strategy) with the 
same probability !/<, just as 9H, would have done. So from player Ts 
point of view, F* is at least as good as F. 

The same argument with players 1 and 2 interchanged hence with 
the rows of the matrix in Figure 35 playing the roles which the column 
had above shows that from player 2's point of view too F* is at least as 
good as F. 



1 Arithmetically 



<r' a" -f 1 for a' ^ <r' 

*'-*" + 1 + a* for <r' < <r' 



Hence 5(<r', a") is always one of the numbers 1, , ot. 

1 31li is his personal move, so his strategy must provide for it in r*. There was no 
need for this in r, since 9R, was a chance move. 



SOME ELEMENTARY GAMES 185 

Since the viewpoints of the two players are opposite, this means that 
F* and F are equivalent. 1 

18.7. Interpretation of This Result 

18.7.1. Repeated application to all chance moves of F, of the operation 
described in 18.6.2., 18.6.3., will remove them all, thus proving the final 
contention of 18.6.1. The meaning of this result may be even better under- 
stood if we illustrate it by some practical instances of this manipulation. 

(A) Consider the following quite elementary "game of chance." The 
two players decide, by a 50%-50% chance device, who pays the other one 
unit. The application of the device of 18.6.2., 18.6.3. transforms this game, 
which consists of precisely one chance move, into one of two personal moves. 
A look at the matrix of Figure 35 for <*< = 2 with the 3(</, <r") values 1, 2 
replaced by the actual payments 1, 1 shows that it coincides with 
Figure 12. Remembering 14.7.2., 14.7.3. we see that this means what is 
plain enough directly that this is the game of Matching Pennies. 

I.e. : Matching Pennies is the natural device to produce the probabilities 
i> i by personal moves and imperfect information. (Recall 17.1.!) 

(B) Modify (A) so as to allow for a "tie": The two players decide by a 
33%, 33%, 33^% chance device who pays the other one unit, or whether 
nobody pays anything at all. Apply again the device of 18.6.2., 18.6.3. 
Now the matrix of Figure 35 with a K = 3 with the &(&', a") values 1, 2, 3 
replaced by the actual payments 0, 1, 1 coincides with Figure 13. By 
14.7.2., 14.7.3. we see that this is the game of Stone, Paper, Scissors. 

I.e., Stone, Paper, Scissors is the natural device to produce the proba- 
bilities i, i, i by personal moves and incomplete information. (Recall 
17.1.!) 

18.7.2. (C) The d(<r', <r") of Figure 35 can be replaced by another func- 
tion, and even the domains a' K = !, , aand<r" = !, , a, by other 
domains <r' K = 1, , a' K and o-" = 1, , a", provided that the follow- 
ing remains true: Every column of the matrix of Figure 35 contains each 
number 1, , a c the same number of times, 2 and every row contains 
each number !,-, the same number of times. 8 Indeed, the con- 
siderations of 18.6.2. made use of these two properties of S(<7<, a") (and of 
:, *'.') only. 

It is not difficult to see that the precaution of "cutting" the deck before 
dealing cards falls into this category. When one of the 52 cards has to be 
chosen by a chance move, with probability ^, this is usually achieved by 
"mixing" the deck. This is meant to be a chance move, but if the player 
who mixes is dishonest, it may turn out to be a "personal" move of his. 

1 We leave it to the reader to cast these considerations into the precise formalism of 1 1. 
and 17.2., 17.8.: This presents absolutely no difficulties, but it is somewhat lengthy. 
The above verbal arguments convey the essential reason of the phenomenon under con- 
sideration in a clearer and simpler way we hope. 

* Hence <*i/ times; consequently a' K must be a multiple of o. 

1 Hence a"/c times; consequently a" must be a multiple of a,. 



186 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 

As a protection against this, the other player is permitted to point out the 
place in the mixed deck, from which the card in question is to be taken, by 
"cutting" the deck at that point. This combination of two^moves even 
if they are personal is equivalent to the originally intended chance move. 
The lack of information is, of course, the necessary condition for the effec- 
tiveness of this device. 

Here a, = 52, a' K = 52! = the number of possible arrangements of the 
deck, a" = 52 the number of ways of " cutting." We leave it to the reader 
to fill in the details and to choose the 5(<r^, a") for this set-up. 1 

19. Poker and Bluffing 
19.1. Description of Poker 

19.1.1. It has been stressed repeatedly that the case fti = ft 2 = 2 as 
discussed in 18.3. and more specifically in 18.4., comprises only the very 
simplest zero-sum two-person games. We then gave in 18.5. some instances 
of the complications which can arise in the general zero-sum two-person 
game, but the understanding of the implications of our general result 
(i.e. of 17.8.) will probably gain more by the detailed discussion of a special 
game of the more complicated type. This is even more desirable because 
for the games with 0i = $2 = 2 the choices of the r\, r 2 , called (pure) strate- 
gies, scarcely deserve this name: just calling them "moves" would have 
been less exaggerated. Indeed, in these extremely simple games there 
could be hardly any difference between the extensive and the normalized form ; 
and so the identity of moves and strategies, a characteristic of the normalized 
form, is inescapable in these games. We shall now consider a game in the 
extensive form in which the player has several moves, so that the passage 
to the normalized form and to strategies is no longer a vacuous operation. 

19.1.2. The game of which we give an exact discussion is Poker. 2 How- 
ever, actual Poker is really a much too complicated subject for an exhaustive 
discussion and so we shall have to subject it to some simplifying modifica- 

1 We assumed that the mixing is used to produce only one card. If whole " hands" 
are dealt, "cutting" is not an absolute safeguard. A dishonest mixer can produce corre- 
lations within the deck which one "cut" cannot destroy, and the knowledge of which 
gives this mixer an illegitimate advantage. 

1 The general considerations concerning Poker and the mathematical discussions of 
the variants referred to in the paragraphs which follow, were carried out by J. von 
Neumann in 1926-28, but not published before. (Cf . a general reference in " Zur Theorie 
der Gesellschaftsspiele," Math. Ann., Vol. 100 [1928]). This applies in particular to the 
symmetric variant of 19.4.-19.10., the variants (A), (B) of 19.11.-19.13., and to the entire 
interpretation of "Bluffing" which dominates all these discussions. The unsymmetric 
variant (C) of 19.14.-19.16. was considered in 1942 for the purposes of this publication. 
The work of E. Borel and /. Ville, referred to in footnote 1 on p. 154, also con- 
tains considerations on Poker (Vol. IV, 2: "Applications aux Jeux de Hasard," Chap. 
V: "Le jeu de Poker"). They are very instructive, but mainly evaluations of prob- 
abilities applied to Poker in a more or less heuristic way, without a systematic use of any 
underlying general theory of games. 

A definite strategical phase of Poker ("La Relance" - "The Overbid") is analyzed 
on pp. 91-97 loc. cit. This may be regarded also as a simplified variant of Poker, 



POKER AND BLUFFING 187 

tions, some of which are, indeed, quite radical. 1 It seems to us, neverthe- 
less, that the basic idea of Poker and its decisive properties will be conserved 
in our simplified form. Therefore it will be possible to base general con- 
clusions and interpretations on the results which we are going to obtain 
by the application of the theory previously established. 

To begin with, Poker is actually played by any number of persons, 2 
but since we are now in the discussion of zero-sum two-person games, we 
shall set the number of players at two. 

The game of Poker begins by dealing to each player 5 cards out of a 
deck. 8 The possible combinations of 5 which he may get in this way 
there are 2,598,960 of them 4 are called "hands" and arranged in a linear 
order, i.e. there is an exhaustive rule defining which hand is the strongest 
of all, which is the second, third, strongest down to the weakest. 5 
Poker is played in many variants which fall into two classes: "Stud" and 
"Draw" games. In a Stud game the player's hand is dealt to him in its 
entirety at the very beginning, and he has to keep it unchanged throughout 
the entire play. In "Draw" games there are various ways for a player to 
exchange all or part of his hand, and in some variants he may get his hand 
in several successive stages in the course of the play. Since we wish to 
discuss the simplest possible form, we shall examine the Stud game only. 

In this case there is no point in discussing the hands as hands, i.e. as 
combinations of cards. Denoting the total number of hands by S 
S = 2,598,960 for a full deck, as we saw we might as well say that each 

comparable to the two which we consider in 19.4. -19. 10. and 19.14-19.16. It is actually 
closely related to the latter. 

The reader who wishes to compare these two variants, may find the following indica- 
tions helpful: 

(I) Our bids a, 6 correspond to 1 + a, 1 loc. cit. 

(II) The difference between our variant of 19.4.-19.10. and that in loc. cit. is this: 
If player 1 begins with a "low" bid, then our variant provides for a comparison of hands, 
while that in loc. cit. makes him lose the amount of the "low" bid unconditionally. I.e. 
we treated this initial "low" bid as "seeing" cf. the discussion at the beginning of 
19.14., particularly footnote 1 on p. 211 while in loc. cit. it is treated as "passing." 
We believe that our treatment is a better approximation to the phase in question in real 
Poker; and in particular that it is needed for a proper analysis and interpretation of 
"Bluffing." For technical details cf. footnote 1 on p. 219. 

1 Cf. however 19.11. and the end of 19.16. 

2 The "optimum" in a sense which we do not undertake to interpret is supposed 
to be 4 or 5. 

3 This is occasionally a full deck of 52 cards, but for smaller numbers of participants 
only parts of it usually 32 or 28 are used. Sometimes one or two extra cards with 
special functions, "jokers," are added. 

4 This holds for a full deck. The reader who is conversant with the elements of com- 
binatorics will note that this is the number of "combinations without repetitions of 
5 out of 52": 



/52\ ^52.51-50.49.48 

U/ * 1.2-3.4.5 = 2 > 598 > 960 - 



& This description involves the well known technical terms "Royal Flush," "Straight 
Flush," "Four of a Kind," "Full House," etc. There is no need for us to discuss them 
here. 



188 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 

player draws a number s = 1, , S instead. The idea is that s = <S 
corresponds to the strongest possible hand, a = S 1 to the second 
strongest, etc., and finally s = 1 to the weakest. Since a " square deal" 
amounts to assuming that all possible hands are dealt with the same prob- 
ability, we must interpret the drawing of the above number s as a chance 
move, each one of the possible values s = 1, , S having the same 
probability 1/8. Thus the game begins with two chance moves: The 
drawing of the number s for player 1 and for player 2, 1 which we denote 
by 81 and $2. 

19.1.3. The next phase of the general game of Poker consists of the 
making of "Bids" by the players. The idea is that after one of the players 
has made a bid, which involves a smaller or greater amount of money, his 
opponent has the choice of " Passing," "Seeing," or "Overbidding." 
Passing means that he is willing to pay, without further argument, the 
amount of his last preceding bid (which is necessarily lower than the present 
bid). In this case it is irrelevant what hands the two players hold. The 
hands are not disclosed at all. "Seeing" means that the bid is accepted: 
the hands will be compared and the player with the stronger hand receives 
the amount of the present bid. "Seeing" terminates the play. "Overbid- 
ding" means that the opponent counters the present bid by a higher one, 
in which the roles of the players are reversed and the previous bidder has 
the choice of Passing, Seeing or Overbidding, etc. 2 

19.2. Bluffing 

19.2.1. The point in all this is that a player with a strong hand is likely 
to make high bids and numerous overbids since he has good reason to 
expect that he will win. Consequently a player who has made a high bid, 
or overbid, may be assumed by his opponent a posteriori! to have a 
strong hand. This may provide the opponent with a motive for " Passing." 
However, since in the case of "Passing" the hands are not compared, even 
a player with a weak hand may occasionally obtain a gain against a stronger 
opponent by creating the (false) impression of strength by a high bid, or 
by overbid, thus conceivably inducing his opponent to pass. 

This maneuver is known as "Bluffing." It is unquestionably prac- 
ticed by all experienced players. Whether the above is its real motivation 
may be doubted; actually a second interpretation is conceivable. That is 
if a player is known to bid high only when his hand is strong, his opponent is 
likely to pass in such cases. The player will, therefore, not be able to collect 
on high bids, or on numerous overbids, in just those cases where his actual 
strength gives him the opportunity. Hence it is desirable for him to create 

1 In actual Poker the second player draws from a deck from which the first player's 
hand has already been removed. We disregard this as we disregard some other minor 
complications of Poker. 

2 This scheme is usually complicated by the necessity of making unconditional pay- 
ments, the "ante," at the start, in some variants for the first bidder, in others for all 
those who wish to participate, again in others extra payments are required for the privi- 
lege of drawing, etc. We disregard all this. 



POKER AND BLUFFING 189 

uncertainty in his opponent's mind as to this correlation, i.e. to make it 
known that he does occasionally bid high on a weak hand. 

To sum up: Of the two possible motives for Bluffing, the first is the 
desire to give a (false) impression of strength in (real) weakness; the second 
is the desire to give a (false) impression of weakness in (real) strength. 
Both are instances of inverted signaling (cf. 6.4.3.), i.e. of misleading the 
opponent. It should be observed however that the first- type of Bluffing 
is most successful when it "succeeds," i.e. when the opponent actually 
"passes," since this secures the desired gain; while the second is most 
successful when it "fails," i.e. when the opponent "sees," since this will 
convey to him the desired confusing information. 1 

19.2.2. The possibility of such indirectly motivated hence apparently 
irrational bids has also another consequence. Such bids are necessarily 
risky, and therefore it can conceivably be worth while to make them riskier 
by appropriate counter measures, thus restricting their use by the oppon- 
ent. But such counter measures are ipso facto also indirectly motivated 
moves. 

We have expounded these heuristic considerations at such length 
because our exact theory makes a disentanglement of all these mixed 
motives possible. It will be seen in 19.10. and in 19.15.3., 19.16.2. how the 
phenomena which surround Bluffing can be understood quantitatively, 
and how the motives are connected with the main strategic features of the 
game, like possession of the initiative, etc. 

19.3. Description of Poker (Continued) 

19.3.1. Let us now return to the technical rules of Poker. In order to 
avoid endless overbidding the number of bids is usually limited. 2 In order 
to avoid unrealistically high bids with hardly foreseeable irrational effects 
upon the opponent there are also maxima for each bid and overbid. 
It is also customary to prohibit too small overbids; we shall subsequently 
indicate what appears to be a good reason for this (cf. the end of 19.13.). 
We shall express these restrictions on the size of bids and overbids in the 
simplest possible form: We shall assume that two numbers a, b 

a > b > 

1 At this point we might be accused once more of disregarding our previously stated 
guiding principle; the above discussion obviously assumes a series of plays (so that 
statistical observation of the opponent's habits is possible) and it has a definitely 
"dynamical" character. And yet we have repeatedly professed that our considerations 
must be applicable to one isolated play and also that they are strictly statical. 

We refer the reader to 17.3., where this apparent contradiction has been carefully 
examined. Those considerations are fully valid in this case too, and should justify our 
procedure. We shall add now only that our inconsistency the use of many plays and 
of a dynamical terminology is a merely verbal one. In this way we were able to make 
our discussions more succinct and more akin to the way that these things are talked about 
in everyday language. But in 17.3. it was elaborated how all these questionable pictures 
can be replaced by the strictly static problem of finding a good strategy. 

1 This is the stop rule of 7.2.3. 



190 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 

are given ab inilio, and that for every bid there are only two possibilities: 
the bid may be "high," in which case it is a; or "low," in which case it is 
6. By varying the ratio a/b which is clearly the only thing that matters 
we can make the game risky when a/b is much greater than 1, or relatively 
safe when a/b is only a little greater than 1. 

The limitation of the number of bids and overbids will now be used for a 
simplification of the entire scheme. In the actual play one of the players 
begins with the initial bid; after that the players alternate. 

The advantage or disadvantage contained in the possession of the 
initiative by one player but concurrent with the necessity of acting first! 
constitutes an interesting problem in itself. We shall discuss an (unsym- 
metric) form of Poker where this plays a role in 19.14., 19.15. But we 
wish at first to avoid being saddled ^yvith this problem too. In other words, 
we wish to avoid for the moment all deviations from symmetry, so as to 
obtain the other essential features of Poker in their purest and simplest 
form. We shall therefore assume that the two players both make initial 
bids, each one ignorant of the other's choice. Only after both have made 
this bid is each one informed of what the other did, i.e. whether his bid was 
"high "or "low." 

19.3.2. We simplify further by giving to the players only the choice of 
"Passing" or "Seeing," i.e. by excluding "Overbidding." Indeed, "Over- 
bidding" is only a more elaborate and intensive expression of the tendency 
which is already contained in a high initial bid. Since we wish to do things 
as simply as possible, we shall avoid providing several channels for the same 
tendency. (Cf. however (C) in 19.11. and 19.14., 19.15.). 

Accordingly we prescribe these conditions: Consider the moment 
when both players are informed of each other's bids. If it then develops 
that both bid "high" or that both bid "low," then the hands are compared 
and the player with the stronger hand receives the amount a or b respectively 
from his opponent. If their hands are equal, no payment is made. If on 
the other hand one bids "high" and one bids "low," then the player with 
the low bid has the choice of "Passing" or "Seeing." "Passing" means 
that he pays to the opponent the amount of the low bid (without any 
consideration of their hands). "Seeing" means that he changes over 
from his "low" bid to the "high" one, and the situation is treated as if 
they both had bid "high" in the first place. 

19.4. Exact Formulation of the Rules 

19.4. We can now sum up the preceding description of our simplified 
Poker by giving an exact statement of the rules agreed upon: 

First, by a chance move each player obtains his "hand," a number 
s = 1, S, each one of these numbers having the same probability 1/5. 
We denote the hands of players 1, 2, by 81, 82 respectively. 

After this each player will, by a personal move, choose either a or b, 
the "high" or "low" bid. Each player makes his choice (bid) informed 



POKER AND BLUFFING 191 

about his own hand, but not about his opponent's hand or choice (bid). 
Lastly, each player is informed about the other's choice but not about his 
hand. (Each still knows his own hand and choice.) If it turns out that 
one bids "high" and the other "low," then the latter has the choice of 
'' Seeing" or "Passing." 

This is the play. When it is concluded the payments are made as 
follows: If both players bid "high," or if one bids "high," and the other 

bids "low" but subsequently "Sees," then for i = $ 2 player 1 obtains 

< 
a 
from player 2 the amount respectively. If both players bid "low," 

a 

> b 

then for si = s 2 player 1 obtains from player 2 the amount respectively. 

< -b 

If one player bids "high," and the other bids "low" and subsequently 

"Passes," then the "high bidder" being ^ player 1 obtains from player 2 

the amount , . 
o 

19.6. Description of the Strategies 

19.6.1. A (pure) strategy in this game consists clearly of the following 
specifications : To state for every " hand " s = 1, , S whether a "high" 
or a "low" bid will be made, and in the latter case the further statement 
whether, if this "low" bid runs into a "high" bid of the opponent, the player 
will "See" or "Pass." It is simpler to describe this by a numerical index 
i. = 1, 2, 3; i t = I meaning a "high" bid; i, = 2 meaning a "low" bid 
with subsequent "Seeing" (if the occasion arises); t. = 3 meaning a "low" 
bid with subsequent "Passing" (if the occasion arises). Thus the strategy 
is a specification of such an index i, for every s = 1, , S, i.e. of the 
sequence t'i, , is. 

This applies to both players 1 and 2. Accordingly we shall denote the 
above strategy by 2i(t'i, is) or 2 2 ( ji, , js). 

Thus each player has the same number of strategies: as many as there 
are sequences i\ } , is, i.e. precisely 3 s . With the notations of 11.2.2. 

0i = 182 = = 3 s . 

1 For the sake of absolute formal correctness this should still be arranged according 
to the patterns of 6. and 7. in Chapter II. Thus the two first-mentioned chance moves 
(the dealing of hands) should be called moves 1 and 2; the two subsequent personal njoves 
(the bids), moves 3 and 4; and the final personal move ("Passing" or "Seeing"), move 5. 

In the case of move 5, both the player whose personal move it is, and the number 
of alternatives, depend on the previous course of the play as described in 7.1.2. and 9.1.5. 
(If both players bid "high" or both bid "low," then the number of alternatives is 1, and 
it does not matter to which player we ascribe this vacuous personal move. If one bids 
"high" and the other bids "low," then the personal move is the "low" bidder's). 

A consistent use of the notations loc. cit. would also necessitate writing <n, <n for 
i, I;<TI, <rifor the "high" or "low" bid;** for "Passing" or "Seeing." 

We leave it to the reader to iron out all these differences. 



192 



ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 



If we wanted to adhere rigorously to the notations of loc. cit., we should 
now enumerate the sequences fi, , i s with a r\ = 1, , ft and then 
denote the (pure) strategies of the players 1, 2 by S^, S^. But we prefer 
to continue with our present notations. 

We must now express the payment which player 1 receives if the strate- 
gies 2i(t"i, , is), 2j(ji, , js) are used by the two players. This 
is the matrix element 3C(i\, , t'alji, * * , js). 1 

If the players have actually the "hands" i, $2 then the payment 
received by player 1 can be expressed in this way (using the rules stated 
above): It is 90n (t-j(i it j,) where sgn($i s 2 ) is the sign of s\ s 2 , 2 and 
where the three functions 

+(i, j), JB (t, j), -(*, j) f, j = 1, 2, 3. 
can be represented by the following matrix schemes: 3 



^ 


1 


2 


3 


1 


a 


a 


& 


2 


a 


6 


& 


3 


-6 


6 


6 



\ 3 


1 


2 


3 


1 








& 


2 











3 


-6 









\j 


1 


2 


3 


1 


a 


a 


b 


2 


a 


-6 


-b 


3 


-6 


-b 


-& 



Figure 36. Figure 37. Figure 38. 

Now i, s 2 originate from chance moves, as described above. Hence 

8 

1 

9 a i, , ja) 2 

19.5.2. We now pass to the (mixed) strategies in the sense of 17.2. 

These are the vectors , rj belonging to Sp. Considering the notations 
1 The entire sequence t'i, , is is the row index, and the'entire sequence ji t , 

ja is the column index. In our original notations the strategies were Si, Sj and the 

matrix element 3C(n, r 2 ). 

-I- > 

1 I.e. for s i 8 t respectively. It expresses in an arithmetical form which hand is 

stronger. 

8 The reader will do well to compare these matrix schemes with our verbal statements 
of the rules, and to verify their appropriateness. 

Another circumstance which is worth observing is that the symmetry of the game 
corresponds to the identities 

M*. 3) m --(/ 0. o(i, j) -JBo(j, 
4 The reader may verify 



as a consequence of the relations at the end of footnote 3 above. I.e. 

3C(ti f , ia\ji, - ,j 5 ) 
is skew-symmetric, expressing once more the, symmetry of the game. 



POKER AND BLUFFING 193 

which we are now using, we must index the components of these vectors 

also in the new way: We must write fy i , ^ ig instead of v i? v 

We express (17:2) of 17.4.1., which evaluates the expectation value of 
player 1's gain 



, if) = 



There is an advantage in interchanging the two S and writing 

K( { , 77 ) = gj 2} 2^ Snri.c,-.,) (*'.,, j'Ofc, ..... ^ ..... v 

i.t i ..... /! ..... Js 
If we now put 



(19:1) 

*ii i^d 'excluding , 



(19:2) <rj, = 

/IP J's excluding /. f 



then the above equation becomes 
(19:3) K(7, 7) = 



i,i tj 

It is worth while to expound the meaning of (19:1)-(19:3) verbally. 
(19:1) shows that pji is the probability that player 1, using the mixed 

strategy , will choose i when his "hand" is a\\ (19:2) shows that a-J is the 


probability that player 2, using the mixed strategy y , will choose j when his 

"hand" is S2. 1 Now it is intuitively clear that the expectation value 

> > 

K( , rj ) depends on these probabilities p{, <r$ only, and not on the underly- 
ing probabilities fc t < a , ^ ^ themselves. 2 The formula (19:3) can 

1 We know from 19 4. that i or; - 1 means a "high" bid, t - 2, 3 a "low" bid with 
(the intention of) a subsequent "Seeing" or "Passing" respectively. 

2 This means that two different mixtures of (pure) strategies may in actual effect be 
the same thing. 

Let us illustrate this by a simple example. Put S 2, i.e. let there be only a "high " 
and a "low" hand. Consider i - 2, 3 as one thing, i.e. let there be only a "high" and a 



194 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 

easily be seen to be correct in this direct way: It suffices to remember 
the meaning of the JB w < ti -. t )(i, j) and the interpretation of the pji, <rj. 

19.5.3. It is clear, both from the meaning of the pji, o-Ji and from their 
formal definition (19:1), (19:2), that they fulfill the .conditions 

3 

(19:4) all P ; ^ 0, p\> = 1 

t-i 

3 

(19:5) allcr}.0, irj. = 1 

On the other hand, any pji, aj which fulfill these conditions can be obtained 

from suitable , 77 by (19:1), (19:2). This is clear mathematically, 1 and 
intuitively as well. Any such system of pji, <rj is one of probabilities which 
define a possible modus procedendi, so they must correspond to some mixed 
strategy. 

(19:4), (19:5) make it opportune to form the 3-dimensional vectors 

P' 1 = (Pi 1 , P?S Pa 1 }, *'* = {*i f , <r' 2 2 , <rj|. 

Then (19:4), (19:5) state precisely that all p*i, a** belong to 5 3 . 

This shows how much of a simplification the introduction of these 

vectors is: (or 77 ) was a vector in 50, i.e. depending on ft 1 = 3 s 1 

* * 

numerical constants; the p '* (or the a ) are 5 vectors in 5 8 , i.e. each one 

depends on 2 numerical constants; hence they amount together to 25 
numerical constants. And 3 s 1 is much greater than 25, even for moder- 
ate 5. 2 

"low" bid. Then there are four possible (pure) strategies, to which we shall give names* 

"Bold": Bid "high" on every hand. 

"Cautious": Bid "low" on every hand. 

"Normal": Bid "high" on a "high" hand, "low" on a "low" hand. 

"Bluff": Bid "high" on a "low" hand, "low" on a "high" hand. 

Then a 50-50 mixture of "Bold" and "Cautious" is in effect the same thing as a 
50-50 mixture of "Normal" and "Bluff": both mean that the player will according 
to chance bid 50-50 "high" or "low" on any hand. 

Nevertheless these are, in our present notations, two different "mixed" strategies, 

i.e. vectors . 

This means, of course, that our notations, which were perfectly suited to the general 
case, are redundant for many particular games. This is a frequent occurrence in mathe- 
matical discussions with general aims. 

There was no reason to take account of this redundance as long as we were working 
out the general theory. But we shall remove it now for the particular game under 
consideration. 

1 Put e.g. fy i s - P { t . . . p* , i, , t , a - <7} v . . . <r, s and verify the (17:1 :a), 

(17:1 :b) of 17.2.1. as consequences of the above (19:4), (19:5). 

8 Actually S is about 2J millions (cf. footnote 4 on p. 187); so 3 s 1 and 25 are both 
great, but the former is quite exorbitantly the greater. 



POKER AND BLUFFING 195 

19.6. Statement of the Problem 

19.6. Since we are dealing with a symmetric game, we can use the char- 

"""* 
acterization of the good (mixed) strategies i.e. of the in A given in 


(17:H) of 17.11.2. It stated this: must be optimal against itself, i.e. 

> > > 

Min- K( , ij ) must be assumed for rj = . 

Now we saw in 19.5. that K( { , t\ ) depends actually on the p % a . So 

we may write for it, K(7s ,7V 1 , 7 5 ). Then (19:3) in 19.5.2. 
states (we rearrange the S somewhat) 

(19:6) K(7', ' ,7V\ , O = 55 

* * 

And the characteristic of the p l , , p 8 of a good strategy is that 

Min^ 7,K(7 l , ' ' ' ,7V 1 , - ,7 s ) 

is assumed at a l = p 1 y - - , a s = p s . The explicit conditions for this 
can be found in essentially the same way as in the similar problem of 17.9. 1. ; 
we will give a brief alternative discussion. 

The Min-* -> of (19:6) amounts to a minimum with respect to 

ff l , . . . , O 8 

> > 

each cr l , , a s separately. Consider therefore such a a . It is 

restricted only by the requirement to belong to $3, i.e. by 

3 

all o}i SO, X *'f = 1- 

y-i 

(19:6) is a linear expression in these three components ^V, orj*, cr|. Hence 

it assumes its minimum with respect to a '* there where all those component s 
<rj which do not have the smallest possible coefficient (with respect to j, 
cf. below), vanish. 

The coefficient of <r* is 

^ V . C n(. r .,)(i, J)P? to be denoted by g 7^. 

,,f 
Thus (19:6) becomes 

(19:7) K(7S , 7 5 |7s , 7 



196 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 

> 
And the condition for the minimum (with respect to a ) is this: 

(19:8) For each pair s 2 , j, for which 7} does not assume its minimum 

(in j *), we have crjt = 0. 

Hence the characteristic of a good strategy minimization at a '= p l , , 



(19 :A) p *, , p a describe a good strategy, i.e. a in J!, if and 

only if this is true: 

For each pair s 2 , j for which 7j does not assume its minimum 
(in j l ), we have p;* = 0. 

We finally state the explicit expressions for the 7<, of course by using the 
matrix schemes of Figures 36-38. They are 



(19:9:a) 7*1' =* 



2 
(ap\i + ap' 2 - 

-i 

(19:9:b) 



(19:9:c) 



19.7. Passage from the Discrete to the Continuous Problem 

19.7.1. The criterion (19 :A) of 19.6., together with the formulae (19:7), 
(19:9:a), (19:9:b), (19:9:c), can be used to determine all good strategies. 2 
This discussion is of a rather tiresome combinatorial character, involving 
the analysis of a number of alternatives. The results which are obtained 

1 We mean in j and not in s, j\ 

2 This determination has been carried out by one of us and will be published elsewhere. 



POKER AND BLUFFING 



197 



are qualitatively similar to those'which we shall derive below under some- 
what modified assumptions, except for certain differences in very delicate 
detail which may be called the "fine structure" of the strategy. We shall 
say more about this in 19.12. 

For the moment we are chiefly interested in the main features of the solu- 
tion and not in the question of "fine structure. " We begin by turning our 
attention to the " granular " structure of the sequence of possible hands 

8 = 1, - ' - , S. 

If we try to picture the strength of all possible "hands" on a scale from 
0% to 100%, or rather of fractions from to 1, then the weakest possible 
hand, 1, will correspond to 0, and the strongest possible hand, 5, to 1. 

Hence the "hand" s(= 1, , S) should be placed at z = ~ __ 1 on this 
scale. I.e. we have this correspondence: 





Old scale: 


S SB 


1 


2 


3 




S - 1 


S 




























1 


2 




S -2 


I 










S - 1 


S - I 




S - 1 





Figure 39. 

Thus the values of z fill the interval 
(19:10) ^ z g 1 

very densely, 1 but they form nevertheless a discrete sequence. This is the 
"granular" structure referred to above. We will now replace it by a 
continuous one. 

I.e. we assume that the chance move which chooses the hand s i.e. z 
may produce any z of the interval (19:10). We assume that the probability 
of any part of (19:10) is the length of that part, i.e. that z is equidistributed 
over (19:10). 2 We denote the "hands" of the two players 1, 2 by *i, z a 
respectively. 

19.7.2. This change entails that we replace the vectors 
> 

p , a -i (si, ,, = 1, , S) by vectors p , <r (0 ^ *i, z* ^ 1); but 

they are, of course, still probability vectors of the same nature as before, 
i.e. belonging to S*. In consequence, the components (probabilities) 
p' 1 , *',* (*i> s 2 = 1, , S; i, j = 1, 2, 3) give way to the components 
Pjs<rj(0 ^ *,,z 2 ^ l;i,j = 1,2,3). Similarly the y',* (in (19:9:a), (19:9:b), 
(19:9:c) of 19.6.) become 75*. 

We now rewrite the expressions for K and the 7} in the formulae (19:7), 
(19:9:a), (19:9:b), (19:9:c) in 19.6. Clearly all sums 



1 It will be remembered (cf. footnote 4 on p. 187) that.S is about 2 J millions. 
1 This is the so-called geometrical probability. 



198 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 

s s 
1 y 

must be replaced by integrals 



/: 



sums 

1-1 



by integrals 

r _ r + 

dzi, 



/* 

./O 



while isolated terms behind a factor 1//S may be neglected. 1 ' 2 These being 
understood, the formulae for K and the 7} (i.e. 7*) become: 

(19:7*) K = 

(19:9:a*) y{> = [ " (-opf - op} 



(19:9:b*) 7 J. = * (-op[. - b p ;> - fepj.)<fci + (opj. + bp' t > 

(19:9:c*) yl* 

And the characterization (19 :A) of 19.6. goes over into this: 

(19:B) The 7 (0 ^ 2 g 1) (they all belong to 8 9 ) describe a good 

strategy if and only if this is true: 

For each z, j for which 7* does not assume its minimum 
(in ,;' a )> we have pj = O. 4 

Specifically we mean the middle terms bp\* and 6pJ in (19:9:a) and (19:9:c). 
1 These terms correspond to i = * 2 , in our present set-up to z\ j, and since the 
i, 2s are continuous variables, the probability of their (fortuitous) coincidence is indeed 0. 
Mathematically one may describe these operations by saying that we are now 
carrying out the limiting process S > oo . 
8 We mean in ,; and not in z, j\ 

4 The formulae (19:7*), (19:9:a*), (19:9:6*), ( 19 :9:c*) and this criterion could also have 

> * 
been derived directly by discussing this "continuous" arrangement, with the p f i, p f i 

in place of the , 17 from the start. We preferred the lengthier and more explicit proce- 
dure followed in 19.4. -19.7. in order to make the rigor and the completeness of our proce- 
dure apparent. The reader will find it a good exercise to carry out the shorter direct 
discussion, mentioned above. 

It would be tempting to build up a theory of games, into which such continuous 
parameters enter, systematically and directly; i.e. in sufficient generality for applications 
like the present one, and without the necessity for a limiting process from discrete games. 

An interesting step in this direction was taken by /. Ville in the work referred to in 
footnote 1 on p. 154: pp. 110-113 loc. cit. The continuity assumptions made there seem, 
however, to be too restrictive for many applications, in particular for the present one. 



POKER AND BLUFFING 199 

19.8. Mathematical Determination of the Solution 

19.8.1. We now proceed to the determination of the good strategies p ', 
i.e. of the solution of the implicit condition (19:B) of 19.7. 

Assume first that p| > ever happens. 1 For such a z necessarily 
Min, 75 = y\ hence y\ ^ y* 2 i.e. 

7*2 - y\ ^ 0. 
Substituting (19:9:a*), (19:9:b*) into this gives 

(19:11) (a - 6) ( fydz, - f* P jcfei) + 26 p^dz, g 0. 

Now let z be the upper limit of these z with p\ > O. 2 Then (19:11) holds 
by continuity for z = Z Q too. As fy > does not occur for Zi > 2 by 

hypothesis so the / p dz\ term in (19:11) is now 0. So we may write it 

J *o 

with + instead of , and (19:11) becomes: 



(a - 6) P pjufei + 26 P pjufei ^ 0. 

o J * 



But p|i is always ^ and sometimes > 0, by hypothesis; hence the first 
term is > O. 8 ' 4 The second term is clearly g: 0. So we have derived 
a contradiction. I.e. we have shown 

(19:12) pj = O. 6 

19.8.2. Having eliminated j = 2 we now analyze the relationship of 
j = I and j = 3. Since p| = so p\ + pj = 1 i.e.: 

(19:13) P J = 1 - pj, 

and consequently 

(19:14) ^ pj g 1. 

Now there may exist in the interval ^ z g 1 subintervals in which 
always p* = or always p\ = I. 6 A z which is not inside any interval of 

1 I.e. that the good strategy under consideration provides for j 2, i.e. "low" 
bidding with (the intention of) subsequent "Seeing," under certain conditions. 

1 I.e. the greatest 2for which pj > occurs arbitrarily near to z. (But we do not 
require pj > for all z < Z Q .) This 2 exists certainly if the z with pj > exist. 

1 Of course a b > 0. 

4 It does not seem necessary to go into the detailed fine points of the theory of integra- 
tion, measure, etc. We assume that our functions are smooth enough so that a positive 
function has a positive integral etc. An exact treatment could be given with ease if we 
made use of the pertinent mathematical theories mentioned above. 

8 The reader -should reformulate this verbally: We excluded "low" bids with (the 
intention of) subsequent "Seeing" by analysing conditions for the (hypothetical) upper 
limit of the hands for which this would be done; and showed that near there, at least, an 
outright "high" bid would be preferable. 

This is, of course, conditioned by our simplification which forbids "overbidding." 

6 I.e. where the strategy directs the player to bid always "high," or where it directs 
him to bid always "low" (with subsequent "Passing"). 



200 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 

either kind i.e. arbitrarily near to which both pj' 5* and pf ^ 1 occur 

will be called intermediate. Since p\' ^ or p\' 7* 1 (i.e. p|' /^ 0) imply 

Min, 75' = 7*' or y\ f respectively, therefore we see: Both y[' g y s ' and 

7*' ^ 7a' occur arbitrarily near to an intermediate 2. Hence for such a z, 
y\ = 7s by continuity, 1 i.e. 

7' 8 - 7! = 0. 

Substituting (19:9:a*), (19:9:c*) and recalling (19:12), (19:13), gives 

(a + 6) ( Z p^dz, - (a - 6) f l p^dz, + 26 f l (1 - P \^dz l = 
JQ Js Jt 

i.e. 

(19:15) (a + 6) p^dz, - Vi^i + 26 ( 1 - *) = 0. 



Consider next two intermediate ', z". Apply (19:15) to z = z' and 
e = z" and subtract. Then 

2(a + b) 
obtains, i.e. 

(19:16) 



Verbally: Between two intermediate z', z" the average of p{ is -r , 
So neither p* s= nor p\ = 1 can hold throughout the interval 

z' g z ^ z" 

since that would yield the average or 1. Hence this interval must contain 
(at least) a further intermediate z, i.e. between any two intermediate places 
there lies (at least) a third one. Iteration of this result shows that between 
two intermediate z', z" the further intermediate z lie everywhere dense. 
Hence the z', z" for which (19:16) holds lie everywhere dense between z', z" . 
But then (19:16) must hold for all 5', z" between 2', z", by continuity. 2 

This leaves no alternative but that pi = r r everywhere between z' z" * 

a -r o 

1 The 7* are defined by integrals (19:9:a*), (19:9:b*), ( 19 :9:c*), hence they are certainly 
continuous. 

1 The integral in (19:16) is certainly continuous. 

* Clearly isolated exceptions covering a z area i.e. of total probability zero (e.g. a 
finite number of fixed z's) could be permitted. They alter no integrals. An exact 
mathematical treatment would be easy but does not seem to be called for in this context 

(cf. footnote 4 on p. 199). So it seems simplest to assume pf pr in 2' ^ z <: 2" 

a -p o 

without any exceptions. 

This ought to be kept in mind when appraising the formulae of the next pages which 
deal with the interval 2' ^ z ^ 2" on one hand, and with the intervals : z < I 1 and 
I" < z' g 1 on the other; i.e. which count the points 2', I" to the first-mentioned interval. 
This is, of course, irrelevant: two fixed isolated points z' and z" in this case could 
be disposed of in any way (cf. above). 

The reader must observe, however, that while there is no significant difference 



POKER AND BLUFFING 201 

19.8.3. Now if intermediate z exist at all, then there exists a smallest 
one and a largest one; choose z', 2" as these. We have 

(19:17) p\ = ^pj throughout ti z z". 

If no intermediate z exist, then we must have p\ = (for all z) or p\ ss 1 
(for all z). It is easy to see that neither is a solution. 1 Thus intermediate z 
do exist and with them z', z" exist and (19:17) is valid. 

19.8.4. The left hand side of (19:15) is y\ - y\ for all z\ hence for z = 1 



(since pi i = is excluded). By continuity y\ y\ > 0, i.e. 7i < 7! remains 
true even when z is merely near enough to 1. Hence pj = 0, i.e. p* = 1 for 
these z. Thus (19:17) necessitates z" < 1. Now no intermediate z exists 
in 2" ^ z g 1; hence we have p\ = or p\ = 1 throughout this interval. 
Our preceding result excludes the former. Hence 

(19:18) pi s 1 throughout z" ^ z 1. 

19.8.5. Consider finally the lower end of (19:17), z'. If z' > then we 
have an interval ^ z g z'. This interval contains no intermediate z; 
hence we have p\ = or pi = 1 throughout z '. The first derivative 
of 7S - 7ii i-e- of the left side of (19:15), is clearly 2(a + 6)pi - 26. Hence 
in ^ z < z' this derivative is 2(a + 6) - 26 = 26 < if pi as 
there, 2(a + 6) 1 - 26 = 2a > if p\ = 1 there, i.e. 7*3 - y\ is monotone 
decreasing or increasing respectively, throughout ^ z < z f . Since its 
value is at the upper end (the intermediate point z')> we have 73 7* > 
or < respectively, i.e. y\ < y\ or 75 < y\ respectively, throughout 
^ z < '. The former necessitates p\ = 0, pi ss 1 the latter pi = in 
^ z < z'\ but the hypotheses with which we started were pi as or pi B 1 
respectively, there. So there is u contradiction in each case. 

Consequently 

(19:19) z' = 0. 

19.8.6. And now we determine z" by expressing the validity of (19:15) 
for the intermediate z = z' = 0. Then (19:15) becomes 

-(a + 6) f 1 pi^ 1 + 26 = 



between a < and a ^ when the z'a themselves are compared, this is not so for the y' r 
Thus we saw that y' > y\ implies p\ - 0, while y\ ^ 71 nas no such consequence. 
(Cf. also the discussion of Fig. 41 and of Figs. 47, 48.) 

1 I.e. bidding "low" (with subsequent "Pass") under all conditions is not a good 
strategy; nor is bidding "high" under all conditions. 

Mathematical proof: For p\ m 0: Compute 7? - -6, 71 - & hence 7? < y\ 
contradicting p\ - 1 ^ 0. For pj m 1: Compute 7? - <*, 7i - & hence 7? < ?! 
contradicting pj 1 ^ 0. 



202 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 

But (19:17), (19:18), (19:19) give 



r^-r.-J^ + u-n-i 

Jo a + b 



+ 6 
So we have 

26 



+ 6 

o 2/ , = t _ 26 = g-6 
+ 6 + 6 + 6' 

i.e. 

(19:20) 2" = "-- 

Combining (19:17), (19:18), (19:19), (19:20) gives: 
6 for g z g ^=- 



(19:21) ,1 + b 



= 1 for 



Together with (19:12), (19:13) this characterizes the strategy completely. 

19.9. Detailed Analysis of the Solution 

19.9.1. The results of 19.8. ascertain that there exists one and only one 
good strategy in the form of Poker under consideration. 1 It is described 
by (19:21), (19:12), (19:13) in 19.8. We shall give a graphical picture of this 
strategy which will make it easier to discuss it verbally in what follows. 
(Cf. Figure 40. The actual proportions of this figure correspond to 
a/6 ~ 3.) 

The line plots the curve p = p\. Thus the height of above 

the line p = is the probability of a "high" bid: p\; the height of the line 
p = 1 above is the probability of a "low" bid (necessarily with sub- 
sequent "pass"): p\ = 1 p\. 

19.9.2. The formulae (19:9:a*), (19:9:b*), (19:9:c*) of 19.7. permit us 
now to compute the coefficients 7*. We give the graphical representations 
instead of the formulae, leaving the elementary verification to the reader. 
(Cf. Figure 41. The actual proportions are those of Figure 40, i.e. a/6 ~ 3 

cf. there.) The line plots the curve 7 = 7*; the line plots the 

curve 7 = 7j ; the line plots the curve 7 = y\. The figure shows that 

1 We have actually shown only that nothing else but the strategy determined in 19.8. 
can be good. That this strategy is indeed good, could be concluded from the established 
existence of (at least) a good strategy, although our passage to the "continuous" case 
may there create some doubt. But we shall verify below that the strategy in question is 
good, i.e. that it fulfills (19:B) of 19.7. 



POKER AND BLUFFING 
and (i.e. y\ and 75) coincide in g z g a ~ 



203 

and that and 



(i.e. y\ and 7$) coincide in ^ z ^ 1. All three curves are made 



a - 6 
a 

Figure 40. 




Figure 41. 



of two linear pieces each, joining at z = 



a - 6 



The actual values of the 



7* at the critical points 



0, , 1 are given in the figure. 1 



1 The simple computational verification of these results is left to the reader. 



204 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 

19.9.3. Comparison of Figures 40 and 41 shows that our strategy is 
indeed good, i.e. that it fulfills (19 :B) of 19.7. Indeed: In ^ z ^ ^ 
where both p{ 5^ 0, pj 5* both y{ and yl are the lowest curves, i.e. equal 
to Min, y'j. In fl ~" < z ^ 1 where only p{ 5* there only 7? is the 

lowest curve, i.e. equal to Min, y]. (The behavior of y\ does not matter, 
since always pj = 0.) 

We can also compute K from (19:7*) in 19.7., the value of a play. K = 
is easily obtained; and this is the value to be expected since the game is 
symmetric. 

19.10. Interpretation of the Solution 

19.10.1. The results of 19.8., 19.9., although mathematically complete, 
call for a certain amount of verbal comment and interpretation, which we 
now proceed to give. 

First the picture of the good strategy, as given in Figure 40, indicates 
that for a sufficiently strong hand p{ = 1; i.e. that the player should then 

bid "high," and nothing else. This is the case for hands z > For 

weaker hands, however, p\ = ^r~r> p\ = 1 pf = . , ; so both p{, pj 7* 0; 
i.e. the player should then bid irregularly "high" and "low" (with specified 
probabilities). This is the case for hands z g The "high" bids 

(in this case) should be rarer than the "low" ones, indeed -| = -=- and a > 6. 

PI o 

This last formula shows too that the last kind of "high" bids become 
increasingly rare if the cost of a "high" bid (relative to a "low" one) 
increases. 

Now these "high" bids on "weak" hands made irregularly, governed 
by (specified) probabilities only, and getting rarer when the cost of "high" 
bidding is increased invite an obvious interpretation: These are the 
"Bluffs" of ordinary Poker. 

Due to the extreme simplifications which we applied to Poker for the 
purpose of this discussion, "Bluffing" comes up in a very rudimentary form 
only; but the symptoms are nevertheless unmistakable: The player is 

advised to bid always "high" on a strong hand f z > J and to bid 

mostly "low" (with the probability jpr-j) on a "low" one ( z < ?-ZjM 
but with occasional, irregularly distributed "Bluffs" (with the probability 



POKER AND BLUFFING 205 

19.10.2. Second, the conditions in the zone of "Bluffing," z a , 

a 

throw some light on another matter too, the consequences of deviating 
from the good strategy, "permanent optimality," "defensive," "offensive," 
as discussed in 17.10.1., 17.10.2. 

Assume that player 2 deviates from the good strategy, i.e. uses proba- 
bilities (Ty which may differ from the pj obtained above. Assume, further- 
more, that player 1 still uses those p*, i.e. the good strategy. Then we can 
use for the 7' of (19:9a*), (19:9:b*), (19:9:c*) in 19.7., the graphical repre- 
sentation of Figure 41, and express the outcome of the play for player 1 
by (19:7*) in 19.7. 

(19:22) 

Consequently player 2's <r* are optimal against player 1's p* if the analogue 
of the condition (19:8) in 19.6. is fulfilled: 

(19 :C) For each pair z, j for which y] does not assume its minimum 

(in j *) we have a* = 0. 

I.e. (19 :C) is necessary and sufficient for <7* being just as good against pj as p* 
itself, that is, giving a K = 0. Otherwise a] is worse, that is, giving a 
K > 0. In other words: 

(19 :D) A mistake, i.e. a strategy <r* which deviates from the good 

strategy pj will cause no losses when the opponent sticks to the 
good strategy if and only if the a* fulfill (19 :C) above. 

Now one glance at Figure 41 suffices to make it clear that (19 :C) means 

a | = ff\ = for z > a "" but merely a\ = for z ^ a ~^^ I.e.: (19:C) 
ct a 

prescribes "high" bidding, and nothing else, for strong hands ( z > J; 

it forbids "low" bidding with subsequent "Seeing" for all hands, but it 
foils to prescribe the probability ratio of "high" bidding and of "low" 
bidding (with subsequent "Passing") for weak hands, i.e. in the zone of 

"Bluffing" 



19.10.3. Thus any deviation from the good strategy which involves 
more than just incorrect "Bluffing," leads to immediate losses. It suffices 
for the opponent to stick to the good strategy. Incorrect "Bluffing" 
causes no losses against an opponent playing the good strategy; but the 

1 We mean in j, and not in *, j! 

a b 
1 Actually even ?* would be permitted at the one place z But this 

isolated value of * has probability and so it can be disregarded. Of. footnote 3 on 
p. 200. 



206 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 

opponent could inflict losses by deviating appropriately from the good 
strategy. I.e. the importance of "Bluffing" lies not in the actual play, 
played against a good player, but in the protection which it provides against 
the opponent's potential deviations from the good strategy. This is in 
agreement with the remarks made at the end of 19.2., particularly with the 
second interpretation which we proposed there for " Bluffing." 1 Indeed, the 
element of uncertainty created by "Bluffing" is just that type of constraint 
on the opponent's strategy to which we referred there, and which was ana- 
lyzed at the end of 19.2. 

Our results on "bluffing" fit in also with the conclusions of 17.10.2. 
We see that the unique good strategy of this variant of Poker is not per- 
manently optimal; hence no permanently optimal strategy exists there. 
(Cf. the first remarks in 17.10.2., particularly footnote 3 on p. 163.) And 
"Bluffing" is a defensive measure in the sense discussed in the second half 
of 17.10.2. 

19.10.4. Third and last, let us take a look at the offensive steps indicated 
loc. cit., i.e. the deviations from good strategy by which a player can profit 
from his opponent's failure to "Bluff" correctly. 

We reverse the roles: Let player 1 " Bluff " incorrectly, i.e. use p* different 
from those of Figure 40. Since only incorrect "Bluffing" is involved, we 
still assume 

p* 2 == for all z 

a-b 



Pf = 1 I 
Pi = / 



r n ^ 

for all z > 



So we are interested only in the consequences of 

(19:23) p\ % ^-~ for some z = Z Q < ^~' 2 

The left hand side of (19:15) in 19.8. is still a valid expression for y\ 7*!. 

Consider now a z < z . Then ^ in (19:23) leaves / p^dzi unaffected, but 

Jo 

., increases n _ , , ., decreases ,, , ~, , , ., f ,+* * e \ 

it , / pi^azi hence it . the left hand side of (19:15), i.e. 

decreases J z increases 

7s 7i- Since y\ y\ would be without the change (19:23) (cf. Figure 
41), so it will now be ^ 0. I.e. y\ ^ y\. Consider next a z in 

/ ^ a - 6 

ZQ < Z ^ 

a 

1 All this holds for the form of Poker now under consideration. For further view- 
points cf. 19.16. 

2 We need this really for more than one z, cf. footnote 3 on p. 200. The simplest 
assumption is that these inequalities hold in a small neighborhood of the ZD in question. 

It would be easy to treat this matter rigorously in the sense of footnote 4 on p. 199 
and of footnote 3 on p. 200. We refrain from doing it for the reason stated there. 



POKER AND BLUFFING 207 

Then ^ in (19:23) " 1 " eases f* p ^ Zl wn ii e jt leaves f ' p{fei unaffected; 

increases 

hence it , the left hand side of (19:15), i.e. 7} y\. Since y\ y\ 

would be without the change (19:23) (cf. Fig. 41), so it will now be ^ 0. 
I.e. 7f ^ 75. Summing up: 

(19 :E) The change (19:23) with ^ causes 

7s % y\ for z < z , 
7' 3 % 7l for z, < z ~^- 

Hence the opponent can gain, i.e. decrease the K of (19:22), t?y using &* 

which differ from the present pj: For z < z by increasing * at the expense 

i 

of ff \, i.e. by . -erf from the value of pf, jj-i to the extreme value , 

<rj increasing ' a + b 1 

And for ZQ < z ^ --- by increasing * at the expense of ** i.e. by , . 

a <r| ^ <r\ decreasing 

a\ from the value of pf, . to the extreme value n In other words: 

(19:F) If the opponent " Bluffs" too .. . for a certain hand ZQ, then 

little 

he can be punished by the following deviations from the good 



strategy: " Bluffing" for hands weaker than z^ and "Bluff- 

ing" , for hands stronger than ZQ. 
less 

I.e. by imitating his mistake for hands which are stronger 
than ZQ and by doing the opposite for weaker ones. 

These are the precise details of how correct " Bluffing" protects against 
too much or too little "Bluffing" of the opponent, and its immediate 
consequences. Reflections in this direction could be carried even beyond 
this point, but we do not propose to pursue this subject any further. 

19.11. More General Forms of Poker 

19.11. While the discussions which we have now concluded throw a 
good deal of light on the strategical structure and the possibilities of Poker, 
they succeeded only due to our far reaching simplification of the rules of 
the game. These simplifications were formulated and imposed in 19.1., 
19.3. and 19.7. For a real understanding of the game we should now 
make an effort to remove them. 

By this we do not mean that all the fanciful complications of the game 
which we have eliminated (cf. 19.1.) must necessarily be reinstated, 1 

1 Nor do we wish, yet to consider anything but a two-person game! 



208 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 

but some simple and important features of the game were equally lost and 
their reconsideration would be of great advantage. We mean in particular: 

(A) The " hands " should be discrete, and not continuous. (Cf. 19.7.) 

(B) There should be more than two possible ways to bid. (Cf. 19.3.) 

(C) There should be more than one opportunity for each player to bid, 
and alternating bids, instead of simultaneous ones, should also be considered. 
(Cf. 19.3.) 

The problem of meeting these desiderata (A), (B), (C) simultaneously 
and finding the good strategies is unsolved. Therefore we must be satis- 
fied for the moment to add (A), (B), (C) separately. 

The complete solutions for (A) and for (B) are known, while for (C) 
only a very limited amount of progress has been made. It would lead 
too far to give all these mathematical deductions in detail, but we shall 
report briefly the results concerning (A), (B), (C). 

19.12. Discrete Hands 

19.12.1. Consider first (A). I.e. let us return to the discrete scale of 
hands s = 1, , S as introduced at the end of 19.1.2., and used in 
19.4-19.7. In this case the solution is in many ways similar to that of 
Figure 40. Generally pj = and there exists a certain 5 such that pf = 1 

for s > s, while p\ j 0, 1 for s < s. Also, if we change to the z scale (cf. 
s o __ } a ^ 

Fig. 39) , then -~ r is very nearly l So we have a zone of " Bluffing " 

o 1 d 

and above it a zone of "high" bids, just as in Fig. 40. 

But the p\ for s < s, i.e. in the zone of " Bluffing," are not at all equal 

to or near to the , , of Fig. 40. 2 They oscillate around this value by 

amounts which depend on certain arithmetical peculiarities of S but do not 
tend to disappear for S > oo . The averages of the p\ however, tend to 

: r- 3 In other words: 
a + b 

The good strategy of the discrete game is very much like the good 
strategy of the continuous game: this is true for all details as far as the 
division into two zones (of "Bluffing" and of "high" bids) is concerned; 
also for the positions and sizes of these zones, and for the events in the zone 
of "high" bids. But in the zone of "Bluffing" it applies only to average 
statements (concerning several hands of approximately equal strength). 
The precise procedures for individual hands may differ widely from those 

* Precisely: %-^-l - ^^ for S -* . 

o 1 fl 

b 
2 I.e. not PI -* 7 for S > < whatever the variability of . 

1 b 

* Actually (pf + P?* 1 ) - T for most a < . 



POKER AND BLUFFING 209 

given in Figure 40, and depend on arithmetical peculiarities of 8 and S 
(with respect to a/6). 1 

19.12.2. Thus the strategy which corresponds more precisely to Figure 40 

i.e. where p[ m for all a < s is not good, and it differs quite 

considerably from the good one. Nevertheless it can be shown that the 
maximal loss which can be incurred by playing this "average" strategy 
is not great. More precisely, it tends to f or S >.* 

So we see: In the discrete game the correct way of " Bluffing " has a 
very complicated "fine structure," which however secures only an extremely 
small advantage to the player who uses it. 

This phenomenon is possibly typical, and recurs in much more compli- 
cated real games. It shows how extremely careful one must be in asserting 
or expecting continuity in this theory. 3 But the practical importance 
-i.e. the gains and losses caused seems to be small, and the whole thing 
is probably terra incognita to even the most experienced players. 

19.13. m possible Bids 

19.13.1. Consider, second, (B) : I.e. let us keep the hands continuous, but 
permit bidding in more than two ways. I.e. we replace the two bids 

a >6(>0) 
by a greater number, say m, ordered: 

ai > a 2 > > a m _i > a m (> 0). 

In this case too the solution bears a certain similarity to that of Figure 40. 4 
There exists a certain z 6 such that for z > Z Q the player should make the 
highest bid, and nothing else, while for z < 2 he should make irregularly 
various bids (always including the highest bid a, but also others), with 
specified probabilities. Which bids he must make and with what proba- 

1 Thus in the equivalent of Figure 40, the left part of the figure will not be a straight 
line (P " TT in S 2 ^ j, but one which oscillates violently around this 

average. 

1 It is actually of the order 1 /S. Remember that in real Poker S is about 2} millions. 
(Cf. footnote 4 on p. 187.) 

1 Recall in this connection the remarks made in the second part of footnote 4 on p. 
198. 

4 It has actually been determined only under the further restriction of the rules which 
forbids "Seeing" a higher bid. I.e. each player is expected to make his final, highest bid 
at once, and to "Pass" (and accept the consequences) if the opponent's bid should turn 
out higher than his. 

a - 6 
1 Analogue of the z in Figure 40. 



210 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 

bilities, is determined by the value of z. 1 So we have a zone of "Bluffing" 
and above it a zone of "high" bids actually of the highest bid and nothing 
else just as in Figure 40. But the "Bluffing" in its own zone z g Z Q 
has a much more complicated and varying structure than in Figure 40. 

We shall not go into a detailed analysis of this structure, although 
it offers some quite interesting aspects. We shall, however, mention one of 
its peculiarities. 

19.13.2. Let two values 

a > b > 

be given, and use them as highest and lowest bids: 

di = dj a m == b. 

Now let m > and choose the remaining bids a*, - , a m -i so that they 
fill the interval 

(19:24) 6 g x ^a 

with unlimited increasing density. (Cf. the two examples to be given in 
footnote 2 below.) If the good strategy described above now tends to a 
limit i.e. to an asymptotic strategy for m oo then one could interpret 
this as a good strategy for the game in which only upper and lower bounds 
are set for the bids (a and 6), and the bids can be anything in between (i.e. 
in (19:24)). I.e. the requirement of a minimum interval between bids 
mentioned at the beginning of 19.3. is removed. 

Now this is not the case. E.g. we can interpolate the a 2 , , a m _i 
between ai = a and a m = b both in arithmetic and in geometric sequence. 2 
In both cases an asymptotic strategy obtains for m > but the two strate- 
gies differ in many essential details. 

If we consider the game in which all bids (19:24) are permitted, as one 
in its own right, then a direct determination of its good strategies is possible. 

1 If the bids which he must make are ai, a p , a fl , , a n (l < p < q < < n), 
then it can be shown that their probabilities must be 

111 If 1,1, , 1 

, ,_,... , I c -- j --- h + 
ca\ ca p ca q ca n V at a p a,, 

respectively. I.e. if a certain bid is to be made at all, then its probability must be 
inversely proportional to the cost. 

Which Op, a c , a m actually occur for a given z is determined by a more com- 
plicated criterion, which we shall not discuss here. 

Observe that the c above was needed only to make the sum of all probabilities 
equal to 1. The reader may verify for himself that the probabilities in Figure 40 have 
the above values. 

1 The first one is defined by 

a, - - T ((m - p)a + (p - 1)6) for p - 1, 2, , m - 1, m 
m i 

the second one is defined by 



a p m ~a m ~*b*~ l for p 1, 2, , m 1, m. 



POKER AND BLUFFING 211 

It turns out that both strategies mentioned above are good, together with 
many others. 

This chows to what complications the abandonment of a minimum inter- 
val between bids can lead: a good strategy of the limiting case cannot be an 
approximation for the good strategies of all nearby cases with a finite num- 
ber of bids. The concluding remarks of 19.12. are thus re-emphasized. 

19.14. Alternate Bidding 

19.14.1. Third and last, consider (C) : The only progress so far made in 
this direction is that we can replace the simultaneous bids of the two players 
by two successive ones; i.e. by an arrangement in which player 1 bids first 
and player 2 bids afterwards. 

Thus the rules stated in 19.4. are modified as follows: 

First each player obtains, by a chance move, his hand 8 = 1, , S, 
each one of these numbers having the same probability l/S. We denote 
the hands of players 1, 2, by Si, 2 respectively. 

After this 1 player 1 will, by a personal move, choose either a or 6, the 
"high" or the "low" bid. 2 He does this informed about his own hand 
but not about the opponent's hand. If his bid is "low," then the play is 
concluded. If his bid is "high," then player 2 will, by a personal move, 
choose either a or 6, the "high " or the "low " bid. 3 He does this informed 
about his own hand, and about the opponent's choice, but not his hand. 

This is the play. When it is concluded, the payments are made as 

> 

follows: If player 1 bids "low," then for si = s 2 player 1 obtains from player 

< 

b > 

2 the amount respectively. If both players bid " high," then for Si = s 2 
-6 < 

a 
player 1 obtains from player 2 the amount respectively. If player 1 

a 

bids "high" and player 2 bids "low," then player 1 obtains from player 2 
the amount b. 4 

19.14.2. The discussion of the pure and mixed strategies can now be 
carried out, essentially as we did for our original variant of Poker in 19.5. 

We give the main lines of this discussion in a way which will be per- 
fectly clear for the reader who remembers the procedure of 19.4.-19.7. 

A pure strategy in this game consists clearly of the following specifica- 
tions: to state for every hand s = 1, , S whether a "high" or a "low" 
bid will be made. It is simpler to describe this by a numerical index 
i. = 1, 2; t. = 1 meaning a "high" bid, i. = 2 meaning a "low" bid. Thus 

1 We continue from here on as if player 2 had already made the "low" bid, and this 
were player 1's turn to "See" or to "Overbid." We disregard "Passing" at this stage. 

1 I.e. "Overbid" or "See," cf. footnote 1 above. 

8 I.e. "See" or "Pass." Observe the shift of meaning since footnote 2 above. 

4 In interpreting these rules, recall the above footnotes. From the formalist ic point 
of view, footnote 1 on p. 191 should be recalled, mutatis mutandis. 



212 



ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 



the strategy is a specification of such an index t, for every s = 1, , S 
i.e. of a sequence t'i, , is. 

This applies to both players 1 and 2; accordingly we shall denote the 
above strategy by 2i(i i, , ia) or 2*(ji y , ja). Thus each player 
has the same number of strategies, as many as there are sequences 
i, , <*; i.e. precisely 2 5 . With the notations of 11.2.2. 

0i - A - ft = 2*. 

(But the game is not symmetrical !) 

We must now express the payment which player 1 receives if the strate- 
gies 2i(ti, , is), *0*i, * , ja) are used by the two players. This is 
the matrix element OC(t'i, , ia\ji 9 , ja). If the players have 
actually hands *i, Sj then the payment received by player 1 can be expressed 
in this way (using the rules stated above): It is JB^nc^-*,)^, j f ) where 
sgn(si *) is the sign of 81 s and where the three functions 



can be represented by the following matrix schemes: 



t \ 


1 


2 


1 


a 


6 


2 


b 


b 



\j 


1 


2 


1 





6 


2 









\j 
t \ 


1 


2 


1 


a 


& 


2 


-b 


-6 



Figure 42. Figure 43. Figure 44, 

Now Si, Sj originate from chance moves, as described above. Hence: 

S 



, ja) 



- 1 



19.14.3. We now pass to the mixed strategies in the sense of 17.2. These 

> 
are vectors , 17 belonging to S a . We must index the components of these 

vectors like the (pure) strategies: we must write ^ ..... <f> ^ ..... <f instead 

Of fe,, 1?r,. 

We express (17:2) of 17.4.1. which evaluates the expectation of player 1's 
gain 



..... 



'tis, j'i, 



t. ,ta excluding t 



POKER AND BLUFFING 213 

There is an advantage in interchanging the two Z and writing 

> i VA 

K( , ? ) = - 2 2, 

pj 

If we now put 

(^25) P',= ...... V 

(19:26) < = 

J. ' i ja excluding ; j 

then the above equation becomes l 
(19:27) K(7, 7) = gi 

19.14.4. All this is precisely as in 19.5.2. As there, (19:25) shows that 

p* is the probability that player 1, using the mixed strategy will choose i 
when his hand is s\. (19:26) shows that a',* is the probability that player 2, 

using the mixed strategy 77 will choose j when his hand is s 2 . It is again 

> 
clear intuitively that the expectation value K( , 17 ) depends upon these 

probabilities only, and not on the underlying probabilities {^ ..... s , 17^,. ____ , a 
themselves. (19:27) expresses this and could have easily been derived 
directly, on this basis. 

It is also clear, both from the meaning of the p', <rj and from their formal 
definitions (19:25), (19:26), that they fulfill the conditions: 

2 

(19:28) all p}. V p}i = 1 

-i 

2 

(19:29) alUji V <rj = 1, 

;-i 
and that any p's <r} which fulfill these conditions can be obtained from 

suitable T> V by (19:25), (19:26). (Cf. the corresponding step in 19.5.?. 
particularly footnote 1 on p. 194.) It is therefore opportune to form the 
2-dimensional vectors 

P * ! - {pfs Pi'K * *' = (*i'> ^J 1 )- 
Then (19:28), (19:29) state precisely that all 7\ ^ ' belong to S. 



214 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 

Thus (or 17 ) was a vector in 8$ i.e. depending on ft 1 = 2 s 1 

constants; the p * (or <r ') are S vectors in St i.e. each one depends on one 
numerical constant, hence they amount together to S numerical constants. 
So we have reduced 2 s 1 to S. (Cf . the end of 19.5.3.) 
19.14.5. We now rewrite (19:27) as in 19.6. 

(19:30) K(7s ' ' , 7V\ , 7 s ) = ^ V 7;-*;', 

with the coefficients 

I 

S' 

i.e. using the matrix schemes of Figures 42-44, 

,-! S 

(19:31:a) 7l = g 

,-i a 

- * I V V M) 

Since the game is no longer symmetric, we need also the corresponding 
formulae in which the roles of the two players are interchanged. This is: 

(19:32) K( p ', , p V S ' ' ' , O = g 

with the coefficients 

H* .81 

S * 02 
o 

i.e. using the matrix schemes of Figures 42-44, 

i-l 8 

(19:33:a) J. = g 



(19:33:b) - g ^^ + MO + 



The criteria for good strategies are now essentially repetitions of those in 
19.6. I.e. due to the asymmetry of the variant now under consideration 
our present criterion will be obtained from the general criterion (17:D) 



POKER AND BLUFFING 215 

of 17.9. in the same way as that of 19.6. could be obtained from the sym- 
metrical criterion at the end of 17.11.2. I.e. : 

(19:G) The 7 l , , 7* and the 7 l , , 7* they all belong 

to /Si describe good strategieefif and only if this is true: 

For each t, j, for which 7* does not assume its minimum 

(in j l ) we have crj = 0. For each i, i for which 6J does not 
assume its maximum (in i *) we have pj = 0. 

19.14.6. Now we replace the discrete hands *i, *i by continuous ones, 
in the sense of 19.7. (Cf. in particular Figure 39 there.) As described in 

19.7. this replaces the vectors p \ <r (si t t = 1, , S) by vectors 

p *, <r *(0 ^ *i,2s ^ 1), which are still probability vectors of the same nature 
as before, i.e. belonging to Sj. So the components pji, <r*- make place for the 
components pji, <rjt. Similarly the 5*-, 7j become 5*, 7j. The sums in our 
formulae (19:30), (19:31 :a), (19:31:b), and (19:32), (19:33:a), (19:33:b) go 
over into integrals, just as in (19:7*), (19:9 :a*), (19:9:b*), (19:9:c*) in 19.7. 
So we obtain: 



(19:30*) K 

(19:31 *) y\> = /'' (-ap|. - bp'.Odz, + f ' (apj. + 6p{>)(b t| 

^0 / *t 

(19:31 :b*) T! = f" 0>ti l ~ b P' 
/o 



and 
(19:32*) 



(19:33:a*) ',. 

(19:33:b*) <; = f" (hrjt + bff' t >)dz t + f 1 (-bo*? - fo;)<bi. 

y ' *t 

Our criterion for good strategies is now equally transformed. (This is the 
same transition as that from the discrete criterion of 19.6. to the continuous 
criterion of 19.7.) We obtain 

(19 :H) The p f i and the <r ' (0 g * Ip zi g 1) they all belong to Si- 

describe good strategies if and only if this is true: 

For each *s, j for which 751 does not assume its minimum 
(in j 2 ) we have <r* = 0. For each * lf i for which $Ji does not 
assume its maximum (in i 2 ) we have pj = 0. 

* We mean in j (t) and not in **, ,; (t i, i) ! 
s We mean in j (t) and not in z s , ; (ci> j) ! 



216 



ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 



19.15. Mathematical Description of All Solutions 

19.15.1. The determination of the good strategies p ' and a *, i.e. of the 
solutions of the implicit condition stated at the end of 19.14., can be carried 
out completely. The mathematfcal methods which achieve this are similar 
to those with which we determined in 19.8. the good strategies of our original 
variant of Poker, i.e. the solutions of the implicit condition stated at the 
end of 19.7. 

We shall not give the mathematical discussion here, but we shall describe 

the good strategies p * and a * which it produces. 

There exists one and only one good strategy p * while the good strategies 

<r form an extensive family. (Cf . Figures 45-46. The actual proportions 
of these figures correspond to a/6 ~ 3.) 




Figure 45. 



Figure 46. 



(o - b)b 
" a(a + 36) 
a + 2a6 - 6* 
a (a + 36) 

- plot the curves p = p\ and a = a\ respectively. Thus the 



The lines - 

height of above the line p = (a = 0) is the probability of a "high" 

bid, p\ (or}) ; the height of the line p = 1 (<r = 1) above is the probability 

of a "low" bid, pj = 1 - pj fa = 1 - <rj). The irregular 

part of the v = <r* curve (in Figure 46) in the interval u ^ z ^ v represents 

the multiplicity of the good strategies a z : Indeed, this part of the o- = a\ 
curve is subject to the following (necessary and sufficient) conditions: 



I a\dz 
v - *<> J.. 



b 
a 
b 
a 



when 
when 



u 



U < 2 < V. 



Verbally: Between u and v the average of <rj is 6/a, and on any right end 
of this interval the average of a\ is j 6/a. 



POKER AND BLUFFING 



217 



Thus both p * and a * exhibit three different types of behavior on these 
three intervals: 1 

First :0 g z < u. Second :u <> z v. Third :v < z ^ 1. The lengths 
of these three intervals are u, v u, 1 v, and the somewhat complicated 
expressions for M, v can be best remembered with the help of these easily 
verified ratios: 

tt:l t; = a b:a + b 
v u:l t; = a:b. 

19.15.2. The formulae (19:31:a*), (19:31:b*) and (19:33:a*), (19:33:b*) 
of 19.14.6. permit us now to compute the coefficients ?J, 3J. We give (as in 
19.9. in Figure 41) the graphical representations, instead of the formulae, 
leaving the elementary verification to the reader. For identification of the 

p *, <r * as good strategies only the differences, t\ 6J, y\ y\ matter: Indeed, 
the criterion at the end of 19.14. can be formulated as stating that whenever 
this 'difference is > then p = or <r| = respectively, and that whenever 





Figure 47. Figure 48. 

tg a = 2a, tg ft - 26, tg y - 2 (a - b) 

this difference is < then pj = or <rj = respectively. We give therefore 
the graphs of these differences. (Cf. Figures 47, 48. The actual propor- 
tions are those of Figures 45, 46; i.e. a/6 ~ 3, cf. there.) 

The line plots the curve y = y\ yj; the line 

plots the curve 5 = &{ b\. The irregular part of the d = $5 - d' 2 curve 
(in Figure 48) in the interval u ^ z ^ v corresponds to the similarly 
irregular part of the <r = o-J curve (in Figure 46) in the same interval, 

i.e. it also represents the multiplicity of the good strategies a '. The restric- 
tion to which that part of the o- = a\ curve is subjected (cf. the discussion 
after Figure 46) means that this part of the 6 = b\ 5J curve must lie 
within the shaded triangle ///////// (cf. Figure 48). 

19.15.3. Comparison of Figure 45 with Figure 47, and of Figure 46 
with Figure 48 shows that our strategies are indeed good, i.e. that they 
fulfill (19:H). We leave it to the reader to verify this, in analogy with the 
comparison of Figure 40 and Figure 41 in 19.9. 

1 Concerning the endpoints of these intervals, etc., cf. footnote 3 on p. 200. 



218 ZERO-SUM TWO-PERSON GAMES: EXAMPLES 

The value of K can also be obtained from (19:30*) or (19:32*) in 19.14.6. 
The result is: 



Thus player 1 has a positive expectation value for the play, i.e. an advan- 
tage 2 which is plausibly imputable to his possessing the initiative. 

19.16. Interpretation of the Solutions. Conclusions 

19.16.1. The results of 19.15. should now be discussed in the same way 
as those of 19.8., 19.9. were in 19.10. We do not wish to do this at full 
length, but just to make a few remarks on this subject. 

We see that instead of the two zones of Figure 40 three zones appear 
in Figures 45, 46. The highest one (farthest to the right) corresponds to 
"high" bids, and nothing else, in all these figures (i.e. for both players). 
The behavior of the other zones, however, is not so uniform. 

For player 2 (Figure 46) the middle zone describes that kind of " Bluff- 
ing" which we had on the lowest zone in Figure 40, irregular "high" and 
"low" bids on the same hand, But the probabilities, while not entirely 
arbitrary, are not uniquely determined as in Figure 40. 3 And there exists 
a lowest zone (in Figure 46) where player 2 must always bid "low," i.e. 
where his hand is too weak for that mixed conduct. 

Furthermore, in player 2's middle zone the 7* show the same indifference 
as in Figure 41 y\ - y{ = there, both in Figure 41 and in Figure 47 
so the motives for his conduct in this zone are as indirect as those discussed 
in the last part of 19.10. Indeed, these "high" bids are more of a defense 
against "Bluffing," than "Bluffing" proper. Since this bid of player 2 
concludes the play, there is indeed no motive for the latter, while there is a 
need to put a rein on the opponent's "Bluffing" by occasional "high" 
bids, by "Seeing" him. 

For player 1 (Figure 45) the situation is different. He must bid " high," 
and nothing else, in the lowest zone; and bid "low," and nothing else, in 
the middle zone. These "high" bids on the very weakest hands while 
the bid on the medium hands is "low" are aggressive "Bluffing" in its 

1 For numerical orientation: If a/6 = 3, which is the ratio on which all our figures are 
based, then u J, v J and K = - 

1 For a/6 ~ 3 this is about 6/9 (cf. footnote 1 above), i.e. about 11 per cent, of the 
"low "bid. 

1 Cf. the discussion after Figure 46. Indeed, it is even possible to meet those require- 

ments with o\ and 1 only; e.g. aj in the lower - fraction and a\ * 1 in the 

6 
upper - fraction of the middle interval. 

The existence of such a solution (i.e. never o\ ^ 0, 1, by Figure 45 never p[ y* 0, 1 
either) means, of course, that this variant is strictly determined. But a discussion on 
that basis (i.e. with pure strategies) will not disclose solutions like the one actually drawn 
in Figure 46. 



POKER AND BLUFFING 219 

purest form. The d* are not at all indifferent in this zone of "Bluffing" 
(i.e. the lowest zone) : t>\ 6J > there in Figure 48. i.e. any failure to 
"Bluff" under these conditions leads to instant losses. 

19.16.2. Summing up: Our new variant of Poker distinguishes two 
varieties of "Bluffing": the purely aggressive one practiced by the player 
who has the initiative; and a defensive one "Seeing" irregularly, even 
with a medium hand, the opponent who is suspected of "Bluffing" 
practiced by the player who bids last. Our original variant where the 
initiative was split between the two players because they bid simultane- 
ously contained a procedure which we can now recognize as a mixture of 
these two things. 1 

All this gives valuable heuristic hints how real Poker with longer 
sequences of (alternating) bids and overbids ought to be approached. 
The mathematical problem is difficult, but probably not beyond the reach of 
the techniques that are available. It will be considered in other publications. 

1 The variant of E. Borel, referred to in footnote 2 on p. 186, is treated loc. cit. in a 
way which bears a certain resemblance to our procedure. Using our terminology, the 
course of E. Borel can be described as follows: 

The Max-Min (Max for player 1, Min for player 2) is determined both for pure and 
for mixed strategies. The two are identical, i.e. this variant is strictly determined. 
The good strategies which are obtained in this way are rather similar to those of our 
Figure 46. Accordingly the characteristics of "Bluffing" do not appear as clearly as in 
our Figures 40 and 45. Of. the analogous considerations in the text above. 



CHAPTER V 
ZERO-SUM THREE-PERSON GAMES 

20. Preliminary Survey 
20.1. General Viewpoints 

20.1.1. The theory of the zero-sum two-person game having been 
completed, we take the next step in the sense of 12.4. : We shall establish 
the theory of the zero-sum three-person game. This will bring entirely 
new viewpoints into play. The types of games discussed thus far have 
had also their own characteristic problems. We saw that the zero-sum 
one-person game was characterized by the emergence of a maximum problem 
and the zero-sum two-person game by the clear cut opposition of interest 
which could no longer be described as a maximum problem. And just as 
the transition from the one-person to the zero-sum two-person game 
removed the pure maximum character of the problem, so the passage from 
the zero-sum two-person game to the zero-sum three-person game obliterates 
the pure opposition of interest. 

20.1.2. Indeed, it is apparent that the relationships between two players 
in a zero-sum three-person game can be manifold. In a zero-sum two- 
person game anything one player wins is necessarily lost by the other and 
vice versa, so there is always an absolute antagonism of interests. In a 
zero-sum three-person game a particular move of a player which, for the 
sake of simplicity, we assume to be clearly advantageous to him may be 
disadvantageous to both other players, but it may also be advantageous 
to one and (a fortiori) disadvantageous to the other opponent. 1 Thus some 
players may occasionally experience a parallelism of interests and it may be 
imagined that a more elaborate theory will have to decide even whether 
this parallelism is total, or partial, etc. On the other hand, opposition of 
interest must also exist in the game (it is zero-sum) and so the theory 
will have to disentangle the complicated situations which may ensue. 

It may happen, in particular, that a player has a choice among various 
policies: That he can adjust his conduct so as to get into parallelism of 
interest with another player, or the opposite; that he can choose with 
which of the other two players he wishes to establish such a parallelism, and 
(possibly) to what extent. 

1 All this, of course, is subject to all the complications and difficulties which we have 
already recognized and overcome in the zero-sum two-person game: whether a particular 
move is advantageous or disadvantageous to a certain player may not depend on that 
move alone, but also on what other players do. However, we are trying first to isolate 
the new difficulties and to analyze them in their purest form. Afterward we shall dis- 
cuss the interrelation with the old difficulties. 

220 



PRELIMINARY SURVEY 221 

20.1.3. As soon as there is a possibility of choosing with whom to 
establish parallel interests, this becomes a case of choosing an ally. When 
alliances are formed, it is to be expected that some kind of a mutual under- 
standing between the two players involved will be necessary. One can 
also state it this way: A parallelism of interests makes a cooperation 
desirable, and therefore will probably lead to an agreement between the 
players involved. An opposition of interests, on the other hand, requires 
presumably no more than that a player who has elected this alternative 
act independently in his own interest. 

Of all this there can be no vestige in the zero-sum two-person game. 
Between two players, where neither can win except (precisely) the other's 
loss, agreements or understandings are pointless. 1 This should be clear by 
common sense. If a formal corroboration (proof) be needed, one can 
find it in our ability to complete the theory of the zero-sum two-person 
game without ever mentioning agreements or understandings between 
players. 

20.2. Coalitions 

20.2.1. We have thus recognized a qualitatively different feature of the 
zero-sum three-person game (as against the zero-sum two-person game). 
Whether it is the only one is a question which can be decided only later. 
If we succeed in completing the theory of the zero-sum three-person game 
without bringing in any further new concepts, then we can claim to have 
established this uniqueness. This will be the case essentially when we reach 
23.1. For the moment we simply observe that this is a new major element 
in the situation, and we propose to discuss it fully before taking up anything 
else. 

Thus we wish to concentrate on the alternatives for acting in cooperation 
with, or in opposition to, others, among which a player can choose. I.e. we 
want to analyze the possibility of coalitions the question between which 
players, and against which player, coalitions will form. 2 

1 This is, of course, different in a general two-person game (i.e. one with variable sum) : 
there the two players may conceivably cooperate to produce a greater gain. Thus there 
is a certain similarity between the general two-person game and the zero-sum three- 
person game. 

We shall see in Chap. XI, particularly in 56.2.2., that there is a general connection 
behind this: the general n-person game is closely related to the zero-sum n + I -person 
game. 

1 The following seems worth noting: coalitions occur first in a zero-sum game when 
the number of participants in the game reaches three. In a two-person game there are 
not enough players to go around: a coalition absorbs at least two players, and then 
nobody is left to oppose. But while the three-person game of itself implies coalitions, 
the scarcity of players is still such as to circumscribe these coalitions in a definite way: a 
coalition must consist of precisely two players and be directed against precisely one (the 
remaining) player. 

If there are four or more players, then the situation becomes considerably more 
involved, several coalitions may form, and these may merge or oppose each other, etc. 
Some instances of this appear at the end of 36.1.2., et seq., the end of 37.1.2., et seq.; 
another allied phenomenon at the end of 38.3.2. 



222 ZERO-SUM THREE-PERSON GAMES 

Consequently it is desirable to form an example of a zero-sum three- 
person game in which this aspect is foremost and all others are suppressed; 
i.e., a game in which the coalitions are the only thing that matters, and the 
only conceivable aim of all players. 1 

20.2.2. At this point we may mention also the following circumstance: 
A player can at best choose between two possible coalitions, since there are 
two other players either of whom he may try to induce to cooperate with him 
against the third. We shall have to elucidate by the study of the zero-sum 
three-person game just how this choice operates, and whether any particular 
player has such a choice at all. If, however, a player has only one possi- 
bility of forming a coalition (in whatever way we shall in fine interpret this 
operation) then it is not quite clear in what sense there is a coalition at all: 
moves forced upon a player in a unique way by the necessities of the rules 
of the game are more in the nature of a (one sided) strategy than of a (cooper- 
ative) coalition. Of course these considerations are rather vague and 
uncertain at the present stage of our analysis. We bring them up neverthe- 
less, because these distinctions will turn out to be decisive. 

It may also seem uncertain, at this stage at least, how the possible 
choices of coalitions which confront one player are related to those open to 
another; indeed, whether the existence of several alternatives for one player 
implies the same for another. 

21. The Simple Majority Game of Three Persons 
21.1. Description of the Game 

21.1. We now formulate the example mentioned above: a simple zero- 
sum three-person game in which the possibilities of understandings i.e. 
coalitions between the players are the only considerations which matter. 

This is the game in question: 

Each player, by a personal move, chooses the number of one of the 
two other players. 2 Each one makes his choice uninformed about the 
choices of the two other players. 

After this the payments will be made as follows: If two players have 
chosen each other's numbers we say that they form a couple* Clearly 

1 This is methodically the same device as our consideration of Matching Pennies in 
the theory of the zero-sum two-person game. We had recognized in 14.7.1. that the 
decisive new feature of the zero-sum two-person game was the difficulty of deciding 
which player "finds out" his opponent. Matching Pennies was the game in which this 
" finding out" dominated the picture completely, where this mattered and nothing else. 

2 Player 1 chooses 2 or 3, player 2 chooses 1 or 3, player 3 chooses 1 or 2. 

* It will be seen that the formation of a couple is in the interest of the players who 
create it. Accordingly our discussion of understandings and coalitions in the paragraphs 
which follow will show that the players combine into a coalition in order to be able to 
form a couple. The difference between the concepts of a couple and a coalition neverthe- 
less should not be overlooked : A couple is a formal concept which figures in the set of rules 
of the game which we define now; a coalition is a notion belonging to the theory concern- 
ing this game (and, as will be seen, many other games). 



THE SIMPLE MAJORITY GAME 223 

there will be precisely one couple, or none at all. 1 - 2 If there is precisely one 
couple, then the two players who belong to it get one-half unit each, while 
the third (excluded) player correspondingly loses one unit. If there is no 
couple, then no one gets anything. 8 

The reader will have no difficulty in recognizing the actual social proc- 
esses for which this game is a highly schematized model. We shall call it 
the simple majority game (of three players). 

21.2. Analysis of the Game. Necessity of "Understandings" 

21.2.1. Let us try to understand the situation which exists when the 
game is played. 

To begin with, it is clear that there is absolutely nothing for a player 
to do in this game but to look for a partner, i.e. for another player who 
is prepared to form a couple with him. The game is so simple and abso- 
lutely devoid of any other strategic possibilities that there just is no occasion 
for any other reasoned procedure. Since each player makes his personal 
move in ignorance of those of the others, no collaboration of the players 
can be established during the course of the play. Two players who wish to 
collaborate must get together on this subject before the play, i.e. outside 
the game. The player who (in making his personal move) lives up to his 
agreement (by choosing the partner's number) must possess the conviction 
that the partner too will do likewise. As long as we are concerned only 
with the rules of the game, as stated above, we are in no position to judge 
what the basis for such a conviction may be. In other words what, if 
anything, enforces the "sanctity" of such agreements? There may be 
games which themselves by virtue of the rules of the game as defined in 
6.1. and 10.1. provide the mechanism for agreements and for their enforce- 
ment. 4 But we cannot base our considerations on this possibility, since a 
game need not provide this mechanism; the simple majority game described 
above certainly does not. Thus there seems to be no escape from the 
necessity of considering agreements concluded outside the game. If we do 
not allow for them, then it is hard to see what, if anything, will govern the 
conduct of a player in a simple majority game. Or, to put this in a some- 
what different form : 

1 I.e. there cannot be simultaneously two different couples. Indeed, two couples 
must have one player on common (since there are only three players), and the number 
chosen by this player must be that of the other player in both couples, i.e. the two 
couples are identical. 

2 It may happen that no couples exist: e.g., if 1 chooses 2, 2 chooses 3, and 3 chooses 1. 

3 For the sake of absolute formal correctness this should still be arranged according 
to the patterns of 6. and 7. in Chap. II. We leave this to the reader, as in the analogous 
situation discussed in footnote 1 on p. 191. 

4 By providing personal moves of one player, about which only one other player is 
informed and which contain (possibly conditional) statements of the first player's future 
policy; and by prescribing for him to adhere subsequently to these statements, or by 
providing (in the functions which determine the outcome of a game) penalties for the 
non-adherence. 



224 ZERO-SUM THREE-PERSON GAMES 

We are trying to establish a theory of the rational conduct of the partici- 
pants in a given game. In our consideration of the simple majority game 
we have reached the point beyond which it is difficult to go in formulating 
such a theory without auxiliary concepts such as " agreements/' "under- 
standings/ 1 etc. On a later occasion we propose to investigate what theo- 
retical structures are required in order to eliminate these concepts. For 
this purpose the entire theory of this book will be required as a foundation, 
and the investigation will proceed along the lines indicated in Chapter XII, 
and particularly in 66. At any rate, at present our position is too weak and 
our theory not sufficiently advanced to permit this "self-denial." We shall 
therefore, in the discussions which follow, make use of the possibility of the 
establishment of coalitions outside the game; this will include the hypothesis 
that they are respected by the contracting parties. 

21.2*2. These agreements have a certain amount of similarity with 
" conventions " in some games like Bridge with the fundamental difference, 
however, that those affected only one " organization " (i.e. one player split 
into two "persons") while we are now confronted with the relationship of 
two players. At this point the reader may reread with advantage our 
discussion of "conventions" and related topics in the last part of 6.4.2. and 
6.4.3., especially footnote 2 on p. 53. 

21.2.3. If our theory were applied as a statistical analysis of a long series 
of plays of the same game and not as the analysis of one isolated play an 
alternative interpretation would suggest itself. We should then view 
agreements and all forms of cooperation as establishing themselves by 
repetition in such a long series of plays. 

It would not be impossible to derive a mechanism of enforcement from 
the player's desire to maintain his record and to be able to rely on the record 
of his partner. However, we prefer to view our theory as applying to an 
individual play. But these considerations, nevertheless, possess a certain 
significance in a virtual sense. The situation is similar to the one which 
we encountered in the analysis of the (mixed) strategies of a zero-sum two- 
person game. The reader should apply the discussions of 17.3. mutatis 
mutandis to the present situation. 

21.3. Analysis of the Game : Coalitions. The Role of Symmetry 

21.3. Once it is conceded that agreements may exist between the players 
in the simple majority game, the path is clear. This game offers to players 
who collaborate an infallible opportunity to win and the game does not 
offer to anybody opportunities for rational action of any other kind. The 
rules are so elementary that this point ought to be fully convincing. 

Again the game is wholly symmetric with respect to the three players. 
That is true as far as the rules of the game are concerned : they do not offer 
to any player any possibility which is not equally open to any other player. 
What the players do within these possibilities is, of course, another matter. 
Their conduct may be unsymmetric; indeed, since understandings, i.e. coali- 



FURTHER EXAMPLES 225 

tions, are sure to arise, it will of necessity be unsymmetric. Among 
the three players there is room for only one coalition (of two players) and 
one player will necessarily be left out. It is quite instructive to observe how 
the rules of the game are absolutely fair (in this case, symmetric), but the 
conduct of the players will necessarily not be. 1 * 2 

Thus the only significant strategic feature of this game is the possibility 
of coalitions between two players. 8 And since the rules of the game are 
perfectly symmetrical, all three possible coalitions 4 must be considered 
on the same footing. If a coalition is formed, then the rules of the game 
provide that the two allies get one unit from the third (excluded) player 
each one getting one-half unit. 

Which of these three possible coalitions will form, is beyond the scope 
of the theory, at least at the present stage of its development. (Cf . the end 
of 4.3.2.) We can say only that it would be irrational if no coalitions were 
formed at all, but as to which particular coalition will be formed must depend 
on conditions which we have not yet attempted to analyze. 

22. Further Examples 
22.1. Unsymmetric Distribution. Necessity of Compensations 

22.1.1. The remarks of the preceding paragraphs exhaust, at least for 
the time being, the subject of the simple majority game. We must now 
begin to remove, one by one, the extremely specializing assumptions which 
characterized this game: its very special nature was essential for us in 
order to observe the role of coalitions in a pure and isolated form in vitro 

1 We saw in 17.11.2. that no such thing occurs in the zero-sum two-person games. 
There, if the rules of the game are symmetric, both players get the same amount (i.e. 
the value of the game is zero), and both have the same good strategies. I.e. there is no 
reason to expect a difference in their conduct or in the results which they ultimately 
obtain. 

It is on emergence of coalitions when more than two players are present and of 
the "squeeze" which they produce among the players, that the peculiar situation 
described above arises. (In our present case of three players the "squeeze" is due to the 
fact that each coalition can consist of only two players, i.e. less than the total number of 
players but more than one-half of it. It would be erroneous, however, to assume that no 
such "squeeze" obtains for a greater number of players.) 

* This is, of course, a very essential feature of the most familiar forms of social organi- 
zations. It is also an argument which occurs again and again in the criticism directed 
against these institutions, most of all against the hypothetical order based upon "Jowser 
faire." It is the argument that even an absolute, formal fairness symmetry of the rules 
of the game does not guarantee that the use of these rules by the participants will be 
fair and symmetrical. Indeed, this "does not guarantee" is an understatement: it is to 
be expected that any exhaustive theory of rational behavior will show that the partici- 
pants are driven to form coalitions in unsymmetric arrangements. 

To the extent to which an exact theory of these coalitions is developed, a real under- 
standing of this classical criticism is achieved. It seems worth emphasizing that this 
characteristically "social" phenomenon occurs only in the case of three or more 
participants. 

5 Such a coalition is in this game, of course, simply an agreement to choose each other's 
numbers, so as to form a couple in the sense of the rules. This situation was foreseen 
already at the beginning of 4.3.2. 

4 Between players 1,2; 1,3; 2,3. 



226 ZERO-SUM THREE-PERSON GAMES 

but now this step is completed. We must begin to adjust our ideas to 
more general situations. 

22.1.2. The specialization which we propose to remove first is this: In 
the simple majority game any coalition can get one unit from the opponent; 
the rules of the game provide that this unit must be divided evenly 
among the partners. Let us now consider a game in which each coalition 
offers the same total return, but where the rules of the game provide for a 
different distribution. For the sake of simplicity let this be the case only in 
the coalition of players 1 and 2, where player 1, say, is favored by an amount e. 
The rules of the modified game are therefore as follows: 

The moves are the same as in the simple majority game described in 
21.1. The definition of a couple is the same too. If the couple 1,2 forms, 
then player 1 gets the amount + l , player 2 gets the amount e, and 
player 3 loses one unit. If any other couple forms (i.e. 1,3 or 2,3) then 
the two players which belong to it get one-half unit each while the third 
(excluded) player loses one unit. 

What will happen in this game? 

To begin with, it is still characterized by the possibility of three coalitions 
corresponding to the three possible couples which may arise in it. 
Prima facie it may seem that player 1 has an advantage, since at least in his 
couple with player 2 he gets more by than in the original, simple majority 
game. 

However, this advantage is quite illusory. If player 1 would really 
insist on getting the extra e in the couple with player 2, then this would 
have the following consequence: The couple 1,3 would never form, because 
the couple 1,2 is more desirable from 1's point of view; the couple 1,2 would 
never form, because the couple 2,3 is more desirable from 2's point of view; 
but the couple 2,3 is entirely unobstructed, since it can be brought about 
by a coalition of 2,3 who then need pay no attention to 1 and his special 
desires. Thus the couple 2,3 and no other will form ; and player 1 will not 
get i + e nor even one-half unit, but he will certainly be the excluded player 
and lose one unit. 

So any attempt of player 1 to keep his privileged position in the couple 
1,2 is bound to lead to disaster for him. The best he can do is to take 
steps which make the couple 1,2 just as attractive for 2 as the competing 
couple 2,3. That is to say, he acts wisely if, in case of the formation of 
a couple with 2, he returns the extra to his partner. It should be noted 
that he cannot keep any fraction of e; i.e., if he should try to keep an extra 
amount e' for himself, 2 then the above arguments could be repeated literally 
with ' in place of e. 3 

1 It seems natural to assume < e < J. 

2 We mean of course <'<. 

8 So the motives for player 1's ultimate disaster the certain formation of couple 
2,3 would be weaker, but the disaster the same and just as certain as before. Cf. in 
this connection footnote 1 on p. 228. 



FURTHER EXAMPLES 227 

22.1.3. One could try some other variations of the original, simple, 
majority game, still always maintaining that the total value of each coalition 
is one unit. E.g. we could consider rules where player 1 gets the amount 
i + in each couple 1,2, 1,3; while players 2 and 3 split even in the couple 
2,3. In this case neither 2 nor 3 would care to cooperate with 1 if 1 should 
try to keep his extra or any fraction thereof. Hence any such attempt 
of player 1 would again lead with certainty to a coalition of 2,3 against him 
and to a loss of one unit. 

Another possibility would be that two players are favored in all couples 
with the third: e.g. in the couples 1,3 and 2,3, players 1 and 2 respectively 
get i + while 3 gets only i ; and in the couple 1,2 both get one-half 
unit each. In this case both players 1 and 2 would lose interest in a coalition 
with each other, and player 3 will become the desirable partner for each of 
them. One must expect that this will lead to a competitive bidding for his 
cooperation. This must ultimately lead to a refund to player 3 of the extra 
advantage e. Only this will bring the couple 1,2 back into the field of 
competition and thereby restore equilibrium. 

22.1.4. We leave to the reader the consideration of further variants, 
where all three players fare differently in all three couples. Furthermore 
we shall not push the above analysis further, although this could be done 
and would even be desirable in order to answer some plausible objections. 
We are satisfied with having established some kind of a general plausibility 
for our present approach which can be summarized as follows: It seems 
that what a player can get in a definite coalition depends not only on what 
the rules of the game provide for that eventuality, but also on the other 
(competing) possibilities of coalitions for himself and for his partner. Since 
the rules of the game are absolute and inviolable, this means that under 
certain conditions compensations must be paid among coalition partners; 
i.e. that a player must have to pay a well-defined price to a prospective 
coalition partner. The amount of the compensations will depend on what 
other alternatives are open to each of the players. 

Our examples above have served as a first illustration for these principles. 
This being understood, we shall now take up the subject de novo and in 
more generality, and handle it in a more precise manner. l 

22.2. Coalitions of Different Strength. Discussion 

22.2.1. In accordance with the above we now take a far reaching step 
towards generality. We consider a game in which this is the case: 

If players 1,2 cooperate, then they can get the amount c, and no more, 
from player 3; if players 1,3 cooperate, they can get the amount 6, and no 
more, from player 2; if players 2,3 cooperate, they can get the amount a, and 
no more, from player 1. 

1 This is why we need not analyze any further the heuristic arguments of this para- 
graph the discussion of the next paragraphs takes care of everything. 

All these possibilities were anticipated at the beginning of 4.3.2. and in 4.3.3. 



228 ZERO-SUM THREE-PERSON GAMES 

We make no assumptions whatsoever concerning further particulars 
about the rules of this game. So we need not describe by what steps of 
what order of complication the above amounts are secured. Nor do we 
state how these amounts are divided between the partners, whether and how 
either partner can influence or modify this distribution, etc. 

We shall nevertheless be able to discuss this game completely. But 
it will be necessary to remember that a coalition is probably connected 
with compensations passing between the partners. The argument is as 
follows: 

22.2.2. Consider the situation of player 1. He can enter two alternative 
coalitions: with player 2 or with player 3. Assume that he attempts to 
retain an amount x under all conditions. In this case player 2 cannot 
count upon obtaining more than the amount c x in a coalition with 
player 1. Similarly player 3 cannot count on getting more than the 
amount 6 x in a coalition with player 1. Now if the sum of these upper 
bounds i.e. the amount (c x) + (b x) is less than what players 2 
and 3 can get by combining with each other in a coalition, then we may 
safely assume that player 1 will find no partner. 1 A coalition of 2 and 3 
can obtain the amount a. So we see: If player 1 desires to get an amount x 
under all conditions, then he is disqualified from any possibility of finding 
a partner if his x fulfills 

(c - x) + (b - x) < a. 
I.e. the desire to get x is unrealistic and absurd unless 

(c - x) + (b - x) ^ a. 
This inequality may be written equivalently as 

. -a + b + c 
** 2 

We restate this : 

(22:l:a) Player 1 cannot reasonably maintain a claim to get under 
all conditions more than the amount a = ~ 

2i 

The same considerations may be repeated for players 2 and 3, and they 
give: 

(22:l:b) Player 2 cannot reasonably maintain a claim to get under 
all conditions more than the amount ft = ^ 

i 

(22:l:c) Player 3 cannot reasonably maintain a claim to get under 

all conditions more than the amount 7 = 5 

& 

1 We assume, of course, that a player is not indifferent to any possible profit, however 
small. This was implicit in our discussion of the zero-sum two-person game as well. 

The traditional idea of the "homo oeconomicus," to the extent to which it is clearly 
conceived at all, also contains this assumption. 



FURTHER EXAMPLES 229 

22.2.3. Now the criteria (22:l:a)-(22:l:c) were only necessary ones, and 
one could imagine a priori that further considerations could further lower 
their upper bounds, a, 0, y or lead to some other restrictions of what 
the players can aim for. This is not so, as the following simple con- 
sideration shows. 

One verifies immediately that 

a + = c, a + 7 = 6, + 7 = <* 

In other words: If the players 1,2,3 do not aim at more than permitted by 
(22:1 :a), (22:1 :b), (22:1 :c), i.e. than a, 0, y respectively, then any two 
players who combine can actually obtain these amounts in a coalition. 
Thus these claims are fully justified. Of course only two players the two 
who form a coalition can actually obtain their "justified" dues. The 
third player, who is excluded from the coalition, will not get a, ft, y respec- 
tively, but a, 6, c instead. 1 

22.3. An Inequality. Formulae 

22.3.1. At this point an obvious question presents itself: Any player 
1,2,3 can get the amount a, 0, y respectively if he succeeds in entering a 
coalition; if he does not succeed, he gets instead only a, b, c. This 
makes sense only if a, 0, y are greater than the corresponding a, 6, c, 
since otherwise a player might not want to enter a coalition at all, but 
might find it more advantageous to play for himself. So the question is 
whether the three differences 

p a _ (__ a ) = a + a, 
g = 0- (-&) =0 + 6, 
r = y ~ (-<0 = y + c, 
are all ^ 0. 

It is immediately seen that they are all equal to each other. Indeed : 

a + b + c 
P = 9 = r = -- ^ -- 

We denote this quantity by A/2. Then our question is whether 



This inequality can be demonstrated as follows : 

22.3.2. A coalition of the players 1,2 can obtain (from player 3) the 
amount c and no more. If player 1 plays alone, then he can prevent players 
2,3 from reducing him to a result worse than a since even a coalition of 
players 2,3 can obtain (from player 1) the amount +a and no more; i.e. 
player 1 can get the amount a for himself without any outside help. 
Similarly, player 2 can get the amount 6 for himself without any outside 
help. Consequently the two players 1,2 between them can get the amount 

1 These are indeed the amounts which a coalition of the other players can wrest from 
players 1,2,3 respectively. The coalition cannot take more. 



230 



ZERO-SUM THREE-PERSON GAMES 



(a -f 6) even if they fail to cooperate with each other. Since the maxi- 
mum they can obtain together under any conditions is c, this implies 
c ^ -a - b i.e. A = a + 6 + c0. 

22.3.3. This proof suggests the following remarks: 

First: We have based our argument on player 1. Owing to the sym- 
metry of the result A=a+6+c^O with respect to the three players, 
the same inequality would have obtained if we had analyzed the situation 
of player 2 or player 3. This indicates that there exists a certain symmetry 
in the role of the three players. 

Second: A = means c = a 6 or just as well a = a, and the two 
corresponding pairs of equations which obtain by the cyclic permutation 
of the three players. So in this case no coalition has a raison d'&tre: Any 
two players can obtain, without cooperating, the same amount which they 
can produce in perfect cooperation (e.g. for players 1 and 2 this amount is 
a b = c). Also, after all is said and done, each player who succeeds 
in joining a coalition gets no more than he could get for himself without 
outside help (e.g. for player 1 this amount is a = a). 

If, on the other hand, A > then every player has a definite interest in 
joining a coalition. The advantage contained in this is the same for all 
three players: A/2. 

Here we have again an indication of the symmetry of certain aspects 
of the situation for all players: A/2 is the inducement to seek a coalition; it 
is the same for all players. 

22.3.4. Our result can be expressed by the following table: 



Player 


i 


2 


3 


Value of a play 


With coalition 


a 


ft 


7 


Without coalition 


a 


-b 


c 



Figure 49. 



If we put 



., L, 1 A a 1 A a-26 + c 
6' = -6 + -A = /J- g A g , 

/ . 1 A 1 A a + b - 2c 
c'=-c + A = T-gA = g , 

then we have 

a' + V + c' = 0, 

and we can express the above table equivalently in the following manner: 

(22 :A) A play has for the players 1,2,3 the basic values a', 6', c' respec- 

tively. (This is a possible valuation, since the sum of these 



THE GENERAL CASE 231 

values is zero, cf. above). The play will, however, certainly be 
attended by the formation of a coalition. Those two players 
who form it get (beyond their basic values) a premium of A/6 and 
the excluded player sustains a loss of A/3. 

Thus the inducement to form a coalition is A/2 for each 
player, and always A/2 ^ 0. 

23. The General Case 
23.1. Exhaustive Discussion. Inessential and Essential Games 

23.1.1. We can now remove all restrictions. 

Let T be a perfectly arbitrary zero-sum three-person game. A simple 
consideration suffices to bring it within the reach of the analysis of 22.2., 
22.3. We argue as follows: 

If two players, say 1 and 2, decide to cooperate completely postponing 
temporarily, for a later settlement, the question of distribution, i.e. of the 
compensations to be paid between partners then F becomes a zero-sum 
two-person game. The two players in this new game are: the coalition 1,2 
(which is now a composite player consisting of two "natural persons "), 
and the player 3. Viewed in this manner T falls under the theory of the 
zero-sum two-person game of Chapter III. Each play of this game has a 
well defined value (we mean the v' defined in 17.4.2.). Let us denote by c 
the value of a play for the coalition 1,2 (which in our present interpretation 
is one of the players). 

Similarly we can assume an absolute coalition between players 1,3 and 
view T as a zero-sum two-person game between this coalition and the player 
2. We then denote by b the value of a play for the coalition 1,3. 

Finally we can assume an absolute coalition between players 2,3, and 
view F as a zero-sum two-person game between this coalition and the 
player 1. We then denote by a the value of a play for the coalition 2,3. 

It ought to be understood that we do not yet! assume that any such 
coalition will necessarily arise. The quantities a, 6, c are merely computa- 
tionally defined; we have formed them on the basis of the main (mathe- 
matical) theorem of 17.6. (For explicit expressions of a, 6, c cf. below.) 

23.1.2. Now it is clear that the zero-sum three-person game F falls 
entirely within the domain of validity of 22.2., 22.3.: a coalition of the 
players 1,2 or 1,3 or 2,3 can obtain (from the excluded players 3 or 2 or 1) 
the amounts c, 6, a respectively, and no more. Consequently all results of 
22.2., 22.3. hold, in particular the one formulated at the end which describes 
every player's situation with and without a coalition. 

23.1.3. These results show that the zero-sum three-person game falls 
into two quantitatively different categories, corresponding to the possi- 
bilities A = and A > 0. Indeed: 

A = 0: We have seen that in this case coalitions have no raison d'etre, 
and each player can get the same amount for himself, by playing a "lone 
hand" against all others, as he could obtain by any coalition. In this case, 



232 ZERO-SUM THREE-PERSON GAMES 

and in this case alone, it is possible to assume a unique value of each play 
for each player, the sum of these values being zero. These are the basic 
values a', &', c' mentioned at the end of 22.3. In this case the formulae of 
22.3. show that a! = a = -a, V = ft = -b, c 1 = y = -c. We shall 
call a game in this case, in which it is inessential to consider coalitions, an 
inessential game. 

A > 0: In this case there is a definite inducement to form coalitions, as 
discussed at the end of 22.3. There is no need to repeat the description 
given there; we only mention that now a > a' > a, ft > b' > 6, 
7 > c' > c. We shall call a game in this case, in which coalitions are 
essential, an essential game. 

Our above classification, inessential and essential, applies at present 
only to zero-sum three-person games. But we shall see subsequently that it 
can be extended to all games and that it is a differentiation of central 
importance. 

23.2. Complete Formulae 

23.2. Before we analyze this result any further, let us make a few purely 
mathematical remarks about the quantities a, 6, c and the a, 0, 7, a', 6', c', 
A based upon them in terms of which our solution was expressed. 

Assume the zero-sum three-person game F in the normalized form of 
11.2.3. There the players 1,2,3 choose the variables TI, r 2 , r 3 respectively 
(each one uninformed about the two other choices) and get the amounts 
3Ci(ri, T 2 , r 3 ), 3C2(ri, T 2 , r 3 ), 3C 3 (n, T 2 , T 3 ) respectively. Of course (the game is 
zero-sum) : 

3Ci(n, T2 , T 8 ) + JC 2 (ri, T 2 , T 3 ) + 3C 3 (n, r 2 , r 3 ) s 0. 
The domains of the variables are: 

T! = 1, 2, - - - , 0,, 

T, = 1, 2, , 02, 
T 3 = 1, 2, , 3 . 

Now in the two-person game which arises between an absolute coalition of 
players 1,2, and the player 3, we have the following situation: 

The composite player 1,2 has the variables n, r 2 ; the other player 3 
has the variable r 8 . The former gets the amount 

3Cl(Tl, T2 , T 3 ) +3C 2 (n, T 2 , T 3 ) 3 -3Cs(Ti, T 2 , T 3 ), 

the latter the negative of this amount. 

A mixed strategy of the composite player 1,2 is a vector of S^, the 

components of which we may denote by { fiiT| . 1 Thus the of S fti p t are 
characterized by 

* V r, 0, 2 *v, = 1- 

*!/* 

1 The number of pairs n, TJ is, of course, 0ifa. 



DISCUSSION OF AN OBJECTION 233 

A mixed strategy of the player 3 is a vector 17 of Sp the components of 
which we denote by j v The i\ of Sf t are characterized by 

Hr, 0, *, = 1. 

*\ 

The bilinear form K( , r? ) of (17:2) in 17.4.1. is therefore 

K( , 1? ) = 2) iJCi(n, T 2 , T 3 ) + JC(n, T 2 , T,) | TI r^ 



and finally 

> . > 

c = Max-* Min-> K( , 77 ) = Min- Max-* K( , rj ). 

f n n { 

The expressions for 6, a obtain from this by cyclical permutations of the 
players 1,2,3 in all details of this representation. 

We repeat the formulae expressing a, /3, 7, a', 6', c f and A: 

A = a + b + c necessarily ^ 0, 

-a + b + c , -2a + b + c 



_ a + 6 c , a + 6 2c 

and we have 



A ^ 0, 

a' + b' + c' = 0, 



,'+, 



24. Discussion of an Objection 
24.1. The Case of Perfect Information and Its Significance 

24.1.1. We have obtained a solution for the zero-sum three-person game 
which accounts for all possibilities and which indicates the direction that the 
search for the solutions of the n-person game must take: the analysis of all 
possible coalitions, and the competitive relationship which they bear to 
each other, which should determine the compensations that players who 
want to form a coalition will pay to each other. 

We have noticed already that this will be a much more difficult problem 
forn ^ 4 players than it was for n = 3 (cf. footnote 2, p. 221). 



234 ZERO-SUM THREE-PERSON GAMES 

Before we attack this question, it is well to pause for a moment to 
reconsider our position. In the discussions which follow we shall put the 
main stress on the formation of coalitions and the compensations between 
the participants in those coalitions, using the theory of the zero-sum two- 
person game to determine the values of the ultimate coalitions which oppose 
each other after all players have "taken sides" (cf. 25.1.1., 25.2.). But is 
this aspect of the matter really as universal as we propose to claim? 

We have adduced already some strong positive arguments for it, in our 
discussion of the zero-sum three-person game. Our ability to build the 
theory of the n-person game (for all ri) on this foundation will, in fine, be 
the decisive positive argument. But there is a negative argument an 
objection to be considered, which arises in connection with those games 
where perfect information prevails. 

The objection which we shall now discuss applies only to the above 
mentioned special category of games. Thus it would not, if found valid, 
provide us with an alternative theory that applies to all games. But since 
we claim a general validity for our proposed stand, we must invalidate all 
objections, even those which apply only to some special case. 1 

24.1.2. Games with perfect information have already been discussed in 
15. We saw there that they have important peculiarities and that their 
nature can be understood fully only when they are considered in the extensive 
form and not merely in the normalized one on which our discussion chiefly 
relied (cf. also 14.8.). 

The analysis of 15. began by considering n-person games (for all n), 
but in its later parts we had to narrow it to the zero-sum two-person game. 
At the end, in particular, we found a verbal method of discussing it (cf. 15.8.) 
which had some remarkable features: First, while not entirely free from 
objections, it seemed worth considering. Second, the argumentation used 
was rather different from that by which we had resolved the general case of 
the zero-sum two-person game and while applicable only to this special 
case, it was more straight forward than the other argumentation. Third, 
it led for the zero-sum two-person games with perfect information to 
the same result as our general theory. 

Now one might be tempted to use this argumentation for n ^ 3 players 
too; indeed a superficial inspection of the pertinent paragraph 15.8.2. does 
not immediately disclose any reason why it should be restricted (as there) to 
n = 2 players (cf., however, 15.8.3.). But this procedure makes no men- 
tion of coalitions or understandings between players, etc.; so if it is usable 
for n = 3 players, then our present approach is open to grave doubts. 2 We 

1 In other words : in claiming general validity for a theory one necessarily assumes the 
burden of proof against all objectors. 

2 One might hope to evade this issue, by expecting to find A = for all zero-sum three- 
person games with perfect information. This would make coalitions unnecessary. Cf. 
the end of 23.1. 

Just as games with perfect information avoided the difficulties of the theory of zero- 
sum two-person games by being strictly determined (cf. 15.6.1.), they would now avoid 
those of the zero-Bum three-person gamee by being inessential. 



DISCUSSION OF AN OBJECTION 235 

propose to show therefore why the procedure of 15.8. is inconclusive when 
the number of players is three or more. 

To do this, let us repeat some characteristic steps of the argumentation 
in question (cf. 15.8.2., the notations of which we are also using). 

24.2. Detailed Discussion. Necessity of Compensations between Three or More Players 

24.2.1. Consider accordingly a game F in which perfect information 
prevails. Let SfTCi, 3fE 2 , , 9(11, be its moves, <TI, (7 2 , , <r, the choices 
connected with these moves, T(<TI, , 0-,) the play characterized by 
these choices, and 3v(7r(oi, , <r,)) the outcome of this play for the player 
j(= 1, 2, - - ,n). 

Assume that the moves 3TCi, 3Tl2, , 3TC,-i have already been made, 
the outcome of their choices being <TI, <r 2 , * , cr,_i and consider the last 
move 3TC, and its <r,. If this is a chance move i.e. ft, (en, , <r,~\) = 0, 
then the various possible values a, = 1,2, , a,(cri, , a,-i) have the 
probabilities p ( 1 ), p v (2), , p,(a,(o-i, , cr,_i)), respectively. If this 
is a personal move of player A: i.e. fc,(ai, ,<r,-i) = k = 1,2, , n, 
then player k will choose a f so as to make SFjb(ir(ori, , 0v- A| tr,)) a maxi- 
mum. Denote this <r, by <r,(<n, , *,_i). Thus one can argue that the 
value of the play is already known (for each player j = 1, n) after 
the moves Sflfcj, 3Tl2, * * * , 2(TC,-i (and before 9ftl,!), i.e. as a function of 
0*1, 0% , <r,-i alone. Indeed: by the above it is 



*-! 

for fc,(<7i, * , <r,_i) = 0, 

where <r, = <r,(<n, , <r,-i) maximizes 
S^Or^i, , <r,-i, <r,)) for 

Consequently we can treat the game T as if it consisted of the moves 
9Tli, 9fn 2 , , 3Tl,_i only (without 3TC,). 

By this device we have removed the last move 9TC,. Repeating it, we 
can similarly remove successively the moves 3fTC,_i, 9fH,_a, , 9H a , 9Tli and 
finally obtain a definite value of the play (for each player j = 1, 2, n). 

24.2.2. For a critical appraisal of this procedure consider the last two 
steps 9Tl,_i, 9fll, and assume that they are personal moves of two different 

This, however, is not the case. To see that, it suffices to modify the rules of the 
simple majority game (cf. 21.1.) as follows: Let the players 1,2,3 make their personal 
moves (i.e. the choices of n, TJ, r* respectively, cf. loc. cit.) in this order, each one being 
informed about the anterior moves. It is easy to verify that the values c, 6, a of tho 
three coalitions 1,2, 1,3, 2,3 are the same as before 

c-6-a-l, A-a+6+c-3>0. 

A detailed discussion of this game, with particular respect to the considerations of 
21.2., would be of a certain interest, but we do not propose to continue this subject 
further at present. 



236 ZERO-SUM THREE-PERSON GAMES 

players, say 1,2 respectively. In this situation we have assumed that 
player 2 will certainly choose cr, so as to maximize $2(0-1, , o-,_i, <r y ). 
This gives a a> = 0-,(<ri, , <r,_i). Now we have also assumed that 
player 1, in choosing <r,_i can rely on this; i.e. that he may safely replace the 
$I(<TI, , ov-i, 0-,), (which is what he will really obtain), by 
$1(0-1, , (r r _i, OV(<TI, , cr,_i)) and maximize this latter quantity. 1 
But can he rely on this assumption? 

To begin with, <r y (cri, , <r,,_i) may not even be uniquely determined: 
$2(^1, , cr,_i, (T,) may assume its maximum (for given <TI, , o>_i) 
at several places ov In the zero-sum two-person game this was irrelevant: 
there $1 = #2, hence two o> which give the same value to $F 2 , also give the 
same value to 9Fi. 2 But even in the zero-sum three-person game, $2 does not 
determine $1, due to the existence of the third player and his $3! So it 
happens here for the first time that a difference which is unimportant for 
one player may be significant for another player. This was impossible in 
the zero-sum two-person game, where each player won (precisely) what the 
other lost. 

What then must player 1 expect if two v v are of the same importance for 
player 2, but not for player 1 ? One must expect that he will try to induce 
player 2 to choose the a, which is more favorable to him. He could offer 
to pay to player 2 any amount up to the difference this makes for him. 

This being conceded, one must envisage that player 1 may even try to 
induce player 2 to choose a a v which does not maximize S^i, * ' * , ov-i, ov). 
As long as this change causes player 2 less of a loss than it causes player 1 
a gain, 3 player 1 can compensate player 2 for his loss, and possibly even 
give up to him some part of his profit. 

24.2.3. But if player 1 can offer this to player 2, then he must also count 
on similar offers coming from player 3 to player 2. I.e. there is no certainty 
at all that player 2 will, by his choice of o-,, maximize 2(0-1, , <r,_i, cr v ). 
In comparing two a v one must consider whether player 2 J s loss is over- 
compensated by player Ts or player 3's gain, since this could lead to under- 
standings and compensations. I.e. one must analyze whether a coalition 1,2 
or 2,3 would gain by any modification of a v . 

24.2.4. This brings the coalitions back into the picture. A closer analysis 
would lead us to the considerations and results of 22.2., 22.3., 23. in every 
detail. But it does not seem necessary to carry this out here in complete 
detail: after all, this is just a special case, and the discussion of 22.2., 22.3., 
23. was of absolutely general validity (for the zero-sum three-person game) 

1 Since this is a function of <TI, , a>_ 2 , <r,_i only, of which <TI, , o>_2 are known 
at 9Rr-iy and <r,,_i is controlled by player 1, he is able to maximize it. 

He cannot in any sense maximize $1(0-1, , 0>-i, o v ) since that also depends on <r, 
which he neither knows nor controls. 

2 Indeed, we refrained in 15.8.2. from mentioning $ 2 at all: instead of maximizing $ 2 , 
we talked of minimizing $1. There was no need even to introduce 9 (a\ t , r-i) 
and everything was described by Max and Min operations on JFi. 

3 I.e. when it happens at the expense of player 3. 



DISCUSSION OF AN OBJECTION 237 

provided that the consideration of understandings and compensations, i.e. of 
coalitions, is permitted. 

We wanted to show that the weakness of the argument of 15.8.2., already 
recognized in 15.8.3., becomes destructive exactly when we go beyond the 
zero-sum two-person games, and that it leads precisely to the mechanism of 
coalitions etc. foreseen in the earlier paragraphs of this chapter. This 
should be clear from the above analysis, and so we can return to our original 
method in dealing with zero-sum three-person games, i.e. claim full validity 
for the results of 22.2., 22.3., 23. 



CHAPTER VI 

FORMULATION OF THE GENERAL THEORY: 
ZERO-SUM n-PERSON GAMES 

25. The Characteristic Function 
25.1. Motivation and Definition 

25.1.1. We now turn to the zero-sum n-person game for general n. The 
experience gained in Chapter V concerning the case n = 3 suggests that 
the possibilities of coalitions between players will play a decisive role in the 
general theory which we are developing. It is therefore important to 
evolve a mathematical tool which expresses these " possibilities" in a 
quantitative way. 

Since we have an exact concept of " value" (of a play) for the zero-sum 
two-person game, we can also attribute a " value" to any given group of 
players, provided that it is opposed by the coalition of all the other players. 
We shall give these rather heuristic indications an exact meaning in what 
follows. The important thing is, at any rate, that we shall thus reach a 
mathematical concept on which one can try to base a general theory and 
that the attempt will, in fine, prove successful. 

Let us now state the exact mathematical definitions which carry out this 
program. 

25.1.2. Suppose then that we have a game F of n players who, for the 
sake of brevity, will be denoted by 1, 2, , n. It is convenient to 
introduce the set / = (1, 2, , n) of all these players. Without yet 
making any predictions or assumptions about the course a play of this game 
is likely to take, we observe this: if we group the players into two parties, 
and treat each party as an absolute coalition i.e. if we assume full coopera- 
tion within each party then a zero-sum two-person game results. 1 Pre- 
cisely: Let S be any given subset of 7, S its complement in /. We 
consider the zero-sum two-person game which results when all players k 
belonging to S cooperate with each other on the one hand, and all players k 
belonging to S cooperate with each other on the other hand. 

Viewed in this manner F falls under the theory of the zero-sum two- 
person game of Chapter III. Each play of this game has a well defined 
value (we mean the v' defined in 17.8.1.). Let us denote by v(S) the value 
of a play for the coalition of all k belonging to S (which, in our present inter- 
pretation, is one of the players). 

1 This is exactly what we did in the case n = 3 in 23.1.1. The general possibility was 
already alluded to at the beginning of 24.1. 

238 



THE CHARACTERISTIC FUNCTION 239 

Mathematical expressions for v(S) obtain as follows: 1 
25.1.3. Assume the zero-sum n-person game F in the normalized form of 
11.2.3. There each player k = 1, 2, , n chooses a variable r* (each one 
uninformed about the n 1 other choices) and gets the amount 

3C*(Tl, T 2 , , T n ). 

Of course (the game is zero-sum) : 

(25:1) 3e*(n, , r n ) m 0. 

*-i 

The domains of the variables are: 

T* = 1, , j8* for k = 1, 2, - , n. 

Now in the two-person game which arises between an absolute coalition of all 
players k belonging to S (player 1') and that one of all players k belonging 
to S (player 2'), we have the following situation: 

The composite player 1' has the aggregate of variables T* where k runs 
over all elements of S. It is necessary to treat this aggregate as one variable 
and we shall therefore designate it by one symbol r a . The composite 
player 2' has the aggregate of variables r k where k runs over all elements 
of S. This aggregate too is one variable, which we designate by the 
symbol r~ a . The player 1' gets the amount 



(25:2) 5c(rV- s ) = OC*(n, - , r n ) = - 3C(n, - , r n );' 

kinS km -S 

the player 2' gets the negative of this amount. 

A mixed strategy of the player I/ is a vector of <S0, 8 the components 

of which we denote by r . Thus the of S0a are characterized by 

t- ^ o, 2) s* a = L 

T 

A mixed strategy of the player 2' is a vector rj of /V, 4 the components 


of which we denote by rj T -a. Thus the ij of Sp-a are characterized by 

rj r -8 ^0, 5J rj T -a = 1. 

r~ 

1 This is a repetition of the construction of 23.2., which applied only to the special 
case n 3. 

1 The T S , r~ 5 of the first expression form together the aggregate of the n, , r n of 
the two other expressions; so T S , r~ 3 determine those n, , r n . 

The equality of the two last expressions is, of course, only a restatement of the 
zero -sum property. 

8 ft 3 is the number of possible aggregates T S , i.e. the product of all 0* where k runs over 
all elements of S. 

4 0~ s is the number of possible aggregates r" 5 , i.e. the product of all 0* where k runs 
over all elements of <S. 



240 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 

> > 

The bilinear form K( , t? ) of (17:2) in 17.4.1. is therefore 
K(7,7) - #(rV-*)r'*-', 

rV s 

and finally 



v(S) = Max- Min- K(, ) = Min- Max-^ K(, ). 

25.2. Discussion of the Concept 

25.2.1. The above function v(S) is defined for all subsets 8 of I and has 
real numbers as values. Thus it is, in the sense of 13.1.3., a numerical 
set function. We call it the characteristic function of the game T. As we 
have repeatedly indicated, we expect to base the entire theory of the 
zero-sum n-person game on this function. 

It is well to visualize what this claim involves. We propose to determine 
everything that can be said about coalitions between players, compensa- 
tions between partners in every coalition, mergers or fights between coali- 
tions, etc., in terms of the characteristic function v(*S) alone. Prima facie, 
this program may seem unreasonable, particularly in view of these two facts: 

(a) An altogether fictitious two-person game, which is related to the 
real n-person game only by a theoretical construction, was used to define 
v(S). Thus v(S) is based on a hypothetical situation, and not strictly 
on the n-person game itself. 

(b) v(S) describes what a given coalition of players (specifically, 
the set S) can obtain from their opponents (the set AS) but it fails to 
describe how the proceeds of the enterprise are to be divided among the 
partners k belonging to S. This division, the "imputation," is indeed 
directly determined by the individual functions 3C*(Ti, , r n ), k belong- 
ing to S, while v(S) depends on much less. Indeed, v(S) is determined by 
their partial sum JC(r 5 , r~ 5 ) alone, and even by less than that since it is 

the saddle value of the bilinear form K( , y ) based on 5C(r 5 , r~" s ) (cf. the 
formulae of 25.1.3.). 

25.2.2. In spite of these considerations we expect to find that the 
characteristic function v(S) determines everything, including the "impu- 
tation" (cf. (b) above). The analysis of the zero-sum three-person game in 
Chapter V indicates that the direct distribution (i.e., "imputation") 
by means of the 3G*(ri, , r n ) is necessarily offset by some system of 
"compensations" which the players must make to each other before coali- 
tions can be formed. The "compensations" should be determined essen- 
tially by the possibilities which exist for each partner in the coalition S 
(i.e. for each k belonging to *S), to forsake it and to join some other coalition 
T. (One may have to consider also the influence of possible simultaneous 
and concerted desertions by sets of several partners in S etc.) I.e. the 
"imputation" of v(/S) to the players k belonging to S should be determined 



THE CHARACTERISTIC FUNCTION 241 

by the other v(T) 1 and not by the 3C*(ri, , r n ). We have demon- 
strated this for the zero-sum three-person game in Chapter V. One of the 
main objectives of the theory we are trying to build up is to establish the 
same thing for the general n-person game. 

26.3. Fundamental Properties 

25.3.1. Before we undertake to elucidate the importance of the char- 
acteristic function v(S) for the general theory of games, we shall investigate 
this function as a mathematical entity in itself. We know that it is a 
numerical set function, defined for all subsets S of / = (1, 2, - , n) 
and we now propose to determine its essential properties. 

It will turn out that they are the following: 

(25:3:a) v(0) = 0, 

(25:3:b) v(-S) = -v(S), 

(25:3:c) v(S u T) ^ v(S) + v(T), if S n T = 0. 

We prove first that the characteristic set function v(>S) of every game 
fulfills (25:3:a)-(25:3:c). 

25.3.2. The simplest proof is a conceptual one, which can be carried out 
with practically no mathematical formulae. However, since we gave 
exact mathematical expressions for v(S) in 25.1.3., one might desire a 
strictly mathematical, formalistic proof in terms of the operations Max 
and Min and the appropriate vectorial variables. We emphasize therefore 
that our conceptual proof is strictly equivalent to the desired formalistic, 
mathematical one, and that the translation can be carried out without 
any real difficulty. But since the conceptual proof makes the essential 
ideas clearer, and in a briefer and simpler way, while the formalistic proof 
would involve a certain amount of cumbersome notations, we prefer to 
give the former. The reader who is interested may find it a good exercise 
to construct the formalistic proof by translating our conceptual one. 

25.3.3. Proof of (25:3:a) : 2 The coalition has no members, so it always 
gets the amount zero, therefore v(0) = 0. 

Proof of (25:3:b): v(*S) and v(-S) originate from the same (fictitious) 
zero-sum two-person game, the one played by the coalition S against 

1 All this is very much in the sense of the remarks in 4.3.3. on the role of " virtual" 
existence. 

1 Observe that we are treating even the empty set as a coalition. The reader should 
think this over carefully. In spite of its strange appearance, the step is harmless and 
quite in the spirit of general set theory. Indeed, it would be technically quite a nuisance 
to exclude the empty set from consideration. 

Of course this empty coalition has no moves, no variables, no influence, no gains, 
and no losses. But this is immaterial. 

The complementary set of , the set of all players 7, will also be treated as a possible 
coalition. This too is the convenient procedure from the set-theoretical point of view. 
To a lesser extent this coalition also may appear to be strange, since it has no opponents. 
Although it has an abundance of members and hence of moves and variables it will 
(in a zero-sum game) equally have nothing to influence, and no gains or losses. But this 
too is immaterial. 



242 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 

the coalition S. The value of a play of this game for its two composite 
players is indeed v(S) and v( S) respectively. Therefore v( S) = v(S). 
Proof of (25:3:c): The coalition S can obtain from its opponents (by 
using an appropriate mixed strategy) the amount v(S) and no more. The 
coalition T can obtain similarly the amount v(7 7 ) and no more. Hence the 
coalition S u T can obtain from its opponents the amount v(S) + v(T), 
even if the subcoalitions S and T fail to cooperate with each other. 1 Since 
the maximum which the coalition S u T can obtain under any condition is 
v(S u T) this implies v(S u T) ^ v(S) + v(2T). 2 

25.4. Immediate Mathematical Consequences 

25.4.1. Before we go further let us draw some conclusions from the above 
(25:3:a)-(25:3:c). These will be derived in the sense that they hold for 
any numerical set function v(S) which fulfills (25:3:a)-(25:3:c) irrespective 
of whether or not it is the characteristic function of a zero-sum n-person 
game F. 

(25:4) v(7) = 0. 

Proof:* By (25:3:a), (25:3:b), v(7) = v(-0) = -v(0) = 0. 
(25:5) v(5i u u S p ) v(5i) + - + v(S 9 ) 

if Si, , S p are pairwise disjunct subsets of 7. 

Proof: Immediately by repeated application of (25:3:c). 
(25:6) v(Si) + + v(S,) g 

if Si, , S p are a decomposition of 7, i.e. pairwise disjunct 
subsets of 7 with the sum 7. 

Proof: We have Si u u S p = 7, hence v(Si u - - - u S p ) = by 
(25:4). Therefore (25:6) follows from (25:5). 

25.4.2. While (25 :4)-(25 :6) are consequences of (25 :3 :a)-(25 : 3 : c) , they 
and even somewhat less can replace (25:3:a)-(25:3:c) equivalently. 
Precisely: 

(25 :A) The conditions (25:3:a)-(25:3:c) are equivalent to the asser- 

tion of (25:6) for the values p = 1, 2, 3 only; but (25:6) must 
then be stated for p = 1, 2 with an = sign, and for p = 3 with 
a sign. 

1 Observe that we are now using S n T 0. If S and T had common elements, we 
could not break up the coalition S U T into the subcoalitions S and T. 

1 This proof is very nearly a repetition of the proof of a + b 4- c ^ in 22.3.2. One 
could even deduce our (25:3:c) from that relation: Consider the decomposition of / into 
the three disjunct subsets S, T, (S U T). Treat the three corresponding (hypothetical) 
absolute coalitions as the three players of the zero-sum three-person game into which this 
transforms T. Then v(), v(T), v(S U T) correspond to the -a, -b, c loc. cit.; hence 
a + b + c means -v(S) - v(T) 4- v(S U T) 0; i.e. v(S U T) v(/S) + v(T). 

For a v(S) originating from a game, both (25:3:a) and (25:4) are conceptually 
contained in the remark of footnote 2 on p. 241. 



GIVEN CHARACTERISTIC FUNCTION 243 

Proof: (25:6) for p = 2 with an = sign states v(S) + v(~S) = 
(we write S for S\, hence Si is S); i.e. v( S) = v(S) which is exactly 
(25:3:b). 

(25:6) for p = 1 with an = sign states v(/) = (in this case Si must be 
/) which is exactly (25:4). Owing to (25:3:b), this is exactly the same 
as (25:3:a). (Cf. the above proof of (25:4).) 

(25:6) for p = 3 with an g sign states v(S) + v(T) + v(- (S u T)) ^ 
(we write S, T for Si, S 2 ; hence SB is - (S u T)), i.e. 

-v(-OSuT)) vOS) +v(T). 

By (25:3:b) this becomes v(S u T) ^ v(S) + v(T) which is exactly (25:3:c). 
So our assertions are equivalent precisely to the conjunction of (25:3:a)- 
(25:3:c). 

26. Construction of a Game with a Given Characteristic Function 

26.1. The Construction 

26.1.1. We now prove the converse of 25.3. 1. : That for any numerical set 
function v(S) which fulfills the conditions (25:3:a)-(25:3:c) there exists a 
zero-sum n-person game F of which this v(S) is the characteristic function. 
In order to avoid confusion it is better to denote the given numerical 
set function which fulfills (25:3:a)-(25:3:c) by v (S). We shall define 
with its help a certain zero-sum n-person game F, and denote the char- 
acteristic function of this F by v(/S). It will then be necessary to prove that 



Let therefore a numerical set function v (S) which fulfills (25:3:a)- 
(25:3:c) be given. We define the zero-sum n-person game F as follows: 1 

Each player k = 1, 2, , n will, by a personal move, choose a subset 
Sk of / which contains k. Each one makes his choice independently of the 
choice of the other players. 2 

After this the payments to be made are determined as follows: 

Any set S of players, for which 

(26:1) S k = S for every k belonging to S 

is called a ring*** Any two rings with a common element are identical. 6 

1 This game F is essentially a more general analogue of the simple majority game of 
three persons, defined in 21. 1. We shall accompany the text which follows with footnotes 
pointing out the details of this analogy. 

2 The w-element set 7 has 2 n ~ l subsets S containing k, which we can enumerate by an 
index r*(/S) 1, 2, , 2*~ l . If we now let the player A; choose, instead of *, its 
index r* Tk(Sk) 1, 2, , 2 n ~ l , then the game is already in the normalized form of 
11.2.3. Clearly all fa - 2*' 1 . 

8 The rings are the analogues of the couples in 21.1. The contents of footnote 3 on 
p. 222 apply accordingly; in particular the rings are the formal concept in the set of rules 
of the game which induces the coalitions which influence the actual course of each play. 

4 Verbally: A ring is a set of players, in which every one has chosen just this set. 

The analogy with the definition of a couple in 21. 1. is clear. The differences are due 
to formal convenience: in 21.1. we made each player designate the other element of the 
couple which he desires; now we expect him to indicate the entire ring. A closer analysis 
of this divergence would be easy enough, but it does not seem necessary. 

6 Proof: Let S and T be two rings with a common element k\ then by (26:1) Sk = S 
and Si, - T, and so S - T. 



244 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 

In other words: The totality of all rings (which have actually formed in a 
play) is a system of pairwise disjunct subsets of /. 

Each player who is contained in none of the rings thus defined forms by 
himself a (one-element) set which is called a solo set. Thus the totality 
of all rings and solo sets (which have actually formed in a play) is a decompo- 
sition of /; i.e. a system of pairwise disjunct subsets of I with the sum I. 
Denote these sets by Ci, , C p and the respective numbers of their 
elements by n\, , n p . 

Consider now a player k. He belongs to precisely one of these sets 
Ci, , C p say to C q . Then player k gets the amount 



(26:2) _ v .(C.)- v (C r ). 1 

n q n 4 

r-l 

This completes the description of the game T. We shall now show that 
this F is a zero-sum n-person game and that it has the desired characteristic 
function v (). 

26.1.2. Proof of the zero-sum character: Consider one of the sets C q . 
Each one of the n q players belonging to it gets the same amount, stated in 
(26:2). Hence the players of C q together get the amount 

(26:3) 

r-l 

In order to obtain the total amount which all players 1, , n get, we 
must sum the expression (26:3) over all sets C q , i.e. over all q = 1, , p. 
This sum is clearly 



- v,(C r ), 

Q-l r-l 

i.e. zero. 2 

Proof that the characteristic function is v (S) : Denote the characteristic 
function of T by v(S). Remember that (25:3:a)-(25:3:c) hold for v(S) 
because it is a characteristic function, and for v (S) by hypothesis. Conse- 
quently (25:4)-(25:6) also hold for both v(S) and v (/S). 

We prove first that 

(26:4) v(iS) ^ v (S) for all subsets 8 of /. 

If S is empty, then both sides are zero by (25:3:a). So we may assume that 
S is not empty. In this case a coalition of all players k belonging to S can 

1 The course of the play, that is the choices Si, , S n or, in the sense of footnote 2 
on p. 243, the choices n, , r n determine the Ci, ; C p , and thus the expression 
(26:2). Of course (26:2) is the JC*(n, , r n ) of the general theory. 

p 

2 Obviously 2^ n q n. 



INESSENTIAL AND ESSENTIAL GAMES 245 

govern the choices of its Sh so as with certainty to make S a ring. It suf- 
fices for every k in S to choose his Sk = S. Whatever the other players 
(in S) do, S will thus be one of the sets (rings or solo sets) Ci, , C p , 
say C g . Thus each fc in C q = S gets the amount (26:2); hence the entire 
coalition S gets the amount (26:3). Now we know that the system 



p 
is a decomposition of /; hence by (25:6) ] v (C r ) ^ 0. That is, the 

r-l 

expression (26:3) is ^ v (C fl ) = VoOS). 1 In other words, the players belong- 
ing to the coalition S can secure for themselves at least the amount v (5) 
irrespective of what the players in S do. This means that v(S) ^ v (S); 
i.e. (26:4). 

Now we can establish the desired formula 



(26:5) v(S) 

Apply (26:4) to -S. Owing to (25:3:b) this means -v(S) ^ -v (S), i.e. 

(26:6) v(S) g VoOS). 

(26:4), (26:6) give together (26:5). 2 

26.2. Summary 

26.2. To sum up: in paragraphs 25.3.-26.1. we have obtained a com- 
plete mathematical characterization of the characteristic functions v(S) of 
all possible zero-sum n-person games F. If the surmise which we expressed 
in 25.2.1. proves to be true, i.e. if we shall be able to base the entire theory 
of the game on the global properties of the coalitions as expressed by v(S), 
then our characterization of v(/S) has revealed the exact mathematical 
substratum of the theory. Thus the characterization of v(S) and the func- 
tional relations (25:3:a)-(25:3:c) are of fundamental importance. 

We shall therefore undertake a first mathematical analysis of the mean- 
ing and of the immediate properties of these relations. We call the func- 
tions which satisfy them characteristic functions even when they are viewed 
in themselves, without reference to any game. 

27. Strategic Equivalence. Inessential and Essential Games 
27.1. Strategic Equivalence. The Reduced Form 

27.1.1. Consider a zero-sum n-person game T with the characteristic 
function v(S). Let also a system of numbers aj, , 2 be given. We 

1 Observe that the expression (26:3), i.e. the total amount obtained by the coalition S, 
is not determined by the choices of the players in S alone. But we derived for it a lower 
bound v (), which is determined. 

2 Observe that in our discussion of the good strategies of the (fictitious) two-person 
game between the coalitions S and S (our above proof really amounted to that), we 
considered only pure strategies, and no mixed ones. In other words, all these two-person 
games happened to be strictly determined. 

This, however, is irrelevant for the end which we are now pursuing. 



246 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 

now form a new game F' which agrees with F in all details except for this: 
F' is played in exactly the same way as F, but when all is over, player k gets 
in F' the amount which he would have got in F (after the same play), plus a. 
(Observe that the aj, , 2 are absolute constants!) Thus if F is 
brought into the normalized form of 11.2.3. with the functions 



then F' is also in this normalized form, with the corresponding functions 
3C*( r i> * ' ' > r n) 3C*(ri, - - , r n ) + ajj. Clearly F' will be a zero-sum 
n-person game (along with F) if and only if 

(27:1) i J = 0, 

fc-1 

which we assume. 

Denote the characteristic function of F' by v'(S), then clearly 



(27:2) v'(S) 

kinS 

Now it is apparent that the strategic possibilities of the two games F and F' 
are exactly the same. The only difference between these two games con- 
sists of the fixed payments J after each play. And these payments are 
absolutely fixed; nothing that any or all of the players can do will modify 
them. One could also say that the position of each player has been shifted 
by a fixed amount, but that the strategic possibilities, the inducements and 
possibilities to form coalitions etc., are entirely unaffected. In other words: 
If two characteristic functions v(S) and v'(S) are related to each other by 
(27 :2) 2 , then every game with the characteristic function v(S) is fully equiva- 
lent from all strategic points of view to some game with the characteristic 
function v'(S), and conversely. I.e. v(S) and v'(S) describe two strategi- 
cally equivalent families of games. In this sense v(S) and v'(S) may them- 
selves be considered equivalent. 

Observe that all this is independent of the surmise restated in 26.2., 
according to which all games with the same v(S) have the same strategic 
characteristics. 

27.1.2. The transformation (27:2) (we need pay no attention to (27:1), 
cf. footnote 2 above) replaces, as we have seen, the set functions v(/S) by a 

1 The truth of this relation becomes apparent if one recalls how v(S), v'(S) were 
defined with the help of the coalition S. It is also easy to prove (27:2) formalistically 
with the help of the3C*(n, , r n ), 3Ci(n, , r n ). 

s Under these conditions (27:1) follows and need not be postulated separately. 
Indeed, by (25:4) in 25.4.1., v(7) - v'(7) - 0, hence (27:2) gives 

n 

2) <4 - 0; i.e. a - 0. 
klal k-l 



INESSENTIAL AND ESSENTIAL GAMES 247 

strategically fully equivalent set-function v'(S). We therefore call this 
relationship strategic equivalence. 

We now turn to a mathematical property of this concept of strategic 
equivalence of characteristic functions. 

It is desirable to pick from each family of characteristic functions v(S) 
in strategic equivalence a particularly simple representative v(/S). The 
idea is that, given v(S), this representative v(S) should be easy to determine, 
and that on the other hand two v(S) and v'(S) would be in strategic equiva- 
lence if and only if their representatives v(*S) and v'(*S) are identical. 
Besides, we may try to choose these representatives v(S) in such a fashion 
that their analysis is simpler than that of the original v(S). 

27.1.3. When we started from characteristic functions v(S) and v'(S), 
then the concept of strategic equivalence could be based upon (27:2) alone; 
(27:1) ensued (cf. footnote 2, p. 246). However, we propose to start now 
from one characteristic function v(S) alone, and to survey all possible v'(S) 
which are in strategic equivalence with it in order to choose the representa- 
tive v(/S) from among them. Therefore the question arises which systems 
aj, , aj we may use, i.e. for which of these systems (using (27:2)) the 
fact that v(S) is a characteristic function entails the same for v'(S). The 
answer is immediate, both by what we have said so far, and by direct 
verification: The condition (27:1) is necessary and sufficient. 1 

Thus we have the n indeterminate quantities aj, , a at our 
disposal in the search for a representative v(S); but the S> ' ' * > a n ar 
subject to one restriction: (27:1). So we have n 1 free parameters at 
our disposal. 

27.1.4. We may therefore expect that we can subject the desired repre- 
sentative v(S) to n 1 requirements. As such we choose the equations 



(27:3) v((l)) = v((2)) = . = v((")). 2 

I.e. we require that every one-man coalition every player left to himself 
should have the same value. 

We may substitute (27:2) into (27:3) and state this together with (27:1), 
and so formulate all our requirements concerning the aj, , a. So 
we obtain: 

(27:1*) al = 0, 

t-i 



(27:2*) 

It is easy to verify that these equations are solved by precisely one system of 

' 



1 This detailed discussion may seem pedantic. We gave it only to make clear that 
when we start with two characteristic functions v(S) and v'(S) then (27:1) is superfluous, 
but when we start with one characteristic function only, then (27:1) is needed. 

1 Observe that these are n 1 and not n equations. 



248 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 



(27:4) a{ 

So we can say: 

(27: A) We call a characteristic function v(S) reduced if and only if it 

satisfies (27:3). Then every characteristic function v(S) is in 
strategic equivalence with precisely one reduced v(S). This 
v(S) is given by the formulae (27:2) and (27:4), and we call it the 
reduced form of v(S). 

The reduced functions will be the representatives for which we have 
been looking. 

27.2. Inequalities. The Quantity r 

27.2. Let us consider a reduced characteristic function v(S). We 
denote the joint value of the n terms in (27:3) by 7, i.e. 

(27:5) - 7 



We can state (27:5) also this way: 

(27:5*) v(S) = 7 for every one-element set S. 

Combination with (25:3:b) in 25.3.1. transforms (27:5*) into 
(27:5**) v(S) = 7 for every (n - l)-element set S. 

We re-emphasize that any one of (27:5), (27:5*), (27:5**) is besides 
defining 7 just a restatement of (27:3), i.e. a characterization of the reduced 
nature of v(S). 

Now apply (25:6) in 25.4.1. to the one-element sets Si = (1), , 
<S = (n). (So p = n). Then (27:5) gives -ny ^ 0, i.e.: 

(27:6) 7^0. 

Consider next an arbitrary subset S of /. Let p be the number of its 
elements: S = (fti, , k p ). Now apply (25:5) in 25.4.1. to the one- 
element sets Si = (fci), , S p = (k p ). Then (27:5) gives 



Apply this also to S which has n p elements. Owing to (25:3:b) in 
25.3.1., the above inequality now becomes 

-*(fl) 2S -(n - p)75 i.e. v(/S) S (n - p)y. 

1 Proof: Denote the joint value of the n terms in (27:2*) by 0. Then (27:2*) amounts 
to al - -v((fc)) + 0, and so (27:1*) becomes 

n n 

n0 - % v((*)) - 0; i.e. - 
fc-i *-i 



INESSENTIAL AND ESSENTIAL GAMES 249 

Combining these two inequalities gives: 
(27:7) py ^ v(/S) g (n p)y for every p-element set S. 

(27:5*) and v(0) = (i.e. (25:3:a) in 25.3.1.) can also be formulated 
this way: 

(27:7*) For p = 0, 1 we have = in the first relation of (27:7). 

(27:5**) and v(7) = (i.e. (25:4) in 25.4.1.) can also be formulated 
this way: 

(27:7**) For p = n 1, n we have = in the second relation of (27:7). 

27.3. Inessentiality and Essentiality 

27.3.1. In analyzing these inequalities it is best now to distinguish two 
alternatives. 

This distinction is based on (27 :6) : 

First case: 7 = 0. Then (27:7) gives v(S) =0 for all S. This is a 
perfectly trivial case, in which the game is manifestly devoid of further 
possibilities. There is no occasion for any strategy of coalitions, no element 
of struggle or competition: each player may play a lone hand, since there 
is no advantage in any coalition. Indeed, every player can get the amount 
zero for himself irrespective of what the others are doing. And in no 
coalition can all its members together get more than zero. Thus the value 
of a play of this game is zero for every player, in an absolutely unequivocal 
way. 

If a general characteristic function v(S) is in strategic equivalence 
with such a v(S) i.e. if its reduced form is v(S) = then we have the 
same conditions, only shifted by a for the player k. A play of a game F 
with this characteristic function v(S) has unequivocally the value ajj for 
the player k: he can get this amount even alone, irrespective of what the 
others are doing. No coalition could do better in toto. 

We call a game F, the characteristic function v(S) of which has such a 
reduced form v(S) = 0, inessential. 1 

27.3.2. Second case :y > 0. By a change in unit 2 we could make y = I. 8 
This obviously affects none of the strategically significant aspects of the 
game, and it is occasionally quite convenient to do. At this moment, how- 
ever, we do not propose to do this. 

In the present case, at any rate, the players will have good reasons to 
want to form coalitions. Any player who is left to himself loses the amount 
y (i.e. he gets -7, cf. (27:5*) or (27:7*)), while any n - 1 players who 

1 That this coincides with the meaning given to the word inessential in 23.1.3. (in the 
special case of a zero-sum three-person game) will be seen at the end of 27.4.1. 

2 Since payments are made, we mean the monetary unit. In a wider sense it might 
be the unit of utility. Cf. 2.1.1, 

3 This would not have been possible in the first case, where 7 0. 



250 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 

cooperate win together the amount 7 (i.e. their coalition gets 7, cf. (27:5**) 
or (27:?**)). 1 

Hence an appropriate strategy of coalitions is now of great importance. 

We call a game T essential when its characteristic function v(S) has a 
reduced form v(S) not = O. 2 

27.4. Various Criteria. Non-additive Utilities 

27.4.1. Given a characteristic function v(S), we wish to have an explicit 
expression for the 7 of its reduced form v(S). (Cf. above.) 

Now 7 is the joint value of the v((fc)), i.e. of the v((fc)) + aj, and this 



is by (27:4) i V v((j)). Hence 

j-i 

(27:8) 7 = - i 



y-i 

Consequently we have: 

(27 :B) The game F is inessential if and only if 

t v((j)) = (i.e. 7 = 0), 

3-1 

and it is essential if and only if 

S v((/)) < (i.e. 7 > 0).* 

;-l 

For a zero-sum three-person game we have, with the notations of 23.1., 
v((l)) = -a, v((2)) = -6, v((3)) = -c; so 7 = iA. Therefore our con- 
cepts of essential and inessential specialize to those of 23.1.3. in the case 
of a zero-sum three-person game. Considering the interpretation of these 
concepts in both cases, this was to be expected. 

1 This is, of course, not the whole story There may be other coalitions of > 1 
but < n 1 players which are worth aspiring to. (If this is to happen, n 1 must 
exceed 1 by more than 1, i.e. n ^ 4.) This depends upon the ^(S) of the sets S with 
> 1 but < n 1 elements. But only a complete and detailed theory of games can 
appraise the role of these coalitions correctly. 

Our above comparison of isolated players and n 1 player coalitions (the biggest 
coalitions which have anybody to oppose!) suffices only for our present purpose: to 
establish the importance of coalitions in this situation. 

1 Cf . again footnote 1 on p. 249. 

8 So -7 is the of footnote 1 on p. 248. 

n 

4 We have seen already that one or the other must be the case, since 2} v ((/)) ^ as 

;'-i 
well as 7 0. 



INESSENTIAL AND ESSENTIAL GAMES 251 

27.4.2. We can formulate, some other criteria of inessentiality: 
(27 :C) The game F is inessential if and only if its characteristic function 

v(S) can be given this form: 

v(S) 2) aj 

tin 5 

for a suitable system a?, , aJJ. 

Proo/: Indeed, this expresses by (27:2) precisely that v(S) is in strategic 
equivalence with v(S) = 0. As this v(S) is reduced, it is then the reduced 
form of v(S) and this is the meaning of inessentiality. 

(27 :D) The game F is inessential if and only if its -characteristic 

function v(S) has always = in (25:3:c) of 25.3.1.; i.e. when 

V (S u T) = v(S) + v(T) if S n T = 0. 

Proof: Necessity: A v(S) of the form given in (27 :C) above obviously 
possesses this property. 

Sufficiency: Repeated application of this equation gives = in (25:5) of 
25.4.1.; i.e. 

v(Si u - - - u Sp) = v(SO + + v(Sp) 

if Si, , S p are pairwise disjunct. 

Consider an arbitrary S, say S = (fci, , k p ). Then Si = (fci), , 
S P = (k p ) give 

v(S) = v((*0) + + v((*,)). 
So we have 

v(S) = 5) a k 

km 8 

with a? = v((l)), , a = v((n)) and so F is inessential by (27 :C). 

27.4.3. Both criteria (27 :C) and (27 :D) express that the values of all 
coalitions arise additively from those of their constituents. 1 It will be 
remembered what role the additivity of value, or rather its frequent absence, 
has played in economic literature. The cases in which value is not gen- 
erally additive were among the most important, but they offered sig- 
nificant difficulties to every theoretical approach; and one cannot say 
that these difficulties have ever been really overcome. In this connection 
one should recall the discussions of concepts like complementarity, total 
value, imputation, etc. We are now getting into the corresponding phase 
of our theory; and it is significant that we find additivity only in the unin- 

c 

1 The reader will understand that we are using the word "value" (of the coalition S) 
for the quantity v(S). 



252 



GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 



teresting (inessential) case, while the really significant (essential) games 
have a non-additive characteristic function. 1 

Those readers who are familiar with the mathematical theory of measure 
will make this further observation: the additive v(S) i.e. the inessential 
games are exactly the measure functions of /, which give I the total 
measure zero. Thus the general characteristic functions v(S) are a new 
generalization of the concept of measure. These remarks are in a deeper 
sense connected with the preceding ones concerning economic value. How- 
ever, it would lead too far to pursue this subject further. 2 

27.5. The Inequalities in the Essential Case 

27.5.1. Let us return to the inequalities of 27.2., in particular to (27:7), 
(27:7*), (27:7**). For 7 = (inessential case) everything is trivially 
clear. Assume therefore that y > (essential case). 




Figure 50. 

Abscissa: p, number of elements of S. Dot at 0, 7, 7, or heavy line: Range of 
possible values v(S) for the S with the corresponding p. 

Now (27:7), (27:7*), (27:7**) set a range of possible values for v(S) 
for every number p of elements in S. This range is pictured for each 
p = 0, 1, 2, - , n 2, n 1, n in Figure 50. 

We can add the following remarks: 

27.5.2. First: It will be observed that in an essential game i.e. when 
7 > necessarily n ^ 3. Otherwise the formulae (27:7), (27:7*), 
(27:7**) or Figure 50, which expresses their content lead to a conflict: 
For n = 1 or 2 an (n l)-element set S has or 1 elements, hence its 

1 We are, of course, concerned at this moment only with a particular aspect of the 
subject: we are considering values of coalitions only i.e. of concerted acts of behavior 
and not of economic goods or services. The reader will observe, however, that the spe- 
cialization is not as far reaching as it may seem : goods and services stand really for the 
economic act of their exchange i.e. for a concerted act of behavior. 

*The theory of measure reappears in another connection. Cf. 41.3.3. 



INESSENTIAL AND ESSENTIAL GAMES 253 

v(S) must on the one hand be 7, and on the other hand or 7, which is 
impossible. 1 

Second: For the smallest possible number of participants in an essential 
game, i.e. for n = 3, the formulae (27:7), (27:7*), (27:7**) or Figure 50 
determine everything: they state the values of v(S) for 0, 1, n 1, n~element 
sets S; and for n = 3 the following are all possible element numbers: 0, 1, 2, 
3. (Cf. also a remark in footnote 1 on p. 250.) This is in harmony with 
the fact which we found in 23.1.3., according to which there exists only 
one type of essential zero-sum three-person games. 

Third: For greater numbers of participants, i.e. for n ^ 4, the problem 
assumes a new complexion. As formulae (27:7), (27:7*), (27:7**) or 
Figure 50 show, the element number of p of the set S can now have 
other values than 0, 1, n 1, n. I.e. the interval 

(27:9) 2 g p ^ n - 2 

now becomes available. 2 It is in this interval that the above formulae no 
longer determine a unique value of v(S); they set for it only the interval 

(27:7) -P7 ^ v(S) S (n - p) 7 , 

the length of which is ny for every p (cf. again Figure 50). 

27.6.3. In this connection the question may be asked whether really 
the entire interval (27:7) is available, i.e. whether it cannot be narrowed 
further by some new, more elaborate considerations concerning v(S). 
The answer is: No. It is actually possible to define for every n 4 a 
single game F p in which, for each p of (27:9), v(5) assumes both values 
p7 and (n p)y for suitable p-element sets S. It may suffice to mention 
the subject here without further elaboration. 

To sum up: The real ramifications of the theory of games appear only 
when n ^ 4 is reached. (Cf. footnote 1 on p. 250, where the same idea 
was expounded.) 

27.6. Vector Operations on Characteristic Functions 

27.6.1. In concluding this section some remarks of a more formal nature 
seem appropriate. 

The conditions (25:3:a)-(25:3:c) in 25.3.1., which describe the charac- 
teristic function v(S), have a certain vectorial character: they allow ana- 
logues of the vector operations, defined in 16.2. 1., of scalar multiplication, and 
of vector addition. More precisely: 

Scalar multiplication: Given a constant t ^ and a characteristic func- 
tion v(S), then tv(S) = u(S) is also a characteristic function. Vector 
addition: Given two characteristic functions v(S), w(S); 3 then 

1 Of course, in a zero-sum one-person game nothing happens at all, and for the zero- 
sum two-person games we have a theory in which no coalitions appear. Hence the 
inessentiality of all these cases is to be expected. 

s It has n 3 elements; and this number is positive as soon as n ^ 4. 

8 Everything here must refer to the same n and to the same set of players 

/ - (1, 2, - - - , n). 



254 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 

v(S) + w(S) z(S) is also a characteristic function. The only difference 
from the corresponding definitions of 16.2. is that we had to require t S> O. 1 - 2 

27.6.2. The two operations defined above allow immediate practical 
interpretation: 

Scalar multiplication: If t = 0, then this produces u(/S) as 0, i.e. the 
eventless game considered in 27.3.1. So we may assume t > 0. In this 
case our operation amounts to a change of the unit of utility, namely to its 
multiplication by the factor t. 

Vector addition: This corresponds to the superposition of the games 
corresponding to v(S) and to w(S). One would imagine that the same 
players 1, 2, , n are playing these two games simultaneously, but 
independently. I.e., no move made in one game is supposed to influence 
the other game, as far as the rules are concerned. In this case the charac- 
teristic function of the combined game is clearly the sum of those of the two 
constituent games. 3 

27.6.3. We do not propose to enter upon a systematic investigation of 
these operations, i.e. of their influence upon the strategic situations in the 
games which they affect. It may be useful, however, to make some remarks 
on this subject without attempting in any way to be exhaustive. 

We observe first that combinations of the operations of scalar multiplica- 
tion and vector addition also can now be interpreted directly. Thus the 
characteristic function 

(27:10) z(S) = tv(S) + w(5) 

belongs to the game which arises by superposition of the games of v(S) and 
w(S) if their units of utility are first multiplied by t and s respectively. 

If s = 1 t y then (27:10) corresponds to the formation of the center of 
gravity in the sense of (16:A:c) in 16.2.1. 

It will appear from the discussion in 35.3.4. (cf. in particular footnote 1 
on p. 304 below) that even this seemingly elementary operation can have 
very involved consequences as regards strategy. 

We observe next that there are some cases where our operations have no 
consequences in strategy. 

First, the scalar multiplication by a t > alone, being a mere change in 
unit, has no such consequences. 

indeed, t < would upset (25:3:c) in 25.3.1. Note that a multiplication of the 
original 3C*(n, , r n ) with a t < would be perfectly feasible. It is simplest to 
consider a multiplication by t 1, i.e. a change in sign. But a change of sign of the 
3C*(Ti, , r) does not at all correspond to a change of sign of the v(S). This should be 
clear by common sense, as a reversal of gains and losses modifies all strategic considera- 
tions in a very involved way. (This reversal and some of its consequences are familiar 
to chess players.) A formal corroboration of our assertion may be found by inspecting 
the definitions of 25.1.3. 

* Vector spaces with this restriction of scalar multiplication are sometimes called 
positive vector spaces. We do not need to enter upon their systematic theory. 

3 This should be intuitively obvious. An exact verification with the help of 25.1.3. 
involves a somewhat cumbersome notation, but no real difficulties. 



GROUPS, SYMMETRY AND FAIRNESS 255 

Second and this is of greater significance the strategic equivalence 
discussed in 27.1. is a superposition: we pass from the game of v(S) to the 
strategically equivalent game of v'(S) by superposing on the former an 
inessential game. 1 (Cf. (27:1) and (27:2) in 27.1.1. and, concerning inessen- 
tiality, 27.3.1. and (27 :C) in 27.4.2.) We may express this in the following 
way: we know that an inessential game is one in which coalitions play no 
role. The superposition of such a game on another one does not disturb 
strategic equivalence, i.e. it leaves the strategic structure of that game 
unaffected. 

28. Groups, Symmetry and Fairness 
28.1. Permutations, Their Groups, and Their Effect on a Game 

28.1.1. Let us now consider the role of symmetry, or more generally, the 
effects of interchanging the players !,-, n or their numbers in an 
n-person game F. This will naturally be an extension of the corresponding 
study made in 17.11. for the zero-sum two-person game. 

This analysis begins with what is in the main a repetition of the steps 
taken in 17.11. for n = 2. But since the interchanges of the symbols 
1, , n offer for a general n many more possibilities than for n = 2, it is 
indicated that we should go about it somewhat more systematically. 

Consider the n symbols 1, , n. Form any permutation P of these 
symbols. P is described by stating for every i = 1, , n, into which i p 
(also = 1, , n), P carries it. So we write: 

(28:1) P:i-*i p , 

or by way of complete enumeration: 



Among the permutations some deserve special mention: 

(28:A:a) The identity I n which leaves every i(= 1, * , n) un- 

changed: 

i - i ln = i. 

(28:A:b) Given two permutations P, Q, their product PQ, which 

consists in carrying out first P and then Q: 



1 With the characteristic function w(S) 2} <** then i n our above notatibns 

fcinS 

v'OSf) - vGSf) +w(S) 

(1 2\ 
2* I/ 

The identity (cf. below) is / - ( !' ' ' ' ' ' *\ 

\i, z, , n/ 



256 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 

The number of all possible permutations is the factorial of n r 

n\ = 1 2 . . . n, 

and they form together the symmetric group of permutations 2 n . Any 
subsystem G of 2 n which fulfills these two conditions: 

(28:A:a*) / n belongs to G, 

(28:A:b*) PQ belongs to G if P and Q do, 

is a group of permutations. 1 

A permutation P carries every subset S of / = (!, , n) into another 
subset S p * 

28.1.2. After these general and preparatory remarks we now proceed 
to apply their concepts to an arbitrary n-person game F. 

Perform a permutation P on the symbols 1, , n denoting the players 
of F. I.e. denote the player k = 1, , n by k p instead of fc; this trans- 
forms the game F into another game F p . The replacement of F by F p must 
make its influence felt in two respects: in the influence which each player 
exercises on the course of the play, i.e. in the index k of the variable r k 
which each player chooses; and in the outcome of the play for him, i.e. in 
the index k of the function 3C* which expresses this. 8 So T p is again in the 
normalized form, with functions 3C(ri, , r n ), k = 1, , n. In 
expressing 3C(ri, , r n ) by means of 3C*(ri, , r n ), we must remem- 
ber: the player k in F had 3C*; now he is k p in F p , so he has3C>. If we form 
3C* with the variables TI, , r n , then we express the outcome of the 
game T p when the player whose designation in F p is k chooses r*. So the 
player k in F who is k p in T p chooses T*/>. So the variables in 3C* must be 
TIP, * , r n p. We have therefore: 

(28:3) 



1 For the important and extensive theory of groups compare L. C. Mathewson: 
Elementary Theory of Finite Groups, Boston 1930; W. Burnside: Theory of Groups of 
Finite Order, 2nd Ed. Cambridge 1911; A. Speiser: Theorie der Gruppen von endlicher 
Ordnung, 3rd Edit. Berlin 1937. 

We shall not need any particular results or concepts of group theory, and mention 
the above literature only for the use of the reader who may want to acquire a deeper 
insight into that subject. 

Although we do not wish to tie up our exposition with the intricacies of group theory, 
we nevertheless introduced some of its basic termini for this reason : a real understanding 
of the nature and structure of symmetry is not possible without some familiarity with 
(at least) the elements of group theory. We want to prepare the reader who may want to 
proceed in this direction, by using the correct terminology. 

For a fuller exposition of the relationship between symmetry and group theory, cf. 
H. Weyl: Symmetry, Journ. Washington Acad. of Sciences, Vol. XXVIII (1938), pp. 
253ff. 

*If S - (* , *,), then S p - (ibf, , k p ). 

8 Cf . the similar situation for n = 2 in footnote 1 on p. 109. 

4 The reader will observe that the superscript P for the index k of the functions 3C 
themselves appears on the left-hand side, while the superscript P for the indices k of the 
variables r* appear on the right-hand side. This is the correct arrangement; and the 
argument preceding (28:3) was needed to establish it. 

The importance of getting this point faultless and clear lies in the fact that we could 



GROUPS, SYMMETRY AND FAIRNESS 257 

Denote the characteristic functions of T and T p by v(S) and v p (S) 
respectively. Since the players, who form in T p the set S p , are the same ones 
who form in T the set S, we have 

(28:4) v p (S p ) = v(5) for every S. 1 

28.1.3. If (for a particular P) T coincides with T p , then we say that T is 
invariant or symmetric with respect to P. By virtue of (28:3) this is 
expressed by 

(28:5) 3Mn, , r n ) ^ 3C*(nP, , T|| -). 

When this is the case, then (28:4) becomes 

(28:6) v(8 p ) = v(S) for every S. 

Given any T, we can form the system G r of all P with respect to which T 
is symmetric. It is clear from (28:A:a), (28:A:b) above, that the identity 7 n 
belongs to Gr, and that if P, Q belong to G r , then their product PQ does too. 
So Gr is a group by (28:A:a*), (28:A:b*) above. We call Gr the invariance 
group of F. 

Observe that (28:6) can now be stated in this form: 

(28:7) v(S) = v(r) if there exists a P in Gr with S p = T, 

i.e. which carries S into T. 

The size of Gr i.e. the number of its elements gives some sort of a 
measure of "how symmetric " F is. If every permutation P (other than 
identity 7 n ) changes T, then G r consists of 7 n alone, r is totally unsymmetric. 
If no permutation P changes T, then G r contains all P, i.e. it is the sym- 
metric group S n , F is totally symmetric. There are, of course, numerous 
intermediate cases between these two extremes, and the precise structure 
of T's symmetry (or lack of it) is disclosed by the group G r . 

28.1.4. The condition after (28:7) implies that S and T have the same 
number of elements. The converse implication, however, need not be 
true if Gr is small enough, i.e. if F is unsymmetric enough. It is therefore 

not otherwise be sure that successive applications of the superscripts P and Q (in this 
order) to r will give the same result as a (single) application of the superscript PQ to r. 
The reader may find the verification of this a good exercise in handling the calculus of 
permutations. 

For n 2 and P I ' . J , application of P on either side had the same effect, so it is 

not necessary to be exhaustive on this point. Cf . footnote 1 on p. 109. 

6 In the zero-sum two-person game, 3C 3C t B 3C 2 , and similarly 3C F s 3Cf = 3Cf . 

Hence in this case (cf . above, n - 2 and P - \\ ' ^ j J (28:3) becomes 3C p (n, n) -3C(ri, n). 

This is in accord with the formulae of 14.6. and 17.11.2. 

But this simplification is possible only in the zero-sum two-person game; in all 
other cases we must rely upon the general formula (28:3) alone. 

1 This conceptual proof is clearer and simpler than a computational one, which could 
be based on the formulae of 25.1.3. The latter, however, would cause no difficulties 
either, only more extensive notations. 



258 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 

of interest to consider those groups G = Gr which permit this converse 
implication, i.e. for which the following is true: 

(28:8) If S, T have the same number of elements, then there exists 

a P in G with S p = T, i.e. which carries S into T. 

This condition (28 :8) is obviously satisfied when G is the symmetric group 
S n , i.e. for the G = Gr = S n of a totally symmetric F. It is also satisfied 
for certain smaller groups, i.e. for certain F of less than total symmetry. 1 

28.2. Symmetry and Fairness 

28.2.1. At any rate, whenever (28:8) holds for G = Gr, we can conclude 
from (28:7): 

(28:9) v(S) depends only upon the number of elements in S. 

That is: 

(28:10) v(S) = v p 

where p is the number of elements in /S, (p 0, 1, , ri). 

Consider the conditions (25:3:a)-(25:3:c) in 25.3.1., which give an 
exhaustive description of all characteristic functions v(S). It is easy to 
rewrite them for v p when (28:10) holds. They become: 

(28:ll:a) v = 0, 

(28:ll:b) v n _ p = -v p , 

(28:ll:c) v p+q ^ v p + v q for p + q g n. 

(27:3) in 27.1.4. is clearly a consequence of (28:10) (i.e. of (28:9)), 
so that such a v(S) is automatically reduced, with 7 = VL We have 
therefore, in particular, (27:7), (27:7*), (27:7**) in 27.2., i.e. the conditions 
of Figure 50. 

Condition (28:ll:c) can be rewritten, by a procedure which is parallel 
to that of (25: A) in 25.4.2. 

(1 2\ 
2' 1 / 
cf. several preceding references); so G = 2 n is the only possibility of any symmetry. 

Consider therefore n 3, and call G set-transitive if it fulfills (28:8). The question, 
which G T* S n are then set-transitive, is of a certain group-theoretical interest, but we 
need not concern ourselves with it in this work. 

For the reader who is interested in group theory we nevertheless mention: 

There exists a subgroup of S n which contains half of its elements (i.e. in!), known as 
the alternating group O. This group is of great importance in group theory and has been 
extensively discussed there. For n ^ 3 it is easily seen to be set-transitive too. 

So the real question is this: for which n < 3 do there exist set-transitive groups 
G * S; a? 

It is easy to show that for n = 3, 4 none exist. For n ** 5, 6 such groups do exist. 
(For n 5 a set-transitive group G with 20 elements exists, while S 6 , as have 120, 60 
elements respectively. For n = 6 a set-transitive group G with 120 elements exists, 
while Se, tte have 720, 360 elements respectively.) For n 7, 8 rather elaborate group- 
theoretical arguments show that no such groups exist. For n 9 the question is still 
open. It seems probable that no such groups exist for any n > 9, but this assertion has 
not yet been established for all these n. 



GROUPS, SYMMETRY AND FAIRNESS 269 

Put r = n p q\ then (28:ll:b) permits us to state (28:ll:c) as 
follows: 

(28:ll:c*) v p + v, + v r ^ if p + q + r = n. 

Now (28:ll:c*) is symmetric with respect to p, g, r; 1 hence we may make 
p ^ q ^ r by an appropriate permutation. Furthermore, when p = 
(hence r-= n - g), then (28:11 :c*) follows from (28:11 :a), (28:11 :b) 
(even with =). Thus we may assume p 7*. o. So we need to require 
(28:ll:c*) only for 1 g p ^ g g r, and therefore the same is true for 
(28:ll:c). Observe finally that, as r = n p q, the inequality g ^ r 
means p + 2q ^ n. We restate this: 

(28:12) It suffices to require (28:ll:c) only when 

1 ^ P ^ q, p + 2g ^ n. 2 

28.2.2. The property (28:10) of the characteristic function is a conse- 
quence of symmetry, but this property is also important in its own right. 
This becomes clear when we consider it in the simplest possible special case: 
for n = 2. 

Indeed, for n = 2 (28:10) simply means that the v' of 17.8.1. vanishes. 8 
This means in the terminology of 17.11.2., that the game T is fair. We 
extend this concept: The n-person game F is fair when its characteristic 
function v(S) fulfills (28:9), i.e. when it is a v p of (28:10). Now, as in 
17.11.2., this notion of fairness of the game embodies what is really essential 
in the concept of symmetry. It must be remembered, however, that the 
concept of fairness and similarly that of total symmetry of the game 
may or may not imply that all individual players can expect the same fate 
in an individual play (provided that they play well). For n = 2 this 
implication did hold, but not for n ^ 3 ! (Cf. 17.11.2. for the former, and 
footnotes 1 and 2 on p. 225 for the latter.) 

28.2.3. We observe, finally, that by (27:7), (27:7*), (27:7**) in 27.2., or 
by Figure 50, all reduced games are symmetric and hence fair, when n = 3, 
but not when n ^ 4. (Cf. the discussion in 27.5. 2.) Now the unrestricted 
zero-sum n-person game is brought into its reduced form by the fixed 
extra payments i, , a n (to the players 1, , n, respectively), as 
described in 27.1. Thus the unfairness of a zero-sum three-person game 
i.e. what is really effective in its asymmetry is exhaustively expressed 
by these i, 2, 8 ; that is, by fixed, definite payments. (Cf. also the 
"basic values/ 7 a', 6', c' of 22.3.4.) In a zero-sum n-person game with 

1 Both in its assertion and in its hypothesis! 

1 These inequalities replace the original p + q ^ n; they are obviously much stronger. 
As they imply 3p ^ p + 2g ^ n and 1 -f 2q ^ p -f 2g ^ n, we have 

n n - 1 

P ^ 3' q * ^~" 

8 By definition v' v((l)) v((2)). For n 2 the only essential assertion of 
(28:9) (which is equivalent to (28:10)) is v((l)) v((2)). Due to the above, this means 
precisely that v' - -v', i.e. that v' - 0. 



260 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 

n ^ 4, this is no longer always possible, since the reduced form need 
not be fair. That is, there may exist, in such a game, much more funda- 
mental differences between the strategic positions of the players, which 
cannot be expressed by the !,, a n , i.e. by fixed, definite payments. 
This will become amply clear in the course of Chapter VII. In the same 
connection it is also useful to recall footnote 1 on p. 250. 

29. Reconsideration of the Zero-sum Three-person Game 
29.1. Qualitative Discussion 

29.1.1. We are now prepared for the main undertaking: To formulate 
the principles of the theory of the zero-sum n-person game. l The character- 
istic function v(S), which we have defined in the preceding sections, provides 
the necessary tool for this operation. 

Our procedure will be the same as before: We must select a special case 
to serve as a basis for further investigation. This shall be one which we 
have already settled and which we nevertheless deem sufficiently charac- 
teristic for the general case. By analyzing the (partial) solution found 
in this special case, we shall then try to crystallize the rules which should 
govern the general case. After what we said in 4.3.3. and in 25.2.2., it 
ought to be plausible that the zero-sum three-person game will be the special 
case in question. 

29.1.2. Let us therefore reconsider the argument by which our present 
solution of the zero-sum three-person game was obtained. Clearly the 
essential case will be the one of interest. We know now that we may as 
well consider it in its reduced form, and that we may also choose y = I. 2 
The characteristic function in this case is completely determined, as dis- 
cussed in the second case of 27.5.2.: 



(29:1) v(5) 





-1 
1 




when S has 



elements. 



3 



We saw that in this game everything is decided by the (two-person) 
coalitions which form, and our discussions 4 produced the following main 
conclusions: 

Three coalitions may form, and accordingly the three players will 
finish the play with the following results: 

1 Of course the general n-person game will still remain, but we shall be able to solve 
it with the help of the zero-sum games. The greatest step is the present one : the passage 
to the zero-sum n-person games. 

Cf. 27.1.4. and 27.3.2. 

1 In the notation of 23.1.1. this means a b c 1. The general parts of the 
discussions referred to were those in 22.2., 22.3., 23. The above specialization takes us 
actually back to the earlier (more special) case of 22.1. So our considerations of 27.1. 
(on strategic equivalence and reduction) have actually this effect in the zero-sum three- 
person games: they cany the general case back into the preceding special one, as stated 
above. 

4 In 22.2.2., 22.2.3.; but these are really just elaborations of those in 22.1.2., 22.1.3. 



RECONSIDERATION 



261 




(1,2) 



(1,3) 



(2,3) 



-1 



-1 



Figure 51. 

This " solution " calls for interpretation, and the following remarks suggest 
themselves in particular: 1 
29.1.3. 

(29:A:a) The three distributions specified above correspond to all 

strategic possibilities of the game. 

(29:A:b) None of them can be considered a solution in itself; it is the 

system of all three and their relationship to each other which 
really constitute the solution. 

(29:A:c) The three distributions possess together, in particular, a 

"stability" to which we have referred thus far only very 
sketchily. Indeed no equilibrium can be found outside of 
these three distributions; and so one should expect that any 
kind of negotiation between the players must always in fine 
lead to one of these distributions. 

(29:A:d) Again it is conspicuous that this "stability" is only a 

characteristic of all three distributions viewed together. No 
one of them possesses it alone; each one, taken by itself, could 
be circumvented if a different coalition pattern should spread 
to the necessary majority of players. 

29.1.4. We now proceed to search for an exact formulation of the 
heuristic principles which lead us to the solutions of Figure 51, always 
keeping in mind the remarks (29:A:a)-(29:A:d). 

A more precise statement of the intuitively recognizable "stability" 
of the system of three distributions in Figure 51 which should be a concise 
summary of the -discussions referred to in footnote 4 on p. 260 leads us 
back to a position already taken in the earlier, qualitative discussions. 2 
It can be put as follows: 

(29:B:a) If any other scheme of distribution should be offered for 

consideration to the three players, then it will meet with 

1 These remarks take up again the considerations of 4.3.3. In connection with 
(29;A:d) the second half of 4.6.2. may also be recalled. 

* These viewpoints permeate all of 4.4.-4.G., but they appear more specifically in 
4.4. Land 4.6.2. 



262 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 

rejection for the following reason: a sufficient number of 
players 1 prefer, in their own interest, at least one of the dis- 
tributions of the solution (i.e. of Figure 51), and are con- 
vinced or ean be convinced 2 of the possibility of obtaining the 
advantages of that distribution. 

(29:B:b) If, however, one of the distributions of the solution is 

offered, then no such group of players can be found. 

We proceed to discuss the merits of this heuristic principle in a more 
exact way. 

29.2. Quantitative Discussion 

29.2.1. Suppose that 0i, 2 , 0s is a possible method of distribution 
between the players 1,2,3. I.e. 

ft + j8> + 0s = 0. 

Then, since by definition v((i))(= 1) is the amount that player i can get 
for himself (irrespective of what all others do), he will certainly block any 
distribution with ft < v((z)). We assume accordingly that 



We may permute the players 1,2,3 so that 

Pi ^ A g; ft. 

Now assume 2 < i- Then a fortiori # 3 < . Consequently the players 
2,3 will both prefer the last distribution of Figure 51, 8 where they both get 
the higher amount i. 4 Besides, it is clear that they can get the advantage of 
that distribution (irrespective of what the third player does), since the 
amounts i, i which it assigns to them do not exceed together v((2, 3)) = 1. 

If, on the other hand, /3 2 ^ i, then a fortiori 0i ^ . Since 8 ^ 1, 
this is possible only when /3i = 2 = i, 0a = 1, i.e. when we have the first 
distribution of Figure 51. (Cf. footnote 3 above.) 

1 Of course, in this case, two. 

1 What this "convincing" means was discussed in 4.4.3. Our discussion which 
follows will make it perfectly clear. 

3 Since we made an unspecified permutation of the players 1,2,3 the last distribution 
of Fig. 51 really stands for all three. 

4 Observe that each one of these two players profits by such a change separately and 
individually. It would not suffice to have only the totality (of these two) profit. Cf., 
e.g., the first distribution of Fig. 51 with the second; the players 1,3 as a totality would 
profit by the change from the former to the latter, and nevertheless the first distribution 
is just as good a constituent of the solution as any other. 

In this particular change, player 3 would actually profit (getting i instead of 1), 
and for player 1 the change is indifferent (getting | in both cases). Nevertheless player 1 
will not act unless further compensations are made and these can be disregarded in this 
connection. For a more careful discussion of this point, cf. the last part of this section. 



EXACT FORM OF THE GENERAL DEFINITIONS 263 

This establishes (29:B:a) at the end of 29.1.4. (29:B:b) loc. cit. is 
immediate: in each of the three distributions of Figure 51 there is, to be 
sure, one player who is desirous of improving his standing, 1 but since there is 
only one, he is not able to do so. Neither of his two possible partners gains 
anything by forsaking his present ally and joining the dissatisfied player: 
already each gets i, and they can get no more in any alternative distribution 
of Figure 51. 2 

29.2.2. This point may be clarified further by some heuristic elaboration. 

We see that the dissatisfied player finds no one who desires spontaneously 
to be his partner, and he can offer no positive inducement to anyone to 
join him; certainly none by offering to concede more than i from the proceeds 
of their future coalition. The reason for regarding such an offer as ineffec- 
tive can be expressed in two ways: on purely formal grounds this offer may 
be excluded because it corresponds to a distribution which is outside the 
scheme of Figure 51; the real subjective motive for which any prospective 
partner would consider it unwise 3 to accept a coalition under such conditions 
is most likely the fear of subsequent disadvantage, there may be further 
negotiations preceding the formation of a coalition, in which he would be 
found in a particularly vulnerable position. (Cf. the analysis in 22.1.2., 
22.1.3.) 

So there is no way for the dissatisfied player to overcome the indifference 
of the two possible partners. We stress: there is, on the side of the two 
possible partners no positive motive against a change into another distribu- 
tion of Figure 51, but just the indifference characteristic of certain types of 
stability. 4 

30. The Exact Form of the General Definitions 
30.1. The Definitions 

30.1.1. We return to the case of the zero-sum n-person game F with 
general n. Let the characteristic function of T be v(S). 

We proceed to give the decisive definitions. 

In accordance with the suggestions of the preceding paragraphs we 
mean by a distribution or imputation a set of n numbers i, , a with 
'the following properties 

(30:1) a, ^ v((0) for i = 1, - - , n, 

(30:2) a, = 0. 

i-l 

1 The one who gets 1. 

1 The reader may find it a good exercise to repeat this discussion with a general (not 
reduced) v(S), i.e. with general a, 6, c, and the quantities of 22.3.4. The result is the 
same; it cannot be otherwise, since our theory of strategic equivalence and reduction is 
correct. (Cf. footnote 3 on p. 260.) 

8 Or unsound, or unethical. 

4 At every change from one distribution of Fig. 51 to another, one player is definitely 
against, one definitely for it; and so the remaining player blocks the change by his 
indifference. 



264 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 

It may be convenient to view these systems !,-, as vectors in the 
n-dimensional linear space L n in the sense of 16.1 2.: 



A set S (i.e. a subset of / = 1, , n) is called effective for the imputa- 


tion a , if 

(30:3) "* * vO 81 )- 

iinS 

- r - 

An imputation a. dominates another imputation ft , in symbols 



if there exists a set S with the following properties: 
(30:4:a) S is not empty, 

(30:4:b) S is effective for a , 

(30:4:c) <* > ft for all i in S. 

A set V of imputations is a solution if it possesses the following properties : 

(30:5:a) No ft in V is dominated by an a in V, 

(30:5:b) Every ft not in V is dominated by some a in V. 

(30:5:a) and (30:5:b) can be stated as a single condition: 
(30:5:c) The elements of V are precisely those imputations which 



. _ 4 _ ^ 

are undominated by any element of V. 



(Cf. footnote 1 on p. 40.) 

30.1.2. The meaning of these definitions can, of course, be visualized 
when we recall the considerations of the preceding paragraphs and also of 
the earlier discussions of 4.4.3. 

To begin with, our distributions or imputations correspond to the more 
intuitive notions of the same name in the two places referred to. What we 
call an effective set is nothing but the players who "are convinced or can be 

convinced" of the possibility of obtaining what they are offered by a ; cf. 
again 4.4.3 and (29:B:a) in 29.1.4. The condition (30:4:c) in the definition 
of domination expresses that all these players have a positive motive for 

> > 

preferring a to ft . It is therefore apparent that we have defined domi- 
nation entirely in the spirit of 4.4.1., and of the preference described by 
(29:B:a) in 29.1.4. 

The definition of a solution agrees completely with that given in 4.5.3., 
as well as with (29:B:a), (29:B:b) in 29.1.4. 



EXACT FORM OF THE GENERAL DEFINITIONS 265 

30.2. Discussion and Recapitulation 

30.2.1. The motivation for all these definitions has been given at the 
places to which we referred in detail in the course of the last paragraph. 
We shall nevertheless re-emphasize some of their nlain features particu- 
larly the concept of a solution. 

We have already seen in 4.6. that our concept of a solution of a game 
corresponds precisely to that of a " standard of behavior" of everyday 
parlance. Our conditions (30:5:a), (30:5:b), which correspond to the 
conditions (4:A:a), (4:A:b) of 4.5.3., express just the kind of "inner sta- 
bility" which is expected of workable standards of behavior. This was 
elaborated further in 4.6. on a qualitative basis. We can now reformulate 
those ideas in a rigorous way, considering the exact character which the 
discussion has now assumed. The remarks we wish to make are these: 1 

30.2.2. 

(30:A:a) Consider a solution V. We have not excluded for an 



imputation ft in V the existence of an outside imputation a ' 

(not in V) with a ' H ft . 2 If such an a ' exists, the attitude 
of the players must be imagined like this: If the solution V 
(i.e. this system of imputations) is " accepted " by the players 1, 
, n, then it must impress upon their minds the idea that 

only the imputations ft in V are " sound" ways of distribution. 

An a ' not in V with a ' H ft , although preferable to an 
effective set of players, will fail to attract them, because it is 
"unsound." (Cf. our detailed discussion of the zero-sum three- 
person game, especially as to the reason for the aversion of each 
player to accept more than the determined amount in a coali- 
tion. Cf . the end of 29.2. and its references.) The view of the 

> 
" unsoundness " of a ' may also be supported by the existence 

> 

of an a in V with a H a ' (cf. (30:A:b) below). All these 

arguments are, of course, circular in a sense and again 
depend on the selection of V as a "standard of behavior," i.e. 
as a criterion of "soundness." But this sort of circularity is 
not unfamiliar in everyday considerations dealing with 
"soundness." 

ir The remarks (30:A:a)-(30:A:d) which follow are a more elaborate and precise 
presentation of the ideas of 4.6.2. Remark (30:A:e) bears the same relationship to 

4.6.3. 



1 Indeed, we shall see in (31 :M) of 31.2.3. that an imputation , for which never 
> 
a ' H , exists only in inessential games. 



266 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 

(30:A:b) If the players 1, , n have accepted the solution V as a 

" standard of behavior/ 1 then the ability to discredit with the 
help of V (i.e. of its elements) any imputation not in Vi is 
necessary in order to maintain their faith in V. Indeed, for 

every outside a ' (not in V) there must exist an a in V with 



a H a '. (This was our postulate (30:5:b).) 

(30:A:c) Finally there must be no inner contradiction in V> i.e. for 

a , ft in V, never a H ft . (This was our other postulate 
(30:5:a).) 

(30:A:d) Observe that if domination, i.e. the relation H , were transi- 

tive, then the requirements (30:A:b) and (30:A:c) (i.e. our 
postulates (30:5:a) and (30:5:b)) would exclude the rather 
delicate situation in (30:A:a). Specifically: In the situation of 

(30:A:a), ft belongs to V, a ' does not, and a ' *- ft . By 
(30:A:b) there exists an a in V so that a H a '. Now if 
domination were transitive we could conclude that a H ft , 

which contradicts (30:A:c) since a , ft both belong to V- 
(30:A:e) The above considerations make it even more clear that only 

V in its entirety is a solution and possesses any kind of stability 
but none of its elements individually. The circular char- 
acter stressed in (30:A:a) makes it plausible also that several 
solutions V may exist for the same game. I.e. several stable 
standards of behavior may exist for the same factual situation. 
Each of these would, of course, be stable and consistent in itself, 
but in conflict with all others. (Cf. also the end of 4.6.3. and 
the end of 4.7.) 

In many subsequent discussions we shall see that this multiplicity of 
solutions is, indeed, a very general phenomenon. 

30.3. The Concept of Saturation 

30.3.1. It seems appropriate to insert at this point some remarks of a 
more formalistic nature. So far we have paid attention mainly to the 
meaning and motivation of the concepts which we have introduced, but the 
notion of solution, as defined above, possesses some formal features which 
deserve attention. 

The formal logical considerations which follow will be of no imme- 
diate use, and we shall not dwell upon them extensively, continuing after- 
wards more in the vein of the preceding treatment. Nevertheless we deem 
that these remarks are useful here for a more complete understanding of the 
structure of our theory. Furthermore, the procedures to be used here will 
have an important technical application in an entirely different connection 
in 51.1.-51.4. 



EXACT FORM OF THE GENERAL DEFINITIONS 267 

30.3.2. Consider a domain (set) D for the elements x, y of which a certain 
relation x&y exists. The validity of (R between two elements x, y of D is 
expressed by the formula x&y. 1 (R is defined by a statement specif ying 
unambiguously for which pairs x, y of D, xfay is true, and for which it is not. 
If xGiy is equivalent to 2/(Rrc, then we say that xfay is symmetric. For any 
relation (R we can define a new relation (R 5 by specifying x(R 8 y to mean the 
conjunction of xfay and yfax. Clearly (R 5 is always symmetric and coincides 
with (R if and only if (R is symmetric. We call (R a the symmetrized form of (R. 2 

We now define: 

(30:B:a) A subset A of D is (Si-satisfactory if and only if x(Ri/ holds 

for all x, y of A. 
(30:B:b) A subset A of D and an element y of D are (Si-compatible 

if and only if x(Ry holds for all x ot A. 

From these one concludes immediately: 

(30:C:a) A subset A of D is (Si-satisfactory if and only if this is true: 

The y which are (R-compatible with A form a superset of A. 

We define next: 

(30:C:b) A subset A of D is (Si-saturated if and only if this is true: 

The y which are (R-compatible with A form precisely the set A . 

Thus the requirement which must be added to (30 :C :a) in order to secure 
(30:C:b) is this: 

(30 :D) If y is not in A, then it is not (R-compatible with A; i.e. 

there exists an x in A such that not x(Ry. 

Consequently (R-saturation may be equivalently defined by (30:B:a) and 
(30:D). 

30.3.3. Before we investigate these concepts any further, we give some 
examples. The verification of the assertions made in them is easy and will 
be left to the reader. 

First: Let D be any set and x&y the relation x = y. Then (R-satis- 
factoriness of A means that A is either empty or a one-element set, while 
(R-saturation of A means that A is a one-element set. 

Second: Let D be a set of real numbers and x(Siy the relation x ^ t/. 3 
Then (R-satisfactoriness of A means the same thing as above, 4 while (R-sat- 
uration of A means that A is a one-element set, consisting of the greatest 
element of D. Thus there exists no such A if D has no greatest element 

1 It is sometimes more convenient to use a formula of the form (R(or, y), but for our 
purposes x&y is preferable. 

2 Some examples: Let D consist of ail real numbers. The relations x y and x 9* y 
are symmetric. None of the four relations x y, x ^ y, x < y, x > y \R symmetric. 
The symmetrized form of the two former is x y (conjunction of x ^ y and x y), 
the symmetrized form of the two latter is an absurdity (conjunction of x < y and x > y). 

8 D could be any other set in which such a relation is defined, cf . the second example in 
65.4.1. 

4 Cf . footnote 1 on p. 268. 



268 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 

(e.g. for the set of all real numbers) and A is unique if D has a greatest 
element (e.g. when it is finite). 

Third : Let D be the plane and xfay express that the points #, y have the 
same height (ordinate). Then (R-satisfactoriness of A means that all 
points of A have the same height, i.e. lie on one parallel to the axis of 
abscissae. (R-saturation means that A is precisely a line parallel to the axis 
of abscissae. 

Fourth: Let D be the set of all imputations, and x<S(.y the negation of the 
domination x H y. Then comparison of our (30:B:a), (30:D) with (30:5:a), 
(30:5:b) in 30.1.1., or equally of (30:C:b) with (30:5:c) id. shows: (R-satura- 
tion of A means that A is a solution. 

30*3.4. One look at the condition (30:B:a) suffices to see that satis- 
factoriness for the relation x<S(y is the same as for the relation yfax and so 
also for their conjunction x(& 8 y. In other words: (R-satisfactoriness is the 
same thing as (R a -satisfactoriness. 

Thus satisfactoriness is a concept which need be studied only on sym- 
metric relations. 

This is due to the x, y symmetric form of the definitory condition (30 :B :a) . 
The equivalent condition (30:C:a) does not exhibit this symmetry, but of 
course this does not invalidate the proof. 

Now the definitory condition (30:C:b) for (R-saturation is very similar 
in structure to (30:C:a). It is equally asymmetric. However, while 
(30:C:a) possesses an equivalent symmetric form (30:B:a), this is not the 
case for (30:C:b). The corresponding equivalent form for (30:C:b) is, as 
we know, the conjunction of (30:B:a) and (30 :D) and (30 :D) is not at all 
symmetric. I.e. (30 :D) is essentially altered if x(Rt/ is replaced by y(Rx. 
So we see: 

(30 :E) While (R-satisfactoriness in unaffected by the replacement of 

(R by (R 5 , it does not appear that this is the case for (R-saturation. 

Condition (30:B:a) (amounting to (R-satisfactoriness) is the same for 
(R and (R 5 . Condition (30 :D) for (R s is implied by the same for (R since (R 5 
implies (R. So we see: 

(30 :F) (R s -saturation is implied by (R-saturation. 

The difference between these two types of saturation referred to above 
is a real one: it is easy to give an explicit example of a set which is (R s -sat- 
urated without being (R-saturated. 1 

Thus the study of saturation cannot be restricted to symmetric relations. 

30.3.5. For symmetric relations (R the nature of saturation is simple 
enough. In order to avoid extraneous complications we assume for this 
section that x(Rx is always true. 2 

1 E.g.: The first two examples of 30.3.3. are in the relation of (R 5 and (R to each other 
(cf. footnote 2 on p. 267); their concepts of satisfactoriness are identical, but those of 
saturation differ. 

* This is clearly the case for our decisive example of 30.3.3.: x&y the negation of * H y 
since never x H x. 



EXACT FORM OF THE GENERAL DEFINITIONS 269 

Now we prove: 

(30 :G) Let (R be symmetric. Then the (R-saturation of A is equiv- 

alent to its being maximal (R-satisfactory. I.e. it is equivalent 
to: A is (R-satisfactory, but no proper superset of A is. 

Proof: (R-saturation means (R-satisfactoriness (i.e. condition (30:B:a)) 
together with condition (30 :D). So we need only prove: If A is (R-satis- 
factory, then (30 :D) is equivalent to the non-(R-satisfactoriness of all proper 
supersets of A. 

Sufficiency of (30 :D): If B D A is (R-satisfactory, then any y in B, but 
not in A, violates (30 :D). 1 

Necessity of (30:D): Consider a y which violates (30:D). Then 

B = A u (y) D A. 

Now B is (R-satisfactory, i.e. for #', y' in B, always x'<S(y'. Indeed, when 
x', y' are both in A, this follows from the (R-satisfactoriness of A. If x', y' 
are both = y, we are merely asserting y&y. If one of z', y' is in A, and the 
other = y, then the symmetry of (R allows us to assume x f in A, y' = y. 
Now our assertion coincides with the negation of (30 :D). 
If (R is not symmetric, we can only assert this: 

(30 :H) (R-saturation of A implies its being maximal (R-satisfactory. 

Proof: Maximal (R-satisfactoriness is the same as maximal (R-satisfactori- 
ness, cf. (30 :E). As (R 5 is symmetric, this amounts to (R saturation by 
(30 :G). And this is a consequence of (R-saturation by (30 :F). 

The meaning of the result concerning a symmetric (R is the following: 
Starting with any (R-satisfactory set, this set must be increased as long as 
possible, i.e. until any further increase would involve the loss of (R-satis- 
factoriness. In this way in fine a maximal (R-satisfactory set is obtained, 
i.e. an (R-saturated one by (30 :G). 2 This argument secures not only 
the existence of (R-saturated sets, but it also permits us to infer that every 
(R-satisfactory set can be extended to an (R-saturated one. 

1 Note that none of the extra restrictions on <H has been used so far. 
8 This process of exhaustion is elementary i.e. it is over after a finite number of 
steps when D is finite. 

However, since the set of all imputations is usually infinite, the case of an infinite D 
is important. When D is infinite, it is still heuristically plausible that the process of 
exhaustion referred to can be carried out by making an infinite number of steps. This 
process, known as transfinite induction, has been the object of extensive set-theoretical 
studies. It can be performed in a rigorous way which is dependent upon the so-called 
axiom of choice. 

The reader who is interested will find literature in F. Hausdorff, footnote 1, on p. 61. 
Cf. also E. ZermelOj Beweis dass jede Menge wohlgeordnet werden kann. Math. Ann. 
Vol. 59 (1904) p. 514ff. and Math. Ann. Vol. 65 (1908) p. 107ff. 

These matters carry far from our subject and are not strictly necessary for our 
purposes. We do not therefore dwell further upon them. 



270 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 

It should be noted that every subset of an (R-saturated set is necessarily 
(R-satisf actory . l The above assertion means therefore that the converse 
statement is also true. 

30.3.6. It would be very convenient if the existence of solutions in our 
theory could be established by such methods. The prima facie evidence, 
however, is against this: the relation which we must use, a;(Ry negation of 
the domination x s- 1 y, cf. 30.3.3. is clearly asymmetrical. Hence we can- 
not apply (30 :G), but only (30 :H): maximal satisfactoriness is only neces- 
sary, but may not be sufficient for saturation, i.e. for being a solution. 

That this difficulty is really deep seated can be seen as follows : If we could 
replace the above (R by a symmetric one, this could not only be used to prove 
the existence of solutions, but it would also prove in the same operation 
the possibility of extending any (R-satisfactory set of imputations to a solution 
(cf. above). Now it is probable that every game possesses a solution, but 
we shall see that there exist games in which certain satisfactory sets are 
subsets of no solutions. 2 Thus the device of replacing (R by something 
symmetric cannot work because this would be equally instrumental in prov- 
ing the first assertion, which is presumably true, and the second one, which 
is certainly not true. 8 

The reader may feel that this discussion is futile, since the relation x&y 
which we must use ("not x H y") is de facto asymmetric. From a technical 
point of view, however, it is conceivable that another relation x$y may be 
found with the following properties: x$y is not equivalent to x&y; indeed, 
is symmetric, while (R is not, but-saturation is equivalent to (R-saturation. 
In this case (R-saturated sets would have to exist because they are the 
-saturated ones, and the g-satisfactory but not necessarily the (R-satis- 
factory sets would always be extensible to g-saturated, i.e. (R-saturated 
ones. 4 This program of attack on the existence problem of solutions is not 
as arbitrary as it may seem. Indeed, we shall see later a similar problem 
which is solved in precisely this way (cf. 51.4.3.). All this is, however, for 
the time being just a hope and a possibility. 

30.3.7. In the last section we considered the question whether every 
(R-satisfactory set is a subset of an (R-saturated set. We noted that for 
the relation x&y which we must use ("not x H y" asymmetric) the answer 
is in the negative. A brief comment upon this fact seems to be worth while. 

If the answer had been in the affirmative it would have meant that any 
set fulfilling (30:B:a) can be extended to one fulfilling (30:B:a) and (30 :D); 
or, in the notations of 30.1.1., that any set of imputations fulfilling (30:5:a) 
can be extended to one fulfilling (30:5:a) and (30:5:b). 

1 Clearly property (30:B:a) is not lost when passing to a subset. 

1 Cf. footnote 2 on p. 285. 

8 This is a rather useful principle of the technical side of mathematics. The inappro- 
priateness of a method can be inferred from the fact that if it were workable at all it 
would prove too much. 

4 The point is that (R- and S-saturation are assumed to be equivalent to each other, 
but <H- and S-satisfactoriness are not expected to be equivalent. 



EXACT FORM OF THE GENERAL DEFINITIONS 271 

It is instructive to restate this in the terminology of 4.6.2. Then the 
statement becomes: Any standard of behavior which is free from inner 
contradiction can be extended to one which is stable, i.e. not only free 
from inner contradictions, but also able to upset all imputations outside 
of it. 

The observation in 30.3.6., according to which the above is not true in 
general, is of some significance: in order that a set of rules of behavior 
should be the nucleus (i.e. a subset) of a stable standard of behavior, it 
may have to possess deeper structural properties than mere freedom from 
inner contradictions. 1 

30.4. Three Immediate Objectives 

30.4.1. We have formulated the characteristics of a solution of an unre- 
stricted zero-sum n-person game and can therefore begin the systematic 
investigation of the properties of this concept. In conjunction with the 
early stages of this investigation it seems appropriate to carry out three 
special enquiries. These deal with the following special cases : 

First: Throughout the discussions of 4., the idea recurred that the unso- 
phisticated concept of a solution would be that of an imputation, i.e. in 
our present terminology, of a one-element set V- In 4.4.2. we saw specifi- 
cally that this would amount to finding a "first" element with respect to 
domination. We saw in the subsequent parts of 4., as well as in our exact 
discussions of 30.2., that it is mainly the intransitivity of our concept of 
domination which defeats this endeavor and forces us to introduce sets of 
imputations V as solutions. 

It is, therefore, of interest now that we are in a position to do it to 
give an exact answer to the following question: For which games do one- 
element solutions V exist? What else can be said about the solutions of 
such games? 

Second: The postulates of 30.1.1. were extracted from our experiences 
with the zero-sum three-person game, in its essential case. It is, therefore, 
of interest to reconsider this case in the light of the present, exact theory. 
Of course, we know indeed this was a guiding principle throughout our 
discussions that the solution which we obtained by the preliminary 
methods of 22., 23., are solutions in the sense of our present postulates 
too. Nevertheless it is desirable to verify this explicitly. The real point, 
however, is to ascertain whether the present postulates do not ascribe to 
those games further solutions as well. (We have already seen that it is not 
inconceivable that there should exist several solutions for the same game.) 

We shall therefore determine all solutions for the essential zero-sum 
three-person games with results which are rather surprising, but, as we 
shall see, not unreasonable. 

1 If the relation S referred to at the end of 30.3.6. could be found, then this $ and 
not (R would disclose which standards of behavior are such nuclei (i.e. subsets): the 
S-satisfactory ones. 

Cf. the similar situation in 51.4., where the corresponding operation is performed 
successfully. 



272 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 

30.4.2. These two items exhaust actually all zero-sum games with n ^ 3. 
We observed in the first remark of 27.5.2. that for n = 1, 2, these games are 
inessential; so this, together with the inessential and the essential cases of 
n = 3, takes care of everything in n ^ 3. 

When this program is fulfilled we are left with the games n ^ 4 and 
we know already that difficulties of a new kind begin with them (cf. the 
allusions of footnote 1, p. 250, and the end of 27.5.3.). 

30.4.3. Third: We introduced in 27.1. the concept of strategic equiva- 
lence. It appeared plausible that this relationship acts as its name 
expresses: two games which are linked by it offer the same strategical 
possibilities and inducements to form coalitions, etc. Now that we have 
put the concept of a solution on an exact basis, this heuristic expectation 
demands a rigorous proof. 

These three questions will be answered in (31 :P) in 31.2.3. ; in 32.2. ; and 
in (31:Q) in 31.3.3., respectively. 

31. First Consequences 
31.1. Convexity, Flatness, and Some Criteria for Domination 

31.1.1. This section is devoted to proving various auxiliary results con- 
cerning solutions, and the other concepts which surround them, like ines- 
sentiality, essentiality, domination, effectivity. Since we have now put 
all these notions on an exact basis, the possibility as well as the obligation 
arises to be absolutely rigorous in establishing their properties. Some of 
the deductions which follow may seem pedantic, and it may appear occasion- 
ally that a verbal explanation could have replaced the mathematical proof. 
Such an approach, however, would be possible for only part of the results 
of this section and, taking everything into account, the best plan seems to 
be to go about the whole matter systematically with full mathematical rigor. 

Some principles which play a considerable part in finding solutions are 
(31 :A), (31 :B), (31 :C), (31 :F), (31 :G), (31 :H), which for certain coalitions 
decide a priori that they must always, or never, be taken into consideration. 
It seemed appropriate to accompany these principles with verbal explana- 
tions (in the sense indicated above) in addition to thqir formal proofs. 

The other results possess varying interest of their own in different direc- 
tions. Together they give a first orientation of the circumstances which 
surround our newly won concepts. The answers to the first and third ques- 
tions in 30.4. are given in (31 :P) and (31 :Q). Another question which 
arose previously is settled in (31 :M). 

31.1.2. Consider two imputations a , ft and assume that it has become 

necessary to decide whether a H ft or not. This amounts to deciding 
whether or not there exists a set S with the properties (30:4:a)-(30:4:c) in 
30.1.1. One of these, (30:4:c) is 

> ft for all i in S. 



FIRST CONSEQUENCES 273 

We call this the main condition. The two others, (30:4:a), (30:4:b), are 
the preliminary conditions. 

Now one of the major technical difficulties in handling this concept of 
domination i.e. in finding solutions V in the sense of 30.1.1. is the presence 
of these preliminary conditions. It is highly desirable to be able, so to say, 
to short circuit them, i.e. to discover criteria under which they are certainly 
satisfied, and others under which they are certainly not satisfied. In look- 
ing for criteria of the latter type, it is by no means necessary that they should 


involve non-fulfillment of the preliminary conditions for all imputations a 

it suffices if they involve it for all those imputations a which fulfill the main 


condition for some other imputation . (Cf. the proofs of (31 :A) or (31 :F), 

where exactly this is utilized.) 

We are interested in criteria of this nature in connection with the ques- 
tion of determining whether a given set V of imputations is a solution or not; 

i.e. whether it fulfills the conditions (30:5:a), (30:5:b) the condition 


(30:5:c) in 30.1.1. This amounts to determining which imputations 

are dominated by elements of V- 

Criteria which dispose of the preliminary conditions summarily, in the 
situation described above, are most desirable if they contain no reference 

at all to ^V' 2 i.e. if they refer to 8 alone. (Cf. (31 :F), (31 :G), (31 :H).) But 


even criteria which involve a may be desirable. (Cf. (31 :A).) We shall 

consider even a criterion which deals with S and a by referring to the 

* 
behavior of another a '. (Of course, both in V. Cf. (31 :B).) 

In order to cover all these possibilities, we introduce the following 
terminology: 

We consider proofs which aim at the determination of all imputations 

/3 , which are dominated by elements of a given set of imputations V- We 

are thus concerned with the relations a H ft (a in V), and the question 
whether a certain set S meets our preliminary requirements for such a rela- 
tion. We call S certainly necessary if we know (owing to the fulfillment by S 

of some appropriate criterion) that S and a always meet the preliminary 
conditions. We call a set S certainly unnecessary, if we know (again owing 
to the fulfillment by S of some appropriate criterion, but which may now 

involve other things too, cf. above) that the possibility that S and a meet 

1 The point being that in our original definition of a ** ft the preliminary conditions 



refer to 5 and to (but not to ft ). Specifically: (30:4:b) does. 


1 The hypothetical element of V, which should dominate ft . 



274 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 

the preliminary conditions can be disregarded (because this never happens, 
or for any other reason. Cf. also the qualifications made above). 

These considerations may seem complicated, but they express a quite 
natural technical standpoint. 1 

We shall now give certain criteria of the certainly necessary and of the 
certainly unnecessary characters. After each criterion we shall give a 
verbal explanation of its content, which, it is hoped, will make our technique 
clearer to the reader. 

31.1.3. First, three elementary criteria: 

(31 :A) S is certainly unnecessary for a given a (in V) if there exists 

an t in S with a, = v((i)). 

Explanation: A coalition need never be considered if it does not promise 
to every participant (individually) definitely more than he can get for 
himself. 

Proof: If a fulfills the main condition for some imputation, then on > ft. 

Since ft is an imputation, so ft ^ v((i)). Hence a< > v((i)). This con- 
tradicts cti = v((i)). 

(31 :B) S is certainly unnecessary for a given a (in V) if it is certainly 

necessary (and being considered) for another a ' (in V), such that 
(31:1) ; ^ a, for all i in S. 

Explanation: A coalition need not be considered if another one, which 
has the same participants and promises every one (individually) at least 
as much, is certain to receive consideration. 

Proof: Let a and ft fulfill the main condition: a, > ft f or alii in S. Then 

a ' and ft fulfill it also, by (31 :1), a( > ft for all i in S. Since S and a' are 

1 For the reader who is familiar with formal logic we observe the following: 

The attributes "certainly necessary" and " certainly unnecessary" are of a logical 
nature. They are characterized by our ability to show (by any means whatever) that a 
certain logical omission will invalidate no proof (of a certain kind). Specifically: Let a 

> > 

proof be concerned with the domination of a ft by an element a of V. Assume that this 

> > 

domination a H occurring with the help of the set S ( a in V) be under consideration. 

Then this proof remains correct if we treat S and a (when they possess the attribute in 
question) as if they always (or never) fulfilled the preliminary conditions, without our 
actually investigating these conditions. In the mathematical proofs which we shall 
carry out, this procedure will be applied frequently. 

It can even happen that the same S will turn out (by the use of two different criteria) 



to be both certainly necessary and certainly unnecessary (for the same a , e.g. for all of 
them). This means merely that neither of the two omissions mentioned above spoils 

* 

any proof. This can happen, for instance, when a fulfills the main condition for no 
imputation. (An example is obtained by combining (3 1 :F) and (3 1 :G) in the case described 
in (31 ::b). Another is pointed out in footnote 1 on p. 310, and in footnote 1 on p. 431.) 



FIRST CONSEQUENCES 275 

being considered, they thus establish that ft is dominated by an element of 
Vi and it is unnecessary to consider S and a . 

(31:C) S is certainly unnecessary if another set TzS is certainly 

necessary (and is being considered). 

Explanation: A coalition need not be considered if a part of it is already 
certain to receive consideration. 



Proof: Let a (in V) and ft fulfill the main condition for S\ then they will 

obviously fulfill it a fortiori for T S. Since T and a are being considered, 
they thus establish that ft is dominated by an element of V and it is unneces- 
sary to consider S and a . 

31.1.4. We now introduce some further criteria, and on a somewhat 
broader basis than immediately needed. For this purpose we begin with 
the following consideration: 

For an arbitrary set S = (k\, , k p ) apply (25:5) in 25.4.1., with 
Si = (ti), , S p = (fc p ). Then 

v(S) ^ v((*0) + ' ' ' + v((fcp)) 
obtains, i.e. 

(31:2) v(S) g; % v((fc)). 

kinS 

The excess of the left-hand side of (31 :2) over the right hand side expresses 
the total advantage (for all participants together) inherent in the formation 
of the coalition S. We call this the convexity of S. If this advantage 
vanishes, i.e. if 

(31:3) vGS) = % v((fc)), 

kin 3 

then we call S flat. 

The following observations are immediate: 

(31 :D) The following sets are always flat: 

(31 :D :a) The empty set, 

(3 1 :D :b) Every one-element set, 

(31 :D:c) Every subset of a flat set. 

(31 :E) Any one of the following assertions is equivalent to the in- 

essentiality of the game: 

(31:E:a) / = (!, , n) is flat, 

(31 :E:b) There exists an S such that both S and S are flat, 

(31:E:c) Every 8 is flat. 

Proof: Ad (31:D:a), (31:D:b): For these sets (31:3) is obvious. 



276 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 

Ad (31 :D :c) : Assume SsT,T flat. Put R = T - S. Then by (31 :2) 
(31:4) v(5) 



k in S 

(31:5) v(ft) X v((fc)). 

tinR 

Since T is flat, so by (30:3) 

(31:6) v(T) - I v((*)). 

*inT 

As S n ft = 0, S u ft = T; therefore 

v(S) + v() ^ v(T), 



* in S * in R kinT 

Hence (31 :6) implies 

(31:7) v(S)+v()3 v((*))+ 

*inS fcinfl 

Now comparison of (31:4), (31:5) and (31:7) shows that we must have 
equality in all of them. But equality in (31:4) expresses just the flatness 
of S. 

Ad (31:E:a): The assertion coincides with (27 :B) in 27.4.1. 

Ad (31:E:c): The assertion coincides with (27 :C) :a 27.4.2. 

Ad (31:E:b): For an inessential game this is true for any S owing to 
(31 :E:c). Conversely, if this is true for (at least one) S, then 

v(5) = v((*)), v(-S) = S v((*)) f 

kin S k not in S 

hence by addition (use (25:3:b) in 25.3.1.), 

= t v((*)) f 
/fe-i 

i.e. the game is inessential by (31:E:a) or by (27 :B) in 27.4.1. 
31.1.6. We are now in a position to prove: 

(31:F) S is certainly unnecessary if it is flat. 

Explanation: A coalition need not be considered if the game allows no 
total advantage (for all its participants together) over what they would get 
for themselves as independent players. 1 

1 Observe that this is related to (31 : A), but not at all identical with it ! Indeed : (31 : A) 
deals with the a t , i.e. with the promises made to each participant individually. (31:F) 
deals with v(*S) (which determines flatness), i.e. with the possibilities of the game for all 
participants together. But both criteria correlate these with the v((i)), i.e. with what 
each player individually can get for himself. 



FIRST CONSEQUENCES 277 

> > 

Proof: If a ^ ft with the help of this S'then we have: Necessarily 

S 5* . cti> fa for all i in S and fa ^ v((i)), hence on > v((i)). So 

2) < > v((t)). As S is flat, this means J) <* > v(/S). But S must 

t in 3 t in 5 i in S 

be effective, <* * v(fi>), which is a contradiction. 

UnS 

(31:G) S is certainly necessary if S is flat and 8 ^ 0. 

Explanation: A coalition must be considered if it (is not empty and) 

opposes one of the kind described in (31 :F). 

> 
Proof: The preliminary conditions are fulfilled for all imputations a . 

Ad (30:4:a): S ^ Q was postulated. 

Ad (30:4:b): Always ^ v((t)), so ^ v((i)). Since 

t not in 3 t not in 3 

n 

5) ; = 0, the left-hand side is equal to ^ en. Since S is flat, the 



t-l 

right-hand side is equal to v( S), i.e. (use (25:3:b) in 25.3.1.) to v(S). 
So - % a. ^ -vGS), a< g v(S), i.e. S is effective. 

t in S t in S 

From (31:F), (31:G) we obtain by specialization: 

(31:H) A p-element set is certainly necessary if p = n 1, and 

certainly unnecessary if p = 0, 1, n. 

Explanation : A coalition must be considered if it has only one opponent. 
A coalition need not be considered, if it is empty or consists of one player 
only (!), or if it has no opponents. 

Proof: p = n 1: S has only one element, hence it is flat by (31:D) 
above. The assertion now follows from (31:G). 

p = 0, 1: Immediate by (31 :D) and (31 :F). 

p = n: In this case necessarily >S = / = (l,*--,n) rendering the 
main condition unfulfillable. Indeed, that now requires a< > ft for all 

n n _ ^ _ ^ 

i = 1, , n, hence a > ft. But as a , are imputations, both 

t-i t-i 
sides vanish, and this is a contradiction. 

Thus those p for which the necessity of S is in doubt, are restricted to 
p ?* 0, 1, n 1, n, i.e. to the interval 

(31:8) 2 g p g n - 2. 

This interval plays a role only when n ^ 4. The situation discussed is 
similar to that at the end of 27.5.2. and in 27.5.3., and the case n = 3 
appears once more as one of particular simplicity. 

31.2. The System of All Imputations. One -element Solutions 
31.2.1. We now discuss the structure of the system of all imputations. 
(31 :1) For an inessential game there exists precisely one imputation: 



278 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 

(31:9) a = {i, -,), <* = v((i)) for t = 1, , n. 

For an essential game there exist infinitely many imputations 
an (n l)-dimensional continuum but (31:9) is not one of 
them. 

Proof: Consider an imputation 

7 = {01, - ,/M, 

and put 

ft = v((0) + * for i = 1, , n. 

Then the characteristic conditions (30:1), (30:2) of 30.1.1. become 
(31:10) i ^ for i = 1, , n. 

(31:11) - - v ((*))- 

i-i *-i 

n 

If T is inessential, then (27:B) in 27.4.1. gives - v((i)) = 0; so 

t'-i 

(31:10), (31:11) amount to ci = = * n = 0, i.e. (31:9) is the unique 
imputation. 

n 

If T is essential, the (27 :B) in 27.4.1. gives - v((t)) > 0, so (31:10), 

t-i 
(31 :11) possess infinitely many solutions, which form an (n l)-dimensional 

continuum; 1 so the same is true for the imputations ft . But the a. of (31 :9) 
is not one of them, because ei = = e n = now violate (31:11). 
An immediate consequence: 

(31 :J) A solution V is never empty. 

Proof: I.e. the empty set is not a solution. Indeed: Consider any 
imputation ft , there exists at least one by (31 :1). ft is not in and no 

a in has a H ft . So violates (30:5:b) in 30.1. 1. 2 

31.2.2. We have pointed out before that the simultaneous validity of 

(31:12) ~2 *- 7, 7 ** "^ 

is by no means impossible. 3 However: 

(31:K) Never a H a. 

1 There is only one equation: (31:11). 

1 This argument may seem pedantic ; but if the conditions for the imputations con- 
flicted (i.e. without (31:1)), then V Q would be a solution. 

3 The sets S of these two dominations would have to be disjunct. By (31 :H) these 
S must have ^ 2 elements each. Hence (31 :12) can occur only when n ^ 4. 

By a more detailed consideration even n 4 can be excluded; but for every n 5 
(31:12) is really possible. 



FIRST CONSEQUENCES 279 

Proof: (30:4:a), (30:4:c) in 30.1.1. conflict for to = ~p. 

(31:L) Given an essential game and an imputation a, there exists 

an imputation ft such that ft H a but not a H ft. 1 
Proof: Put 

a = {,, , }. 
Consider the equation 

(31:13) <* = V ((0). 

Since the game is essential, (31:1) excludes the proposition that (31:13) be 

valid for all i = 1, , n. Let (31:13) fail, say forf = i . Since a is an 
imputation, so a S v((i )), hence the failure of (31:13) me&ns a o > v((i )), 
i.e. 

(31:14) <. = v((i )) + e, a > 0. 

Now define a vector 



by 

ft o = a io - * = v((i )), 

ft = a H r for i ^ t' . 

n 1 

n n 

These equations make it clear that ft ^ v((i)) 2 and that ft = ^ a = O. 8 

i-l -l 

So is an imputation along with a . 

We now prove the two assertions concerning a , ft . 

ft H a : We have ft > a for all i ^ io, i.e. for all i in the set S = (I'D) . 

> 
This set has n 1 elements and it fulfills the main condition (for ft , a ), 


hence (31 :H) gives H a . 

Not a H ft : Assume that a H . Then a set S fulfilling the main con- 
dition must exist, which is not excluded by (31 :H). So S must have 
g: 2 elements. So an i ^ i'o in S must exist. The former implies ft > a 

> 

1 Hence a ?* . 
1 For t - to, we have actually 0, v((*' )). For i 5* i , we have 0, > a v((i)). 

n n 

3 X ft "* 2 a * k ecause the difference of ft and a. is c for one value of i (i t* ) and 
-i t-i 

for n 1 values of i (all i ** io). 



n - 



280 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 

(by the construction of ft ) ; the latter implies a > ft (owing to the main 
condition) and this is a contradiction. 

31.2.3. We can draw the conclusions in which we were primarily inter- 
ested: 

- 

(31:M) An imputation a , for which never a ' H a , exists if and 

only if the game is inessential. 1 

Proof: Sufficiency: If the game is inessential, then it possesses by (31:1) 
precisely one imputation a , and this has the desired property by (31:K). 

Necessity: If the game is essential, and a. is an imputation, then a ' = 
of (31 :L) gives a' = ft H a. 

(31 :N) A game which possesses a one-element solution 2 is necessarily 

inessential. 

Proof: Denote the one-element solution in question by V = ( a ). This 
V must satisfy (30:5:b) in 30.1.1. This means under our present circum- 
stances: Every ft other than a is dominated by a. I.e.: 

> > > 

ft j a implies a H ft . 

Now if the game is essential, then (31 :L) provides a ft which violates this 
condition. 

(31 :0) An inessential game possesses precisely one solution V. This 

is the one-element set V = ( a ) with the a of (31 :1). 

Proof: By (31:1) there exists precisely one imputation, the a of (31:1). 
A solution V cannot be empty by (31 :J); hence the only possibility is 

V = ( a ). Now V = ( a ) is indeed a solution, i.e. it fulfills (30:5 :a), (30:5:b) 

in 30.1.1. : the former by (31 :K), the latter because a is the only imputation 
by (31:1). 

We can now answer completely the first question of 30.4.1.: 

(31 :P) A game possesses a one-element solution (cf . footnote 2 above) 

if and only if it is inessential; and then it possesses no other 
solutions. 

Proof: This is just a combination of the results of (31 :N) and (31:0). 

1 Cf. the considerations of (30:A:a) in 30.2.2., and particularly footnote 2 on p. 265. 

1 We do not exclude the possibility that this game may possess other solutions as well, 
which may or may not be one-element sets. Actually this never happens (under our 
present hypothesis), as the combination of the result of (31:N) with that of (31 :0) or 
the result of (31 :P) shows. But the present consideration is independent of all this. 



FIRST CONSEQUENCES 281 

31.3. The Isomorphism Which Corresponds to Strategic Equivalence 

31.3.1. Consider two games F and F' with the characteristic functions 
v(S) and v'(S) which are strategically equivalent in the sense of 27.1. 
We propose to prove that they are really equivalent from the point of view 
of the concepts defined in 30.1.1. This will be done by establishing an 
isomorphic correspondence between the entities which form the substratum 
of the definitions of 30.1.1., i.e. the imputations. That is, we wish to 
establish a one-to-one correspondence, between the imputations of F and 
those of F', which is isomorphic with respect to those concepts, i.e. which 
carries effective sets, domination, and solutions for F into those for F'. 

The considerations are merely an exact elaboration of the heuristic 
indications of 27.1.1., hence the reader may find them unnecessary. How- 
ever, they give quite an instructive instance of an " isomorphism proof, " 
and, besides, our previous remarks on the relationship of verbal and of 
exact proofs may be applied again. 

31.3.2. Let the strategic equivalence be given by a i, , aj in the sense 

of (27:1), (27:2) in 27.1.1. Consider all imputations a = \a\ 9 , a n ) 

of F and all imputations a ' = {a' lf , a^jofF'. We look for a one-to- 
one correspondence 

(31:15) ~^<=~^' 

with the specified properties. 

What (31:15) ought to be is easily guessed from the motivation at the 
beginning of 27.1.1. We described there the passage from F to F' by adding 
to the game a fixed payment of a to the player k. Applying this principle 
to the imputations means 

(31:16) a' k = a k + a k for * = !,-, n. 1 

Accordingly we define the correspondence (31:15) by the equations (31:16). 

31.3.3. We now verify the asserted properties of (31:15), (31:16). 

The imputations of F are mapped on the imputations of F': This means 
by (30:1), (30:2) in 30.1.1., that 

(31:17) a ^ v((t)) for i - 1, - - . n. 

n 

(31:18) , = 0, 

'-! 

go over into 

(31:17*) a( ^ v'((i)) for i = 1, , n, 

(31:18*) 2:-0. 

t-1 



l lf we introduce the (fixed) vector a - lJ, , i| then (31:16) may be 

> > 

written vectorially a ' a + a . I.e. it is a translation (by a ) in the vector space 
of the imputations. 



282 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 

This is so for (31:17), (31:17*) because v'((t)) = v((t)) + ? (by (27:2) in 

n 

27.1.1.), and for (31:18), (31:18*) because J) a? = (by (27:1) id.). 

t-1 

Effectivity for F goes over into effectivity for F': This means by (30:3) 
in 30. 1.1., that 

2) ^ v(S) 
goes over into 

2 J s vw. 



tin 



This becomes evident by comparison of (31:16) with (27:2). 

Domination for F goes over into domination for F' : This means the same 
thing for (30:4:a)-(30:4:c) in 30.1.1. (30:4:a) is trivial; (30:4:b) is effec- 
tivity, which we settled: (30:4:c) asserts that a > ft goes over into a t - > 0J 
which is obvious. The solutions of F are mapped on the solutions of F': 
This means the same for (30:5:a), (30:5:b) (or (30:5:c)) in 30.1.1. These 
conditions involve only domination, which we settled. 

We restate these results: 

(31:Q) If two zero-sum games F and F' are strategically equivalent, 

then there exists an isomorphism between their imputations 
i.e. a one-to-one mapping of those of F on those of F' which 
leaves the concepts defined in 30.1.1. invariant. 

32. Determination of all Solutions 
of the Essential Zero-sum Three-person Game 

$2.1. Formulation of the Mathematical Problem. The Graphical Method 

32.1.1. We now turn to the second problem formulated in 30.4.1.: 
The determination of all solutions for the essential zero-sum three-person 
games. 

We know that we may consider this game in the reduced form and that 
we can choose 7 = I. 1 The characteristic function in this case is completely 
determined as we have discussed before: 2 



(32:1) v(fl) = 





-1 
1 



when S has 




An imputation is a vector 



elements. 



a = 



1 Cf. the discussion at the beginning of 29.1., or the references there given: the end of 
27.1. and the second remark in 27.3. 

1 Cf. the discussion at the beginning of 20.1., or the second case of 27.5. 



ALL SOLUTIONS OF THE THREE-PERSON GAME 283 

whose three components must fulfill (30:1), (30:2) in 30.1.1.* These con- 
ditions now become (considering (30:1)) 

(32:2) ai -1, a , ^ -1, 8 -1, 

(32:3) on + a* + 3 = 0. 

We know, from (31:1) in 31.2.1., that these ai, <* 2 , a 3 form only a two- 
dimensional continuum i.e. that they should be representable in the plane. 
Indeed, (32:3) makes a very simple plane representation possible. 




Figure 52. 



a, - -I 



a* - 




7 



Figure 53. 

32.1.2. For this purpose we take three axes in the plane, making angles 
of 60 with each other. For any point of the plane we define on, 2, as 
by directed perpendicular distances from these three axes. The whole 
arrangement, and in particular the signs to be ascribed to the <*i, as, as 



284 



GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 



are given in Figure 52. It is easy to verify that for any point the algebraic 
sum of these three perpendicular distances vanishes and that conversely 

any triplet a = {i, 2, 8 } for which the sum vanishes, corresponds to a 
point. 

So the plane representation of Figure 52 expresses precisely the condition 
(32:3). The remaining condition (32:2) is therefore the equivalent of a 

restriction imposed upon the point a within the plane of Figure 52. This 

restriction is obviously that it must lie on or within the triangle formed 

by the three lines i = 1, 2 = 1, a = 1. Figure 53 illustrates this. 

Thus the shaded area, to be called the fundamental triangle, represents 

the a which fulfill (32:2), (32:3) i.e. all imputations. 

32.1.3. We next express the relationship of domination in this graphical 
representation. As n = 3, we know from (31 :H) (cf. also the discussion of 





Figure 54. 



Figure 55. 



(31:8) at the end of 31.1.5.) that among the subsets 8 of / = (1, 2, 3) 
those of two elements are certainly necessary, and all others certainly 
unnecessary. I.e., the sets which we must consider in our determination 
of all solutions V are precisely these : 



Thus for 
domination 
means that 



(1,2); (1,3); (2,3). 



a = {ai, a 2 , as}, ft = {ft, ft, ft} 

a H B 



(32:4) Either i > ft, a 2 > ft; or ai > fa, a* > ft; or 2 > ft, 

as > ft. 

Diagrammatically: a dominates the points in the shaded areas, and no 
others, 1 in Figure 54. 



1 In particular, no points on the boundary lines of these areas. 



ALL SOLUTIONS OF THE THREE-PERSON GAME 285 

> 
Thus the point a dominates three of the six sextants indicated in 

Figure 55 (namely A, C, B). From this one concludes easily that a is 
dominated by the three other sextants (namely B, D, F). So the only 

points which do not dominate a and are not dominated by it, lie on the 
three lines (i.e. six half-lines) which separate these sextants. I.e. : 


(32:5) If neither of a. , ft dominates the other, then the direction 

> 

from a. to ft is parallel to one of the sides of the fundamental 
triangle. 

32.1.4. Now the systematic search for all solutions can begin. 

Consider a solution V, i.e. a set in the fundamental triangle which 
fulfills the conditions (30:5:a), (30:5:b) of 30.1.1. In what follows we shall 
use these conditions currently, without referring to them explicitly on each 
occasion. 

Since the game is essential, V must contain at least two points 1 say 

a and ft . By (32:5) the direction from a to ft is parallel to one of the 
sides of the fundamental triangle; and by a permutation of the numbers of the 

players 1,2,3 we can arrange this to be the side i = 1, i.e. the horizontal. 

* 
So a , ft lie on a horizontal line I. Now two possibilities arise and we treat 

them separately: 

(a) Every point of V lies on I. 

(b) Some points of V do not lie on L 

32.2. Determination of All Solutions 

32.2.1. We consider (b) first. Any point not on I must fulfill (32:5) with 

> 
respect to both a and ft , i.e. it must be the third vertex of one of the two 

> 

equilateral triangles with the base a , ft : one of the two points a ', a " of 

> 
Figure 56. So either a ' or a " belongs to V. Any point of V which differs 

from a, ft and a 'or a " must again fulfill (32:5), but now with respect to all 

> 
three points a , ft and a ' or a ". This, however, is impossible, as an 

inspection of Figure 56 immediately reveals. So V consists of precisely these 
three points, i.e. of the three vertices of a triangle which is in the position 
of triangle / or triangle // of Figure 57. Comparison of Figure 57 with 
Figures 54 or 55 shows that the vertices of triangle / leave the interior of 
this triangle uridominated. This rules out I. 2 

1 This is also directly observable in Fig. 54. 

2 This provides the example referred to in 30.3.6.: The three vertices of triangle / do 
not dominate each other, i.e. they form a satisfactory set in the sense of loc. cit. They are 
nevertheless unsuitable as a subset of a solution. 



286 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 






Figure 57. 




Fundamental Triangle - 

Figure 58. 




danienUl Triangle - 

Figure 59. 



ALL SOLUTIONS OF THE THREE-PERSON GAME 287 

The same comparison shows that the vertices of triangle // leave 
undominated the dotted areas indicated in Figure 58. Hence triangle // 
must be placed in such a manner in the fundamental triangle that these 
dotted areas fall entirely outside the fundamental triangle. This means 
that the three vertices of II must lie on the three sides of the fundamental 
triangle, as indicated in Figure 59. Thus these three vertices are the 
middle points of the three sides of the fundamental triangle. 

Comparison of Figure 59 with Figure 54 or Figure 55 shows that this 
set V is indeed a solution. One verifies immediately that these three 
middle points are the points (vectors) 

(32:6) {-!,*,*}, {*,-!, 41, It,*, -1|, 

i.e. that this solution V is the set of Figure 51. 



Fundament*! 
Triangle 




Figure 60. 

32.2.2. Let us now consider (a) in 32.1.4. In this case all of V lies on the 
horizontal line L By (32 :5) no two points of I dominate each other, so that 
every point of / is undominated by V. Hence every point of I (in the funda- 
mental triangle) must belong to V. I.e., V is precisely that part of / 

which is in the fundamental triangle. So the elements a = {<*i, 2, s} 
of V are characterized by an equation 

(32:7) i c. 

Diagrammatically: Figure 60. 

Comparison of Figure 60 with Figures 54 or 55 shows that the line I 
leaves the dotted area indicated on Figure 60 undominated. Hence the line 
I must be placed in such a manner in the fundamental triangle that the 
dotted area falls entirely outside the fundamental triangle. This means 
that I must lie below the middle points of those two sides of the fundamental 



288 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 

triangle which it intersects. 1 In the terminology of (32:7): c < |. On the 
other hand, c ^ 1 is necessary to make I intersect the fundamental 
triangle at all. So we have: 

(32:8) -1 S c <i 

Comparison of Figure 60 with Figures 54 or 55 shows that under these 
conditions 2 the set V i.e. I is indeed a solution. 

But the form (32:7) of this solution was brought about by a suitable 
permutation of the numbers 1,2,3. Hence we have two further solutions, 
characterized by 

(32:7*) a, = c, 

and characterized by 

(32:7**) 3 = c, 

always with (32:8) 

32.2.3. Summing up: 

This is a complete list of solutions: 

(32:A) For every c which fulfills (32:8): The three sets (32:7) 

(32:7*), (32:7**). 
(32 :B) The set (32:6). 

33. Conclusions 
33.1. The Multiplicity of Solutions. Discrimination and Its Meaning 

33.1.1. The result of 32. calls for careful consideration and comment. 
We have determined all solutions of the essential zero-sum three-person 
game. In 29.1., before the rigorous definitions of 30.1. were formulated, 
we had already decided which solution we wanted; and this solution reap- 
pears now as (32 :B). But we found other solutions besides: the (32: A), 
which are infinitely many sets, each one of them an infinite set of imputa- 
tions itself. What do these supernumerary solutions stand for? 

Consider, e.g., the form (32:7) of (32: A). This gives a solution for 

every c of (32:8) consisting of all imputations a = {i, 2 , 3 } which fulfill 
(32:7), i.e. i = c. Besides this, they must fulfill only the requirements, 

1 The limiting position of J, going through the middle points themselves, must be 
excluded. The reason is that in this position the vertex of the dotted area would lie on 
the fundamental triangle, and this is inadmissable since that point too is undominated 
by V, i.e. by I. 

Observe that the corresponding prohibition did not occur in case (b), i.e. for the 
dotted areas of Figure 58. Their vertices too were undominated by V, but they belong 
to V. In our present position of V, on the other hand, the vertex under consideration 
does not belong to V, i.e. to I. 

This exclusion of the limiting position causes the < and not the ^ in the 
inequality which follows. 

* (32:8), i.e. I intersects the fundamental triangle, but below its middle. 



CONCLUSIONS 289 

(30:1), (30:2) of 30.1.1. i.e. (32:2), (32:3) of 32.1.1. In other words: 
Our solution consists of all 

(33:1) "^ = {c, a, -c -a}, -1 g a 1 - c. 

The interpretation of this solution consists manifestly of this: One 
of the players (in this case 1) is being discriminated against by the two others 
(in this case 2,3). They assign to him the amount which he gets, c. This 
amount is the same for all imputations of the solution, i.e. of the accepted 
standard of behavior. The place in society of player 1 is prescribed by the 
two other players; he is excluded from all negotiations that may lead to 
coalitions. Such negotiations do go on, however, between the two other 
players: the distribution of their share, c, depends entirely upon their 
bargaining abilities. The solution, i.e. the accepted standard of behavior, 
imposes absolutely no restrictions upon the way in which this share is 
divided between them, expressed by a, c a. 1 This is not surprising. 
Since the excluded player is absolutely "tabu," the threat of the partner's 
desertion is removed from each participant of the coalition. There is no 
way of determining any definite division of the spoils. 2 ' 3 

Incidentally: It is quite instructive to see how our concept of a solution 
as a set of imputations is able to take care of this situation also. 

33.1.2. There is more that should be said about this "discrimination" 
against a player. 

First, it is not done in an entirely arbitrary manner. The c, in which 
discrimination finds its quantitative expression, is restricted by (32:8) in 
32.2.2. Now part of (32:8), c ^ 1, is clear enough in its meaning, but the 
significance of the other part c < 4 is considerably more recondite (cf. 
however, below). It all comes back to this: Even an arbitrary system of 
discriminations can be compatible with a stable standard of behavior i.e. 
order of society but it may have to fulfill certain quantitative conditions, 
in order that it may not impair that stability. 

Second, the discrimination need not be clearly disadvantageous to the 
player who is affected. It cannot be clearly advantageous, i.e. his fixed 
value c cannot be equal to or better than the best the others may expect. 
This would mean, by (33:1), that c ^ 1 c, i.e. c ^ i, which is exactly 
what (32:8) forbids. But it would be clearly disadvantageous only for 
c = 1 ; and this is a possible value for c (by (32:8)), but not the only one. 
c = 1 means that the player is not only excluded, but also exploited to 

1 Except that both must be <z 1 i.e. what the player can get for himself, without 
any outside help. 

a, c & ^ 1 is, of course, the 1 ^ a ^ 1 c of (33:1). 

2 Cf. the discussions at the end of 25.2. Observe that the arguments which we 
adduced there to motivate the primate of v(S) have ceased to operate in this particular 
case and v(S) nevertheless determines the solutions! 

8 Observe that due to (32:8) in 32.2.2., the "spoils", i.e. the amount c, can be both 
positive and negative. 

4 And that is excluded in c < J, but not in c ^ 1. 



290 GENERAL THEORY: ZERO-SUM n-PERSONS 

100 per cent. The remaining c (of (32:8)) with 1 < c < i correspond to 
gradually less and less disadvantageous forms of segregation. 

33.1.3. It seems remarkable that our concept of a solution is able to 
express all these nuances of non-discriminatory (32 :B), and discriminatory 
(32: A), standards of behavior the latter both in their 100 per cent injurious 
form, c = 1, and in a continuous family of less and less injurious ones 
1 < c < i. It is particularly significant that we did not look for any 
such thing the heuristic discussions of 29.1 were certainly not in this spirit 
but we were nevertheless forced to these conclusions by the rigorous theory 
itself. And these situations arose even in the extremely simple framework 
of the zero-sum three-person game! 

For n ^ 4 we must expect a much greater wealth of possibilities for 
all sorts of schemes of discrimination, prejudices, privileges, etc. Besides 
these, we must always look out for the analogues of the solution (32:B), i.e. 
the nondiscriminating " objective " solutions. But we shall see that the con- 
ditions are far from simple. And we shall also see that it is precisely the 
investigation of the discriminatory "inobjective" solutions which leads to a 
proper understanding of the general non-zero-sum games and thence to 
application to economics. 

33.2. Statics and Dynamics 

33.2. At this point it may be advantageous to recall the discussions of 
4.8.2. concerning statics and dynamics. What we said then applies now; 
indeed it was really meant for the phase which our theory has now reached. 

In 29.2. and in the places referred to there, we considered the nego- 
tiations, expectations and fears which precede the formation of a coalition 
and which determine its conditions. These were all of the quasi-dynamic 
type described in 4.8.2. The same applies to our discussion in 4.6. and 
again in 30.2., of how various imputations may or may not dominate each 
other depending on their relationship to a solution; i.e., how the conducts 
approved by an established standard of behavior do not conflict with each 
other, but can be used to discredit the non-approved varieties. 

The excuse, and the necessity, for using such considerations in a static 
theory were set forth on that occasion. Thus it is not necessary to repeat 
them now. 



CHAPTER VII 
ZERO-SUM FOUR-PERSON GAMES 

34. Preliminary Survey 
34.1. General Viewpoints 

34.1. We are now in possession of a general theory of the zero-sum 
n-person game, but the state of our information is still far from satisfactory. 
Save for the formal statement of the definitions we have penetrated but 
little below the surface. The applications which we have made i.e. the 
special cases in which we have succeeded in determining our solutions can 
be rated only as providing a preliminary orientation. As pointed out in 
30.4.2., these applications cover all cases n ^ 3, but we know from our past 
discussions how little this is in comparison with the general problem. Thus 
we must turn to games with n ^ 4 and it is only here that the full complexity 
of the interplay of coalitions can be expected to emerge. A deeper insight 
into the nature of our problems will be achieved only when we have mastered 
the mechanisms which govern these phenomena. 

The present chapter is devoted to zero-sum four-person games. Our 
information about these still presents many lacunae. This compels an 
inexhaustive and chiefly casuistic treatment, with its obvious shortcomings. 1 
But even this imperfect exposition will disclose various essential qualitative 
properties of the general theory which could not be encountered previously, 
(for n g 3). Indeed, it will be noted that the interpretation of the mathe- 
matical results of this phase leads quite naturally to specific "social" 
concepts and formulations. 

34.2. Formalism of the Essential Zero -sum Four-person Game 
34.2.1. In order to acquire an idea of the nature of the zero-sum four- 
person games we begin with a purely descriptive classification. 

Let therefore an arbitrary zero-sum four-person game F be given, which 
we may as well consider in its reduced form: and also let us choose y = I. 2 
These assertions correspond, as we know from (27:7*) and (27:7**) in 27.2., 
to the following statements concerning the characteristic functions: 



(34:1) v(5) = 





-1 
1 




when S has 



elements. 



1 E.g., a considerable emphasis on heuristic devices. 

2 Cf. 27.1.4. and 27.3.2. The reader will note the analogy between this discussion 
and that of 29.1.2. concerning the zero-sum three-person game. About this more will 
be said later. 

291 



292 ZERO-SUM FOUR-PERSON GAMES 

Thus only the v(/S) of the two-element sets S remain undetermined by 
these normalizations. We therefore direct our attention to these sets. 
The set I = (1,2,3,4) of all players possesses six two-element subsets S: 

(1,2), (1,3), (1,4), (2,3), (2,4), (3,4). 

Now the v(S) of these sets cannot be treated as independent variables, 
because each one of these S has another one of the same sequence as its 
complement. Specifically: the first and the last, the second and the fifth, 
the third and the fourth, are complements of each other respectively. 
Hence their v(S) are the negatives of each other. It is also to be remem- 
bered that by the inequality (27:7) in 27.2. (with n = 4, p = 2) all these 
v(S) are ^2, ^ 2. Hence if we put 



)) = 2xi, 

(34:2) v((2,4)) = 2x 2 , 

1 v((3,4)) = 2x 3 , 
then we have 

f v((2,3)) = -2*!, 

(34:3) v((l,3)) = -2x 2 , 

lv((l,2)) = -2*3, 
and in addition 

(34:4) -1 ^ xi, x 2 , x, ^ 1. 

Conversely: If any three numbers Xi, x 2 , x 3 fulfilling (34:4) are given, 
then we can define a function v(S) (for all subsets S of I = (1,2,3,4)) by 
(34:l)-(34:3), but we must show that this v(S) is the characteristic function 
of a game. By 26.1. this means that our present v(S) fulfills the conditions 
(25:3:a)-(25:3:c) of 25.3.1. Of these, (25:3:a) and (25:3:b) are obviously 
fulfilled, so only (25:3:c) remains. By 25.4.2. this means showing that 

v(Si) + v(S 2 ) + v(S 3 ) ^ if Si, S 2 , Ss are a decomposition of /. 

(Cf. also (25:6) in 25.4.1.) If any of the sets Si, S 2 , S 8 is empty, the two 
others are complements and so we even have equality by (25:3:a), (25:3:b) 
in 25.3.1. So we may assume that none of the sets Si, S 2 , S 8 is empty. 
Since four elements are available altogether, one of these sets, say Si = S, 
must have two elements, while the two others are one-element sets. Thus 
our inequality becomes 

v(S) -2^0, i.e. v(S) ^ 2. 

If we express this for all two-element sets S, then (34:2), (34:3) transform 
the inequality into 

2*i g 2, 2x 2 ^ 2, 2x 3 ^ 2, 

-2*! g 2, -2*, g 2, -2x, g 2, 

which is equivalent to the assumed (34 :4) . Thus we have demonstrated : 



PRELIMINARY SURVEY 



293 



(34: A) The essential zero-sum four-person games (in their reduced 

form with the choice 7 = 1) correspond exactly to the triplets 
of numbers xi, a? 2 , z 8 fulfilling the inequalities (34:4). The 
correspondence between such a game, i.e. its characteristic 
function, and its x\, z 2 , x* is given by the equations (34:l)-(34:3). 1 

34.2.2. The above representation of the essential zero-sum four-person 
games by triplets of numbers x\, z 2 , x 8 can be illustrated by a simple geo- 
metrical picture. We can view the numbers x\, x$, x 3 as the Cartesian 
coordinates of a point. 2 In this case the inequalities (34:4) describe a part 




Figure 61. 

of space which exactly fills a cube Q. This cube is centered at the origin 
of the coordinates, and its edges are of length 2 because its six faces are the 
six planes 

Xi = 1, Z 2 = 1, X 3 = 1, 

as shown in Figure 61. 

Thus each essential zero-sum four-person game F is represented by 
precisely one point in the interior or on the surface of this cube, and vice 
versa. It is quite useful to view these games in this manner and to try to 
correlate their peculiarities with the geometrical conditions in Q. It 
will be particularly instructive to identify those games which correspond to 
definite significant points of Q. 

1 The reader may now compare our result with that of 29.1.2. concerning the zero-sum 
three-person games. It will be noted how the variety of possibilities has increased. 

2 We may also consider these numbers as the components of a vector in L$ in the 
sense of 16.1.2. et seq. This aspect will sometimes be the more convenient, as in foot- 
note 1 on p. 304. 



294 ZERO-SUM FOUR-PERSON GAMES 

But even before carryitig out this program, we propose to consider 
certain questions of symmetry. We want to uncover the connections 
between the permutations of the players 1,2,3,4, and the geometrical trans- 
formations (motions) of Q. Indeed: by 28.1. the former correspond to the 
symmetries of the game T, while the latter obviously express the symmetries 
of the geometrical object. 

34.3. Permutations of the Players 

34.3.1. In evolving the geometrical representation of the essential 
zero-sum four-person game we had to perform an arbitrary operation, 
i.e. one which destroyed part of the symmetry of the original situation. 
Indeed, in describing the v(S) of the two-element sets S, we had to single 
out three from among these sets (which are six in number), in order to 
introduce the coordinates x\ y x 2 , x 3 . We actually did this in (34:2), (34:3) 
by assigning the player 4 a particular role and then setting up a correspond- 
ence between the players 1,2,3 and the quantities Xi, x 2 , x 3 respectively 
(cf. (34:2)). Thus a permutation of the players 1,2,3 will induce the same 
permutation of the coordinates Xi, x 2 , x 3 and so far the arrangement is 
symmetric. But these are only six permutations from among the total of 
24 permutations of the players 1,2,3,4.* So a permutation which replaces 
the player 4 by another one is not accounted for in this way. 

34.3.2. Let us consider such a permutation. For reasons which will 
appear immediately, consider the permutation A, which interchanges the 
players 1 and 4 with each other and also the players 2 and 3. 2 A look at the 
equations (34:2), (34:3) suffices to show that this permutation leaves Xi 
invariant, while it replaces x 2 , x 3 by x 2 , x 3 . Similarly one verifies: 
The permutation 5, which interchanges 2 and 4, and also 1 and 3, leaves x 2 
invariant and replaces Xi, x 3 by Xi, x 3 . The permutation C, which 
interchanges 3 and 4 and also 1 and 2, leaves x s invariant and replaces Xi, x 2 
by -Xi, -x 2 . 

Thus each one of the three permutations A, B, C affects the variables 
Xi, x 2 , x 8 only as far as their signs are concerned, each changing two signs 
and leaving the third invariant. 

Since they also carry 4 into 1,2,3, respectively, they produce all permuta- 
tions of the players 1,2,3,4, if combined with the six permutations of the 
players 1,2,3. Now we have seen that the latter correspond to the six 
permutations of Xi, x 2 , x 3 (without changes in sign). Consequently the 
24 permutations of 1,2,3,4 correspond to the six permutations of Xi, x 2 , x 3 , 
each one in conjunction with no change of sign or with two changes of 
sign. 8 

1 Cf. 28.1.1., following the definitions (28:A:a), (28:A:b). 

2 With the notations of 29.1.: 

1,2,3,4\ B _ /1,2,3,4\ _ /1,2,3,4 

B ~ c 



3 These sign changes are 1 + 3 4 possibilities in each case, so we have 6 X 4 24 
operations on Xi, x^ x\ to represent the 24 permutations of 1,2,3,4, as it should be. 



SPECIAL POINTS IN THE CUBE Q 



295 



34.3.3. We may also state this as follows: If we consider all movements 
in space which carry the cube Q into itself, it is easily verified that they 
consist of the permutations of the coordinate axes xi, x 2 , x* in combination 
with any reflections on the coordinate planes (i.e. the planes x*, x 9 ; x\ t Xf ; 
#1, xj). Mathematically these are the permutations of x\ y X*, x\ in combina- 
tion with any changes of sign among the xi, X2, x 8 . These are 48 possibili- 
ties. 1 Only half of these, the 24 for which the number of sign changes is 
even (i.e. or 2), correspond to the permutations of the players. 




IV 



Figure 62. 



It is easily verified that these are precisely the 24 which not only carry 
the cube Q into itself, but also the tetrahedron I, V, VI, VII, as indicated in 
Figure 62. One may also characterize such a movement by observing that 
it always carries a vertex of Q into a vertex ; and equally a vertex o into a 
vertex o, but never a into a o. 2 

We shall now obtain a much more immediate interpretation of these 
statements by describing directly the games which correspond to specific 
points of the cube Q: to the vertices or o, to the center (the origin in Figure 
61), and to the main diagonals of Q. 

35. Discussion of Some Special Points in the Cube Q 
35.1. The Corner / (and 7, VI, VII) 

35.1.1. We begin by determining the games which correspond to the 
four corners : 7, V, VI, VII. We have seen that they arise from each other 
by suitable permutations of the players 1,2,3,4. Therefore it suffices to 
consider one of them, say /. 

1 For each variable *i, x tt x\ there are two possibilities: change or no change. This 
gives altogether 2 1 - 8 possibilities. Combination with the six permutations of Xi, t, x* 
yields 8 X 6 48 operations. 

* This group of motions is well known in group theory and particularly in crystallog- 
raphy, but we shall not elaborate the point further. 



296 ZERO-SUM FOUR-PERSON GAMES 

The point 7 corresponds to the values 1,1,1 of the coordinates x\, x z , 
Thus the characteristic function v(>S) of this game is: 



(35:1) v(S) 





-1 

2 



-2 

1 




when S has 




1 
2 (and 4 belongs to S) 

elements 

2 (and 4 does not belong to S) 
3 
4 



(Verification is immediate with the help of (34:1), (34:2), (34:3) in 34.2.1.) 
Instead of applying the mathematical theory of Chapter VI to this game, let 
us first see whether it does not allow an immediate intuitive interpretation. 

Observe first that a player who is left to himself loses the amount 1. 
This is manifestly the worst thing that can ever happen to him since he 
can protect himself against further losses without anybody else's help. 1 
Thus we may consider a player who gets this amount 1 as completely 
defeated. A coalition of two pla3 r ers may be considered as defeated if it 
gets the amount 2, since then each player in it must necessarily get I. 2 - 3 
In this game the coalition of any two players is defeated in this sense if it 
does not comprise player 4. 

Let us now pass to the complementary sets. If a coalition is defeated 
in the above sense, it is reasonable to consider the complementary set 
as a winning coalition. Therefore the two-element sets which contain the 
player 4 must be rated as winning coalitions. Also since any player who 
remains isolated must be rated as defeated, three-person coalitions always 
win. This is immaterial for those three-element coalitions which contain 
the player 4, since in these coalitions two members are winning already 
if the player 4 is among them. But it is essential that 1,2,3 be a winning 
coalition, since all its proper subsets are defeated. 4 

1 This view of the matter is corroborated by our results concerning the three-person 
game in 23. and 32.2., and more fundamentally by our definition of the imputation in 
30.1.1., particularly condition (30:1). 

2 Since neither he nor his partner need accept less than 1, and they have together 
2, this is the only way in which they can split. 

8 In the terminology of 31.1.4.: this coalition is flat. There is of course no gain, and 
therefore no possible motive for two players to form such a coalition. But if it happens 
that the two other players have combined and show no desire to acquire a third ally, we 
may treat the remaining two as a coalition even in this case. 

4 We warn the reader that, although we have used the words " defeated" and " win- 
ning" almost as termini technici, this is not our intention. These concepts are, indeed, 
very well suited for an exact treatment. The "defeated" and "winning" coalitions 
actually coincide with the sets S considered in (31 :F) and in (31 :G) in 31.1.5.; those for 
which S is flat or S is flat, respectively. But we shall consider this question in such 
a way only in Chap. X. 

For the moment our considerations are absolutely heuristic and ought to be taken 
in the same spirit as the heuristic discussions of the zero-sum three-person game in 21., 22. 
The only difference is that we shall be considerably briefer now, since our experience and 
routine have grown substantially in the discussion. 

As we now possess an exact theory of solutions for games already, we are under 



SPECIAL POINTS IN THE CUBE Q 297 

35.1.2. So it is plausible to view this as a struggle for participation in 
any one of the various possible coalitions: 

(35:2) (1,4), (2,4), (3,4), (1,2,3), 

where the amounts obtainable for these coalitions are: 

(35:3) v((l,4)) = v((2,4)) = v((3,4)) = 2, v((l,2,3)) = 1. 

Observe that this is very similar to the situation which we found in 
the essential zero-sum three-person game, where the winning coalitions 
were: 

(35:2*) (1,2), (1,3), (2,3), 

and the amounts obtainable for these coalitions: 
(35:3*) v((l,2)) = v((l,3)) = v((2,3)) = 1. 

In the three-person game we determined the distribution of the pro- 
ceeds (35:3*) among the winners by assuming: A player in a winning coali- 
tion should get the same amount no matter which is the winning coalition. 
Denoting these amounts for the players 1,2,3 by a, $, y respectively, (35:3*) 
gives 

(35:4*) a + = a + 7 =:0 + 7 = l 

from which follows 

(35:5*) a = ft = y = i 

These were indeed the values which those considerations yielded. 

Let us assume the same principle in our present four-person game. 
Denote by a, 0, 7, 5, respectively, the amount that each player 1,2,3,4 gets 
if he succeeds in participating in a winning coalition. Then (35:3) gives 

(35:4) a + 6 = + 6 = 7 + $ = 2, a + + 7 = 1, 

from which follows 

(35:5) = = 7 = i * = i 

All the heuristic arguments used in 21., 22., for the three-person game could 
be repeated. 1 

35.1.3. Summing up: 

(35 :A) This is a game in which the player 4 is in a specially favored 

position to win: any one ally suffices for him to form a winning 
coalition. Without his cooperation, on the other hand, three 
players must combine. This advantage also expresses itself in 

obligation to follow up this preliminary heuristic analysis by an exact analysis which 
is based rigorously on the mathematical theory. We shall come to this. (Cf. loc. cit. 
above, and also the beginning of 36.2.3.) 

1 Of course, without making this thereby a rigorous discussion on the basis of 30.1. 



298 



ZERO-SUM FOUR-PERSON GAMES 



the amounts which each player 1,2,3,4 should get when he is 
among the winners if our above heuristic deduction can be 
trusted. These amounts are i, |, i, | respectively. It is 
to be noted that the advantage of player 4 refers to the case of 
victory only; when defeated, all players are in the same position 
(i.e. get -1). 

The last mentioned circumstance is, of course, due to our normaliza- 
tion by reduction. Independently of any normalization, however, this game 
exhibits the following trait: One player 's quantitative advantage over 
another may, when both win, differ from what it is when both lose. 

This cannot happen in a three-person game, as is apparent from the 
formulation which concludes 22.3.4. Thus we get a first indication of an 
important new factor that emerges when the number of participants reaches 
four. 

35.1.4. One last remark seems appropriate. In this game player 4's 
strategic advantage consisted in the fact that he needed only one ally 
for victory, whereas without him a total of three partners was necessary. 
One might try to pass to an even more extreme form by constructing a game 
in which every coalition that does not contain player 4 is defeated. It is 
essential to visualize that this is not so, or rather that such an advantage 
is no longer of a strategic nature. Indeed in such a game 





1 

2 
3 



if 8 has 



hence 



if S has 



elements and 4 does not belong to S, 



1 

2 

elements and 4 belongs to S. 

o 

4 



This is not reduced, as 

v((I)) = v((2)) v((3)) = -1, 



v((4)) = 3. 



If we apply the reduction process of 27.1.4. to this v(S) we find that its 
reduced form is 

0. 



i.e. the game is inessential. (This could have been shown directly by (27 :B) 
in 27.4.) Thus this game has a uniquely determined value for each player 
1,2,3,4: 1, 1, 1, 3, respectively. 

In other words: Player 4's advantage in this game is one of a fixed 
payment (i.e. of cash), and not one of strategic possibilities. The former 
is, of course, more definite and tangible than the latter, but of less theoretical 
interest since it can be removed by our process of reduction. 



SPECIAL POINTS IN THE CUBE Q 299 

35.1.5. We observed at the beginning of this section that the corners 
V, VI, VII differ from J only by permutations of the players. It is easily 
verified that the special role of player 4 in / is enjoyed by the players 1,2,3, 
in V, VI, VII, respectively. 

35.2. The Corner VIII (and //, ///, 77). The Three-person Game and a "Dummy 91 

35.2.1. We next consider the games which correspond to the four corners 
o : //, ///, IV, VIII. As they arise from each other by suitable permutations 
of the players 1,2,3,4, it suffices to consider one of them, say VIIL 

The point VIII corresponds to the values 1, 1, 1 of the coordinates 
xi, x 2 , x*. Thus the characteristic function v(S) of this game is: 



(35:6) v(S) = 





-1 
-2 



2 
1 




when S has 




1 
2 (and 4 belongs to S) 

elements 

2 (and 4 does not belong to 5) 
3 
4 



(Verification is immediate with the help of (34:1), (34:2), (34:3) in 34.2.1.) 
Again, instead of applying to this game the mathematical theory of Chapter 
VI, let us first see whether it does not allow an immediate intuitive 
interpretation. 

The important feature of this game is that the inequality (25:3:c) in 
25.3. becomes an equality, i.e. : 

(35:7) v(S u T) = v(S) + v(T) if S n T = 0, 

when T = (4). That is: If S represents a coalition which does not contain 
the player 4, then the addition of 4 to this coalition is of no advantage; 
i.e. it does not affect the strategic situation of this coalition nor of its 
opponents in any way. This is clearly the meaning of the additivity 
expressed by (35 :7). 1 

35.2.2. This circumstance suggests the following conclusion, which 
is of course purely heuristic. 2 Since the accession of player 4 to any 

1 Note that the indifference in acquiring the cooperation of 4 is expressed by (35:7), 
and not by 

v(S U T) - vGS). 

That is, a player is "indifferent" as a partner, not if his accession does not alter the value 
of a coalition but if he brings into the coalition exactly the amount which and no more 
than he is worth outside. 

This remark may seem trivial; but there exists a certain danger of misunderstanding, 
particularly in non-reduced games where v((4)) > 0, i.e. where the accession of 4 
(although strategically indifferent!) actually increases the value of a coalition. 

Observe also that the indifference of S and T (4) to each other is a strictly recip- 
rocal relationship. 

1 We shall later undertake exact discussion on the basis of 30.1. At that time it will 
be found also that all these games are special cases of more general classes of some 
importance. (Cf. Chap. IX, particularly 41.2.) 



300 ZERO-SUM FOUR-PERSON GAMES 

coalition appears to he a matter of complete indifference to both sides, it 
seems plausible to assume that player 4 has no part in the transactions that 
constitute the strategy of the game. lie is isolated from the others and 
the amount which he can get for himself v(/S) = 1 is the actual value 
of the game for him. The other players 1,2,3, on the other hand, play 
the game strictly among themselves; hence they are playing a three- 
person game. The values of the original characteristic function v(S) 
which describes the original three-person game are : 



=v((3)) = -1, 



(35:6*) v((l,2)) = v((l,3)) = v((2,3)) = 2, 
v((l,2,3)) = 1, 



/' = (1,2,3) is now the set 
of all players. 



(Verify this from (35:6).) 

At first sight this three-person game represents the oddity that v(/') 
(/' is now the set of all players!) is not zero. This, however, is perfectly 
reasonable: by eliminating player 4 we transform the game into one which 
is not of zero sum; since we assessed player 4 a value 1, the others retain 
together a value 1. We do not yet propose to deal with this situation 
systematically. (Cf. footnote 2 on p. 299.) It is obvious, however, that 
this condition can be remedied by a slight generalization of the transforma- 
tion used in 27.1. We modify the game of 1,2,3 by assuming that each 
one got the amount i in cash in advance, and then compensating for this 
by deducting equivalent amounts from the v(S) values in (35:6*). Just 
as in 27.1., this cannot affect the strategy of the game, i.e. it produces a 
strategically equivalent game. l 

After consideration of the compensations mentioned above 2 we obtain 
the new characteristic function : 

v'(0) = 0, 

v'((l)) = v'((2)) = v'((3)) = - *, 
(35:6**) v'((l,2)) = v'((l,3)) = v'((2,3)) = *, 

v'((l,2,3)) = 0. 

This is the reduced form of the essential zero-sum three-person game dis- 
cussed in 32. except for a difference in unit : We have now y = $ instead 

1 In the terminology of 27.1.1.: a? = al = al |. The condition there which 
we have infringed is (27:1): ^ aj = 0. This is necessary since we started with a non- 

t 
zero-sum game. 

Even 2^ a i " could be safeguarded if we included player 4 in our considerations, 

t 

putting aj = 1. This would leave him just as isolated as before, but the necessary 
compensation would make v((4)) = 0, with results which are obvious. 

One can sum this up by saying that in the present situation it is not the reduced 
form of the game which provides the best basis of discussion among all strategically 
equivalent forms. 

2 I.e. deduction of as many times J from v(S) as 8 has elements. 



SPECIAL POINTS IN THE CUBE Q 301 

of the 7 = 1 of (32:1) in 32.1.1. Thus we can apply the heuristic results 
of 23.1.3., or the exact results of 32. l Let us restrict ourselves, at any 
rate, to the solution which appears in both cases and which is the simplest 
one: (32:B) of 32.2.3. This is the set of imputations (32:6) in 32.2.1., which 
we must multiply by the present value of y = ; i.e.: 

(-*,*,!}, ft, -it!, lit, -*} 

(The players are, of course, 1,2,3.) In other words: The aim of the strategy 
of the players 1,2,3 is to form any coalition of two; a player who succeeds 
in this, i.e. who is victorious, gets f , and a player who is defeated gets $. 
Now each of the players 1,2,3 of our original game gets the extra amount 
i beyond this, hence the above amounts f , 1 must be replaced by 
1, -1. 

36.2.3. Summing up: 

(35 :B) This is a game in which the player 4 is excluded from all 

coalitions. The strategic aim of the other players 1,2,3 is to 
form any coalition of two. Player 4 gets 1 at any rate. Any 
other player 1,2,3 gets the amount 1 when he is among the win- 
ners, and the amount 1 when he is defeated. All this is based 
on heuristic considerations. 

One might say more concisely that this four-person game is only an 
"inflated" three-person game: the essential three-person game of the players 
1,2,3, inflated by the addition of a "dummy" player 4. We shall see later 
that this concept is of a more general significance. (Cf. footnote 2 on 
p. 299.) 

36.2.4. One might compare the dummy role of player 4 in this game 
with the exclusion a player undergoes in the discriminatory solution (32: A) 
in 32.2.3., as discussed in 33.1.2. There is, however, an important differ- 
ence between these two phenomena. In our present set-up, player 4 has 
really no contribution to make to any coalition at all; he stands apart by 
virtue of the characteristic function v(S). Our heuristic considerations 
indicate that he should be excluded from all coalitions in all acceptable 
solutions. We shall see in 46.9. that the exact theory establishes just 
this. The excluded player of a discriminatory solution in the sense of 
33.1.2. is excluded only in the particular situation under consideration. As 
far as the characteristic function of that game is concerned, his role is the 
same as that of all other players. In other words: The "dummy" in our 
present game is excluded by virtue of the objective facts of the situation 
(the characteristic function v(S)). 2 The excluded player in a discrimi- 
natory solution is excluded solely by the arbitrary (though stable) 
"prejudices" that the particular standard of behavior (solution) expresses. 

1 Of course the present discussion is heuristic in any event. As to the exact treat- 
ment, cf. footnote 2 on p. 299. 

2 This is the " physical background,' 1 in the sense of 4.6.3. 



302 ZERO-SUM FOUR-PERSON GAMES 

We observed at the beginning of this section that the corners //, 777, 
IV differ from VIII only by permutations of the players. It is easily 
verified that the special role of player 4 in VIII is enjoyed by the players 
1,2,3 in 77, 777, 77, respectively. 

85.3. Some Remarks Concerning the Interior of Q 

35.3.1. Let us now consider the game which corresponds to the center of 
Q, i.e. to the values 0,0,0 of the coordinates x\ } 2, g. This game is clearly 
unaffected by any permutation of the players 1,2,3,4, i.e. it is symmetric. 
Observe that it is the only such game in Q, since total symmetry means 
in variance under all permutations of x\, 2, x* and sign changes of any two 
of them (cf. 34.3.); hence Xi = x a = x s = 0. 

The characteristic function v(S) of this game is: 



(35:8) v(S) = 




-1 
when S has 

1 






1 

2 elements. 

3 

4 



(Verification is immediate with the help of (34:1), (34:2), (34:3) in 34.2.1.) 
The exact solutions of this game are numerous; indeed, one must say that 
they are of a rather bewildering variety. It has not been possible yet to 
order them and to systematize them by a consistent application of the exact 
theory, to such an extent as one would desire. Nevertheless the known 
specimens give some instructive insight into the ramifications of the theory. 
We shall consider them in somewhat more detail in 37. and 38. 

At present we make only this (heuristic) remark: The idea of this 
(totally) symmetric game is clearly that any majority of the players (i.e. any 
coalition of three) wins, whereas in case of a tie (i.e. when two coalitions 
form, each consisting of two players) no payments are made. 

35.3.2. The center of Q represented the only (totally) symmetric game 
in our set-up: with respect to all permutations of the players 1,2,3,4. The 
geometrical picture suggests consideration of another symmetry as well: 
with respect to all permutations of the coordinates x\ 9 x^ x 8 . In this way 
we select the points of Q with 

(?5:9) xi = xi = si, 

which form a main diagonal of Q, the line 
(35:10) 7-center-y777. 

We saw at the beginning of 34.3.1. that this symmetry means precisely 
that the game is invariant with respect to all permutations of the players 
1,2,3. In other words: 

1 This representation shows once more that the game is symmetric, and uniquely 
characterized by this property. Cf. the analysis of 28.2.1. 



SPECIAL POINTS IN THE CUBE Q 303 

The main diagonal (35:9), (35:10) represents all those games which are 
symmetric with respect to the players 1,2,3, i.e. where only player 4 may 
have a special role. 

Q has three other main diagonals (//-center- F, ///-center- F/, /F-center 
F//), and they obviously correspond to those games where another player 
(players 1,2,3, respectively) alone may have a special role. 

Let us return to the main diagonal (35:9), (35:10). The three games 
which we have previously considered (/, F///, Center) lie on it; indeed in 
all these games only player 4 had a special role. 1 Observe that the entire 
category of games is a one-parameter variety. Owing to (35:9), such a 
game is characterized by the value x\ in 

(35:11) -1 g xi ^ 1. 

The three games mentioned above correspond to the extreme values x\ = 1, 
Xi = - 1 and to the middle value Xi = 0. In order to get more insight into 
the working of the exact theory, it would be desirable to determine exact 
solutions for all these values of Xi, and then to see how these solutions shift 
as x\ varies continuously along (35:10). It would be particularly instruc- 
tive to find out how the qualitatively different kinds of solutions recognized 
for the special values x\ = 1, 0, 1 go over into each other. In 36.3.2. 
we shall give indications about the information that is now available in this 
regard. 

35.3.3. Another question of interest is this: Consider a game, i.e. a 
point in Q, where we can form some intuitive picture of what solutions to 
expect, e.g. the corner F///. Then consider a game in the immediate 
neighborhood of F///, i.e. one with only slightly changed values of Xi, x, 
x 3 . Now it would be desirable to find exact solutions for these neighboring 
games, and to see in what details they differ from the solutions of the 
original game, i.e. how a small distortion of x\, xj, x s distorts the solu- 
tions. 2 Special cases of this problem will be considered in 36.1.2., and at 
the end of 37.1.1., as well as in 38.2.7. 

35.3.4. So far we have considered games that are represented by points 
of Q in more or less special positions. 8 A more general, and possibly more 
typical problem arises when the representative point X is somewhere 
in the interior of Q, in "general" position, i.e. in a position with no 
particular distinguishing properties. 

Now one might think that a good heuristic lead for the treatment of 
the problem in such points is provided by the following consideration. We 
have some heuristic insight into the conditions at the corners /-F/// (cf. 
35.1. and 35.2.). Any point X of Q is somehow "surrounded" by these 
corners; more precisely, it is their center of gravity, if appropriate weights 

1 In the center not even he. 

1 This procedure is familiar in mathematical physics, where it is used in attacking 
problems which cannot be solved in their general form for the time being: it is the analysis 
of perturbations. 

8 Corners, the center, and entire main diagonals. 



304 ZERO-SUM FOUR-PERSON GAMES 

are used. Hence one might suspect that the strategy of the games, repre- 
sented by X, is in some way a combination of the strategies of the (more 
familiar) strategies of the games represented by 1 -VI II. One might even 
hope that this " combination " will in some sense be similar to the formation 
of the center of gravity which related X to I-VIII. 1 

We shall see in 36.3.2. and in 38.2.5.7. that this is true in limited parts 
of Q, but certainly not over all of Q. In fact, in certain interior areas of Q 
phenomena occur which are qualitatively different from anything exhibited 
by I'VIII. All this goes to show what extreme care must be exercised in 
dealing with notions involving strategy, or in making guesses about them. 
The mathematical approach is in such an early stage at present that much 
more experience will be needed before one can feel any self-assurance in 
this respect. 

36. Discussion of the Main Diagonals 
36.1. The Part Adjacent to the Corner VIII.: Heuristic Discussion 

36.1.1. The systematic theory of the four-person game has not yet 
advanced so far as to furnish a complete list of solutions for all the games 
represented by all points of Q. We are not able to specify even one solution 
for every such game. Investigations thus far have succeeded only in 
determining solutions (sometimes one, sometimes more) in certain parts of 
Q. It is only for the eight corners 1 -VI II that a demonstrably complete 
list of solutions has been established. At the present the parts of Q in 
which solutions are known at all form a rather haphazard array of linear, 
plane and spatial areas. They are distributed all over Q but do not fill it 
out completely. 

The exhaustive list of solutions which are known for the corners I-VIII 
can easily be established with help of the results of Chapters IX and X, 
where these games will be fitted into certain larger divisions of the general 
theory. At present we shall restrict ourselves to the casuistic approach 

1 Consider two points X = |a?i, z 2 , x t \ and Y (t/i, y^ 2/s) in Q. We may view 
these as vectors in L 8 and it is indeed in this sense that the formation of a center of 
gravity 

tX + (1 - t)Y - (toi + (1 - Ol/i, tx* + (1 - Oyt, to, + (1 - <)y,} 

is understood. (Cf. (16:A:c) in 16.2.1.) 

Now if X [xi, z 2 , z| and Y = \yi, y^ 2/3) define the characteristic functions 
v(S) and w(S) in the sense of (34:l)-(34:3) in 34.2.1., then tX + (1 - t)Y will give, by 
the same algorithm, a characteristic function 

u(S) s tv(S) + (1 - /)wOSf). 

(It is easy to verify this relationship by inspection of the formulae which we quoted.) 
And this same u(S) was introduced as center of gravity of v(S) and w() by (27:10) in 
27.6.3. 

Thus the considerations of the text are in harmony with those of 27.6. That we 
are dealing with centers of gravity of more than two points (eight: I-VIII) instead of only 
two, is not essential: the former operation can be obtained by iteration of the latter. 

It follows from these remarks that the difficulties which are pointed out in the text 
below have a direct bearing on 27.6.3., as was indicated there. 



DISCUSSION OF THE MAIN DIAGONALS 



305 



which consists in describing particular solutions in cases where such are 
known. It would scarcely serve the purpose of this exposition to give a 
precise account of the momentary state of these investigations 1 and it 
would take up an excessive amount of space. We shall only give some 
instances which, it is hoped, are reasonably illustrative. 

36.1.2. We consider first conditions on the main diagonal /-Center- VIII 
in Q near its end at VIII, x\ = x 2 = x 3 = 1 (cf . 35.3.3.), and we shall try 




VIII 



The diagonal / Center VIII redrawn 
Center 



Figure 63. 

to extend over the x\ = #2 = 3 > 1 as far as possible. (Cf. Figure 63.) 
On this diagonal 



(36:1) 




_ ^ 

2*! 



1 




when S has 




1 
2 (and 4 belongs to S) 

elements 

2 (and 4 does not belong to S) 
3 
4 



(Observe that this gives (35:1) in 35.1.1. for xi = 1 and (35:6) in 35.2.1. for 
x\ = 1.) We assume that x\ > 1 but not by too much, just how 
much excess is to be permitted will emerge later. Let us first consider this 
situation heuristically. 

Since Xi is supposed to be not very far from 1, the discussion of 35.2. 
may still give some guidance. A coalition of two players from among 



1 This will be done by one of us in subsequent mathematical publications. 



306 ZERO-SUM FOUR-PERSON GAMES 

1,2,3 may even now be the most important strategic aim, but it is no longer 
the only one: the formula (35:7) of 35.2.1. is not true, but instead 

(36:2) v(S u T) > v(S) + v(T) if SnT = 

when T = (4). 1 Indeed, it is easily verified from (36:1) that this excess 
is always 2 2(1 + 1). For x\ = 1 this vanishes, but we have x\ slightly 

> 1, so the expression is slightly > 0. Observe that for the preceding 
coalition of two players other than player 4, the excess in (36 :2) 8 is by 
(36:1) always 2(1 Xi). For x\ = 1 this is 4, and as we have x\ slightly 

> 1, it will be only slightly < 4. 

Thus the first coalition (between two players, other than player 4), 
is of a much stronger texture than any other (where player 4 enters into the 
picture), but the latter cannot be disregarded nevertheless. Since the 
first coalition is the stronger one, it may be suspected that it will form first 
and that once it is formed it will act as one player in its dealings with the 
two others. Then some kind of a three-person game may be expected to 
take place for the final crystallization. 

36.1.3. Taking, e.g. (1,2) for this "first" coalition, the surmised three- 
person game is between the players (1,2), 3,4. 4 In this game the a, 6, c of 
23.1. are a = v((3,4)) = 2x l9 b = v((l,2,4)) = 1, c = v((l,2,3)) = I. 6 
Hence, if we may apply the results obtained there (all of this is extremely 

heuristic!) the player (1,2) gets the amount a = ^ = 1 x\, 

& 

if successful (in joining the last coalition), and a = 2xi if defeated. The 

player 3 gets the amount = ^ = x\ if successful, and b = 1 

z 

if defeated. The player 4 gets the amount 7 = ~ = x\ if success- 

ft 

ful, and c = 1 if defeated. 

Since "first" coalitions (1,3), (2,3) may form, just as well as (1,2), 
there are the same heuristic reasons as in the first discussion of the three- 
person game (in 21. -22.) to expect that the partners of these coalitions will 
split even. Thus, when such a coalition is successful (cf. above), its 

members may be expected to get -^ - 1 each, and when it is defeated 

& 

Xi each. 

36.1.4. Summing up: If these surmises prove correct, the situation is as 
follows: 

1 Unless S * or T, in which case there is always in (36:2). I.e. in the pres- 
ent situation S must have one or two elements. 

2 By footnote 1 above, S has one or two elements and it does not contain 4. 
8 I.e., now S, T are two one-element sets, not containing player 4. 

4 One might say that (1,2) is a juridical person, while 3,4 are, in our picture, natural 
persons. 

* In all the formulae which follow, remember that Xi is near to 1, i.e. presumably 
negative; hence Xi is a gain, and x\ is a loss. 



DISCUSSION OF THE MAIN DIAGONALS 307 

If the "first" coalition is (1,2), and if it is successful in finding an ally, 
and if the player who joins it in the final coalition is player 3, then the 

1 _ /* 1 . T 

players 1,2,3,4 get the amounts ~ S ~ S Xi, 1 respectively. If the 

2i i 

player who joins the final coalition is player 4, then these amounts are 

replaced by "I Xl , 1 ~ X S -1, XL If the "first" coalition (1,2) is not 
& & 

successful, i.e. if the players 3,4 combine against it, then the players get the 
amounts Xi, xi, Xi, x\ respectively. 

If the "first" coalition is (1,3) or (2,3), then the corresponding permuta- 
tion of the players 1,2,3 must be applied to the above. 

36.2. The Part Adjacent to the Corner VIII. : Exact Discussion 

36.2.1. It is now necessary to submit all this to an exact check. The 
heuristic suggestion manifestly corresponds to the following surmise : 
Let V be the set of these imputations : 

~~>, (l - si 1 - 



> 
(36:3) a" = 



- si 1 - xi J 

2 ' 2 I an d the imputations which 

\ originate from these by per- 

' ~~* 1 Xl | muting the players, (i.e. the 



x i x 
" 



components) 1,2,3. 



(Cf. footnote 5, p. 306.) We expect that this V is a solution in the rigorous 
sense of 30.1. if Xi is near to 1 and we must determine whether this is so> 
and precisely in what interval of the x\. 

This determination, if carried out, yields the following result: 

(36: A) The set V of (36:3) is a solution if and only if 

-1 ^ xi g -*. 

This then is the answer to the question, how far (from the starting point 
xi = 1, i.e. the corner VIII) the above heuristic consideration guides to 
a correct result. 1 

36.2.2. The proof of (36: A) can be carried out rigorously without any 
significant technical difficulty. It consists of a rather mechanical disposal 

1 We wish to emphasize that (36: A) does not assert that V is (in the specified range of 
Xi) the only solution of the game in question. However, attempts with numerous 
similarly built sets failed to disclose further solutions for x\ ^ J (i.e. in the range of 
(36:A)). For x\ slightly > I (i.e. slightly outside the range of (36:A)), where the 
V of (36: A) is no longer a solution, the same is true for the solution which replaces it. 
Cf. (36:B) in 36.3.1. 

We do not question, of course, that other solutions of the "discriminatory" type, 
as repeatedly discussed before, always exist. But they are fundamentally different from 
the finite solutions V which are now under consideration. 

These are the arguments which seem to justify our view that some qualitative change 
in the nature of the solutions occurs at 

x\ G (on the diagonal /-center- VIII). 



308 ZERO-SUM FOUR-PERSON GAMES 

of a series of special cases, and does not contribute anything to the clarifica- 
tion of any question of principle. 1 The reader may therefore omit reading 
it if he feels so disposed, without losing the connection with the main course 
of the exposition. He should remember only the statement of the results 
in (36:A). 

Nevertheless we give the proof in full for the following reason: The set 
V of (36:3) was found by heuristic considerations, i.e. without using the 
exact theory of 30.1. at all. The rigorous proof to be given is based on 
30.1. alone, and thereby brings us back to the only ultimately satisfactory 
standpoint, that of the exact theory. The heuristic considerations were 
only a device to guess the solution, for want of any better technique; and 
it is a fortunate feature of the exact theory that its solutions can occasionally 
be guessed in this way. But such a guess must afterwards be justified 
by the exact method, or rather that method must be used to determine in 
what domain (of the parameters involved) the guess was admissible. 

We give the exact proof in order to enable the reader to contrast and 
to compare explicitly these two procedures, the heuristic and the rigorous. 

36.2.3. The proof is as follows: 

If x\ = 1, then we are in the corner VIII, and the V of (36:3) coincides 
with the set which we introduced heuristically (as a solution) in 35.2.3., 
and which can easily be justified rigorously (cf. also footnote 2 on p. 299). 
Therefore we disregard this case now, and assume that 

(36:4) xi > -1. 

We must first establish which sets Ss/= (1,2,3,4) are certainly 
necessary or certainly unnecessary in the sense of 31.1.2. since we are 
carrying out a proof which is precisely of the type considered there. 

The following observations are immediate: 

(36:5) By virtue of (31 :H) in 31.1.5., three-element sets S are cer- 

tainly necessary, two-element sets are dubious, and all other 
sets are certainly unnecessary. 2 

(36:6) Whenever a two-element set turns out to be certainly neces- 

sary, we may disregard all those three-element sets of which it is 
a subset, owing to (31 :C) in 31.1.3. 

Consequently we shall now examine the two-element sets. This of course 
must be done for all the a in the set V of (36:3). 

1 The reader may contrast this proof with some given in connection with the theory of 
the zero-sum two-person game, e.g. the combination of 16.4. with 17.6. Such a proof is 
more transparent, it usually covers more ground, and gives some qualitative elucidation 
of the subject and its relation to other parts of mathematics. In some later parts of this 
theory such proofs have been found, e.g. in 46. But much of it is still in the primitive 
and technically unsatisfactory state of which the considerations which follow are typical. 

* This is due to n - 4. 



DISCUSSION OF THE MAIN DIAGONALS 309 

Consider first those two-element sets S which occur in conjunction 

> 

with a V As aj = 1 we may exclude by (31 :A) in 31.1.3. the possibility 
that S contains 4. S = (1,2) would be effective if a{ + a' 2 ^ v((l,2)), 
i.e. 1 - xi ^ -2xi, xi ^ -1 which is not the case by (36:4). S = (1,3) 

is effective if a( + J ^ v((l,3)), i.e. ^-^ -2*!, Xl - f Thus 

46 

the condition 

(36:7) Xl ^ - i 

which we assume to be satisfied makes its first appearance. S = (2,3) we 

do not need, since 1 and 2 play the same role in a ' (cf. footnote 1 above). 


We now pass to a ". As a' 8 ' = 1 we now exclude the S which contains 3 

(cf. above). S = (1,2) is disposed of as before, since a ' and a " agree in 
these components. S = (1,4) would be effective if a" + a" g v((l,4)), 

i.e. ~ ^ 2xi, xi ^ | which, by (36:7), is not the case. S = (2,4) is 
discarded in the same way. 

Finally we take ~Z r ". S = (1,2) is effective: a'/' + a' 2 " = v((l,2)) 
i.e. 2xj. = 2xi. S = (1,3) need not be considered for the following 

reason: We are already considering S = (1,2) for a '", if we interchange 2 
and 3 (cf. footnote 1 above) this goes over into (1,3), with the components 

-Xi, -XL Our original S = (1,3) for a'" with the components -Xi, Xi 
is thus rendered unnecessary by (31 :B) in 31.1.3., as x t ^ xi owing to 
(36:7). S = (2,3) is discarded in the same way. S = (1,4) would be 
effective if a'/' + a' 4 " g v((l,4)) i.e. g 2x b xi ^ 0, which, by (36:7), is 
not the case. S = (2,4) is discarded in the same way. S = (3,4) is effec- 
tive: ai" + a'/' = v((3,4)), i.e. 2xi = 2 Xl . 
Summing up: 

(36:8) Among the two-element sets S the three given below are 

certainly necessary, and all others are certainly unnecessary: 

(1,3) for ^', (1,2) and (3,4) for T'". 

Concerning three-element sets S: By (31:A) in 31.1.3. we may exclude 
those containing 4 for a ' and 3 for a ". Consequently only (1,2,3) is left 
for ' and (1,2,4) for a". Of these the former is excluded by (36:6), 
as it contains the set (1,3) of (36:8). For ^'" every three-element set 

1 Here, and in the entire discussion which follows, we shall make use of the freedom to 
apply permutations of 1,2,3 as stated in (36:3), in order to abbreviate the argumentation. 
Hence the reader must afterwards apply these permutations of 1,2,3 to our results. 



310 ZERO-SUM FOUR-PERSON GAMES 

contains the set (1,2) or the set (3,4) of (36:8); hence we may exclude it by 
(36:6). 

Summing up : 

(36:9) Among the three-element sets <S, the one given below is 

certainly necessary, and all others are certainly unnecessary: 1 

(1,2,4) for 7". 

36.2.4. We now verify (30:5:a) in 30.1.1., i.e. that no a of V dominates 
any of V. 

^ = a ': By (36:8), (36:9) we must use S = (1,3). Can a ' dominate 
with this S any 1,2,3 permutation of a ' or a " or a '"? This requires first 

the existence of a component < x\ (this is the 3 component of a. ') among 


the 1,2,3 components of the imputation in question. Thus a' and a'" 


are excluded. 2 Even in a " the 1,2 components are excluded (cf. footnote 2) 

but the 3 component will do. But now another one of the 1,2,3 components 

of this imputation a " must be < ~ - 1 (this is the 1 component of a ') 

Z 

and this is not the case; the 1,2 components of a. " are both = - 1 - 

& 

a. = a ": By (36:8), (36:9) we must use S = (1,2,4). Can a " dominate 

with this S any 1,2,3 permutation of a ' or a " or a '"? This requires first 
that the 4 component of the imputation in question be < x\ (this is the 

4 component of a")- Thus a "and a "' are excluded. For a 'we must 

require further that two of its 1,2,3 components be < -^ (this is the 1 


as well as the 2 component of a "), and this is not the case; only one of these 

components is 5* ~ *" 

"a* = 1?'": By (36:8), (36:9) we must use S = (1,2) and then S = (3,4). 

5 = (1,2) : Can a'" dominate with this as described above? This requires 
the existence of two components < zi (this is the 1 as well as the 2 com- 

~"* 
ponent of a'") among the 1,2,3 components of the imputation in question. 

This is not the case for a'", as only one of these components is j& x\ 

1 As every three-element set is certainly necessary by (36:5) above, this is another 
instance of the phenomenon mentioned at the end of footnote 1 on p. 274. 

1 Indeed 5^ a?i, i.e. x\ rand -x\ x\, i.e. Xi both by (36:7). 

V 



DISCUSSION OF THE MAIN DIAGONALS 311 

* * 

there. Nor is it the case for a ' or a ", as only one of those components is 

1 x\ * 

?* s there. 1 S = (3,4): Can a '" dominate with this S as described 

t 

above? This requires first that the 4 component of the imputation in 

> 

question be < Xi (this is the 4 component of a "'). Thus a " and a '" are 


excluded. For a ' we must require further the existence of a component 

< x\ (this is the 3 component of a '") among its 1,2,3 components, and 
this is not the case; all these components are ^ Xi (cf. footnote 2 on p. 310). 
This completes the verification of (30:5:a). 

36.2.5. We verify next (30:5 :b) in 30. 1.1., i.e. that an imputation ft which 
is undominated by the elements of V must belong to V. 

Consider a ft undominated by the elements of V. Assume first that 
04 < Xi. If any one of 0i, 2 , 03 were < Xi, we could make (by permuting 

1,2,3) 3 < XL This gives 7'" H 7 with S = (3,4) of (36:8). Hence 

ft i, 02, 03 ^ XL 
If any two of 0i, 2 , 03 were < ~ 1 , we could make (by permuting 1,2.3) 



0i, 02 < ~V^' This gives a " H with S = (1,2,4) of (36:9). Hence, 
2 

at most one of 0i, 2 , 3 i 
1,2,3, we can thus make 



at most one of 0i, 2 , 3 is < ~ - i.e. two are ^ Xl - By permuting 



Clearly 4 ^ 1. Thus each component of is ^ the corresponding com- 
ponent of a ' , and since both are imputations 2 it follows that they coincide: 

= a ', and so it is in V. 

Assume next that 4 ^ x\. If any two of 0i, 2 , 0s were < Xi, we 

* > 
could make (by permuting 1,2,3) 0i, 2 < XL This gives a"' H with 

S = (1,2) of (36:8). Hence, at most one of 0i, 2 , 0s is < Xi, i.e. two are 
^ XL By permuting 1,2,3 we can make 

01, 02 S -Xi. 

If 0s ^ *i, then all this implies that each component of is ^ the cor- 

1 And i-^- 1 -xi, i.e. xi -1. 

2 Consequently for both the sum of all components is the same: zero. 



312 ZERO-SUM FOUR-PERSON GAMES 

responding component of a '", and since both are imputations (cf . footnote 2, 
on p. 311) it follows that they coincide: ft = a '", and so it is in V. 

Assume therefore that fa < XL If any one of 0i, fa were < ~ "' 

I x\ * * 

we could make (by permuting 1,2) fa < ^ This gives a'H ft 

& 

with 5 = (1,3) of (36:8). Hence 

A, A ^ ^J- 



Clearly 8 ^ 1. Thus each component of ft is g: the corresponding com- 
ponent of a", and since both are imputations (cf. footnote 2, p. 311), it 

follows that they coincide: ft = a ", and so it is in V. 
This completes the verification of (SOiSib). 1 
So we have established the criterion (36: A). 2 

36.3. Other Parts of the Main Diagonals 

36.3.1. When Xi passes outside the domain (36 :A) of 36.2.1., i.e. when 
it crosses its border at x\ = i, then the V of (36:3) id. ceases to be a 
solution. It is actually possible to find a solution which is valid for a certain 
domain in x\ > i (adjoining x\ = i), which obtains by adding to the 
V of (36:3) the further imputations 

(36:10) a lv = I j^- 1 , xi, s - 1 , xi\ and permutations as in 



(36:3). 3 

The exact statement is actually this: 
(36 :B) The set V of (36:3) and (36:10) is a solution if and only if 

- i < x, < O. 4 

1 The reader will observe that in the course of this analysis all sets of (36:8), (36:9) 
have been used for dominations, and had to be equated successively to all three a ', a ", 

"7"' of (36:3). 

f Concerning zi = 1, cf. the remarks made a-t the beginning of this proof. 

3 An inspection of the above proof shows that when x\ becomes > J, this goes 

wrong: The set S (1,3) (and with it (2,3)) is no longer effective for a '. Of course this 
rehabilitates the three-element set = (1,2,3) which was excluded solely because (1,3) 
(and (2,3)) is contained in it. 



.Thus domination by this element of V, a ', now becomes more difficult, and it is 
therefore not surprising that an increase of the set V must be considered in the search 
for a solution. 

4 Observe the discontinuity at x\ J which belongs to (36: A) and not to (36:B)l 
The exact theory is quite unambiguous, even in such matters. 



THE CENTER AND ITS ENVIRONS 313 

The proof of (36 :B) is of the same type as that of (36: A) given above, 
and we do not propose to discuss it here. 

The domains (36 :A) and (36 :B) exhaust the part xi ^ of the entire 
available interval 1 g x\ g 1 i.e. the half F/77-Center of the diagonal 
V/77-Center-/. 

36.3.2. Solutions of a nature similar to V described in (36 :A) of 36.2.1. 
and in (36 :B) of 36.3.1., have been found on the other side x\ > i.e. 
the half Center-/ of the diagonal as well. It turns out that on this half, 
qualitative changes occur of the same sort as in the first half covered by 
(36: A) and (36 :B). Actually three such intervals exist, namely: 

(36 :C) ^ xi < i, 

(36 :D) i < xi g *, 

(36:E) | g Xl g 1. 

(Cf. Figure 64, which is to be compared with Figure 63.) 

VIII Omtw J 

x * 



*. - -i -* o * 4 i 

Figure 64. 

We shall not discuss the solutions pertaining to (36 :C), (36:D), (36 :E). 1 
The reader may however observe this: x\ = appears as belonging 
to both (neighboring) domains (36 :B) and (36 :C), and similarly xi = i to 
both domains (36 :D) and (36 :E). This is so because, as a close inspection 
of the corresponding solutions V shows that while qualitative changes in the 
nature of V occur at x\ = and i, these changes are not discontinuous. 

The point Xi = i, on the other hand, belongs to neither neighboring 
domain (36 :C) or (36 :D). It turns out that the types of solutions V which 
are valid in these two domains are both unusable at x\ = i. Indeed, the 
conditions at this point have not been sufficiently clarified thus far. 

37. The Center and Its Environs 
$7.1. First Orientation Concerning the Conditions around the Center 

37.1.1. The considerations of the last section were restricted to a one- 
dimensional subset of the cube Q: The diagonal FJ/7-center-/. By using 
the permutations of the players 1,2,3,4, as described in 34.3., this can be 
made to dispose of all four main diagonals of Q. By techniques that are 
similar to those of the last section, solutions can also be found along some 
other one-dimensional lines in Q. Thus there is quite an extensive net of 
lines in Q on which solutions are known. We do not propose to enumerate 
them, particularly because the information that is available now corresponds 
probably to only a transient state of affairs. 

1 Another family of solutions, which also cover part of the same territory, will be 
discussed in 38.2. Cf. in particular 38.2.7., and footnote 2 on p. 328. 



314 ZERO-SUM FOUR-PERSON GAMES 

This, however, should be said: such a search for solutions along isolated 
one-dimensional lines, when the whole three-dimensional body of the cube Q 
waits for elucidation, cannot be more than a first approach to the problem. 
If we can find a three-dimensional part of the cube even if it is a small 
one for all points of which the same qualitative type of solutions can be 
used, we shall have some idea of the conditions which are to be expected. 
Now such a three-dimensional part exists around the center of Q. For this 
reason we shall discuss the conditions at the center. 

37.1.2. The center corresponds to the values 0,0,0 of the coordinates 
x\, #2, #3 and represents, as pointed out in 35.3.1., the only (totally) sym- 
metric game in our set-up. The characteristic function of this game is : 



(37:1) v(S) = 




-1 



when S has 

1 







1 

2 elements. 

3 

4 



(Cf. (35:8) id.) As in the corresponding cases in 35.1., 35.2., 36.1., we begin 
again with a heuristic analysis. 

This game is obviously one in which the purpose of all strategic efforts 
is to form a three-person coalition. A player who is left alone is clearly a 
loser, any coalition of 3 in the same sense a winner, and if the game should 
terminate with two coalitions of two players each facing each other, then 
this must obviously be interpreted as a tie. 

The qualitative question which arises here is this: The aim in this 
game is to form a coalition of three. It is probable that in the negotiations 
which precede the play a coalition of two will be formed first. This coalition 
will then negotiate with the two remaining players, trying to secure the 
cooperation of one of them against the other. In securing the adherence 
of this third player, it seems questionable whether he will be admitted into 
the final coalition on the same conditions as the two original members. 
If the answer is affirmative, then the total proceeds of the final coalition, 1, 
will be divided equally among the three participants: i, |, . If it is 
negative, then the two original members (belonging to the first coalition 
of two) will probably both get the same amount, but more than . Thus 1 
will be divided somewhat like this: i + c, i + c, i 2e with an e > 0. 

37.1.3. The first alternative would be similar to the one which we 
encountered in the analysis of the point / in 35.1. Here the coalition 
(1,2,3), if it forms at all, contains its three participants on equal terms. 
The second alternative corresponds to the situation in the interval analyzed 
in 36.1. -2. Here any two players (neither of them being player 4) combined 
first, and this coalition then admitted either one of the two remaining play- 
ers on less favorable terms. 

37.1.4. The present situation is not a perfect analogue of either of these. 



THE CENTER AND ITS ENVIRONS 315 

In the first case the coalition (1,2) could not make stiff terms to player 3 
because they absolutely needed him: if 3 combined with 4, then 1 and 2 
would be completely defeated; and (1,2) could not, as a coalition, combine 
with 4 against 3, since 4 needed only one of them to be victorious (cf. the 
description in 35.1.3.). In our present game this is not so: the coalition 
(1,2) can use 3 as well as 4, and even if 3 and 4 combine against it, only a 
tie results. 

In the second case the discrimination against the member who joins 
the coalition of three participants last is plausible, since the original coali- 
tion of two is of a much stronger texture than the final coalition of three. 
Indeed, as x\ tends to 1, the latter coalition tends to become worthless; cf. 
the remarks at the end of 36.1.2. In our present game no such qualitative 
difference can be recognized: the first coalition (of two) accounts for the 
difference between defeat and tie, while formation of the final coalition (of 
three) decides between tie and victory. 

We have no satisfactory basis for a decision except to try both alterna- 
tives. Before we do this, however, an important limitation of our consider- 
ations deserves attention. 

37.2. The Two Alternatives and the Role of Symmetry 

37.2.1. It will be noted that we assume that the same one of the two 
alternatives above holds for all four coalitions of three players. Indeed, we 
are now looking for symmetric solutions only, i.e. solutions which contain, 

along with an imputation a = {i, 2 , a, QU}, all its permutations. 

Now a symmetry of the game by no means implies in general the 
corresponding symmetry in each one of its solutions. The discriminatory 
solutions discussed in 33.1.1. make this clear already for the three-person 
game. We shall find in 37.6. further instances of this for the symmetric 
four-person game now under consideration. 

It must be expected, however, that asymmetric solutions for a symmetric 
game are of too recondite a character to be discovered by a first heuristic 
survey like the present one. (Cf. the analogous occurrence in the three- 
person game, referred to above.) This then is our excuse for looking at 
present only for symmetric solutions. 

37.2.2. One more thing ought to be said: it is not inconceivable that, 
while asymmetric solutions exist, general organizational principles, like 
thflse corresponding to our above two alternatives, are valid either for the 
totality of all participants or not at all. This surmise gains some strength 
from the consideration that the number of participants is still very low, and 
may actually be too low to permit the formation of several groups of par- 
ticipants with different principles of organization. Indeed, we have only 
four participants, and ample evidence that three is the minimum number 
for any kind of organization. These somewhat vague considerations will 
find exact corroboration in at least one special instance in (43 :L) et seq. of 
43.4.2. For the present case, however, we are not able to support them by 
any rigorous proof. 



316 ZERO-SUM FOUR-PERSON GAMES 

87.3. The First Alternative at the Center 

37.3.1. Let us now consider the two alternatives of 37.1.2. We take 
them up in reverse order. 

Assume first that the two original participants admit the third one 
under much less favorable conditions. Then the first coalition (of two) 
must be considered as the core on which the final coalition (of three) crystal- 
lizes. In this last phase the first coalition must therefore be expected to 
act as one player in its dealings with the two others, thus bringing about 
something like a three-person game. If this view is sound, then we may 
repeat the corresponding considerations of 36.1.3. 

Taking, e.g. (1,2), as the "first" coalition, the surmised three-person 
game is between the players (1, 2), 3,4. The considerations referred to 
above therefore apply literally, only with changed numerical values: a = 0, 
6 = c = 1 and so a = 1, ft = y = O. 1 

Since the "first" coalition may consist of any two players, there are 
heuristic reasons similar to those in the discussion of the three-person game 
(in 21. -22.) to expect that the partners in it will split even: when an ally is 
found, as well as when a tie results, the amount to be divided being 1 or 
respectively. 2 

37.3.2. Summing up: if the above surmises prove correct, the situation is 
as follows: 

If the "first" coalition is (1,2) and if it is successful in finding an 
ally, and if the player who joins it in the final coalition is 3, then the players 
1,2,3,4 get the amounts , ,0, 1 respectively. If the "first" coalition 
is not successful, i.e. if a tie results, then these amounts are replaced by 
0,0,0,0. 

If the distribution of the players is different, then the corresponding 
permutation of the players 1,2,3,4 must be applied to the above. 

It is now necessary to submit all this to an exact check. The heuristic 
suggestion manifestly corresponds to the following surmise : 

Let V be the set of these following imputations 

C\7-9\ a ' = ^' i> 0> ~M and the imputations which originate from 

^"=(00001 these by permuting the players (i.e. the 

components) 1,2,3,4. 

We expect that this V is a solution. 

1 The essential difference between this discussion and that referred to, is that player 4 
is no longer excluded from the " first" coalition. 

1 The argument in this case is considerably weaker than in the case referred to (or in 
the corresponding application in 36,1.3.) since every "first" coalition may now wind up 
in two different ways (tie or victory). The only satisfactory decision as to the value of 
the argumentation obtains when the exact theory is applied. The desired justification is 
actually contained in the proof of 38.2.1. -3.; indeed, it is the special case 

y\ - y* - y* - y* - l 
of (38:D) in 38.2.3. 



THE CENTER AND ITS ENVIRONS 317 

A rigorous consideration, of the same type as that which constitutes 
36.2., shows that this V is indeed a solution in the sense of 30.1. We do 
not give it here, particularly because it is contained in a more general proof 
which will be given later. (Cf. the reference of footnote 2 on p. 316.) 

37.4. The Second Alternative at the Center 

37.4.1. Assume next that the final coalition of three contains all its 
participants on equal terms. Then if this coalition is, say (1,2,3), the players 
1,2,3,4 get the amounts i, i; i, 1 respectively. 

It would be rash to conclude from this that we expect the set of impu- 
tations V to which this leads, to be a solution; i.e. the set of these imputa- 
tions a = {i, 2, <*3, a*}> 

(37:3) a '" = (i, i, i, -1} and permutations as in (37:2). 

We have made no attempt as yet to understand how this formation of the 
final coalition in "one piece " comes about, without assuming the previous 
existence of a favored two-person core. 

37.4.2. In the previous solution of (37 :2) such an explanation is discern- 
able. The stratified form of the final coalition is expressed by the imputa- 
tion a ' and the motive for just this scheme of distribution lies in the threat 

~-* "-* 

of a tie, expressed by the imputation a ". To put it exactly: the a ' form a 

solution only in conjunction with the a ", and not by themselves. 

In (37:3) this second element is lacking. A direct check in the sense 

of 30.1. discloses that the a "' fulfill condition (30:5 :a) there, but not (30:5 :b). 
I.e. they do not dominate each other, but they leave certain other imputa- 
tions undominated. Hence further elements must be added to V. 1 

This addition can certainly not be the a" = {0,0,0,0) of (37:2) since 
that imputation happens to be dominated by a '". 2 In other words the 

extension (i.e. stabilization, in the sense of 4.3.3.) of a '" to a solution must 
be achieved by entirely different imputations (i.e. threats) in the case of 

the ~^'" of (37:3) as in the case of the ~' of (37:2). 

It seems very difficult to find a heuristic motivation for the steps which 
are now necessary. Luckily, however, a rigorous procedure is possible 
from here on, thus rendering further heuristic considerations unnecessary, 

1 To avoid misunderstandings : It is by no means generally true that any set of imputa- 
tions which do not dominate each other can be extended to a solution. Indeed, the 
problem of recognizing a given set of imputations as being a subset of some (unknown) 
solution is still unsolved. Cf . 30.3.7. 

In the present case we are just expressing the hope that such an extension will prove 
possible for the V of (37:3), and this hope will be further justified below. 

With S - (1,2,3). 



318 ZERO-SUM FOUR-PERSON GAMES 

Indeed, one can prove rigorously that there exists one and only one sym- 
metric extension of the V of (37:3) to a solution. This is the addition of 

these imputations a = {ai, a2, as, <**} 

(37:4) ~2 IV = (i, i, - i, - *} and permutations as in (37:2). 

37.4.3. If a common-sense interpretation of this solution, i.e. of its 
constituent a lv of (37:4), is wanted, it must be said that it does not seem to 

be a tie at all (like the corresponding a " of (37:2)) rather, it seems to be 
some kind of compromise between a part (two members) of a possible 
victorious coalition and the other two players. However, as stated above, 
we do not attempt to find a full heuristic interpretation for the V of (37:3) 
and (37:4) ; indeed it may well be that this part of the exact theory is already 
beyond such possibilities. 1 Besides, some subsequent examples will 
illustrate the peculiarities of this solution on a much wider basis. Again 
we refrain from giving the exact proof referred to above. 

37.5. Comparison of the Two Central Solutions 

37.6.1. The two solutions (37:2) and (37:3), (37:4), which we found 
for the game representing the center, present a new instance of a possible 
multiplicity of solutions. Of course we had observed this phenomenon 
before, namely in the case of the essential three-person game in 33. 1 . 1 . But 
there all solutions but one were in some way abnormal (we described this by 
terming them " discriminatory"). Only one solution in that case was a 
finite set of imputations; that solution alone possessed the same symmetry 
as the game itself (i.e. was symmetric with respect to all players). This 
time conditions are quite different. We have found two solutions which are 
both finite sets of imputations, 2 and which possess the full symmetry of the 
game. The discussion of 37.1.2. shows that it is difficult to consider either 
solution as " abnormal" or "discriminatory" in any sense; they are distin- 
guished essentially by the way in which the accession of the last participant 
to the coalition of three is treated, and therefore seem to correspond to two 
perfectly normal principles of social organization. 

37.5.2. If anything, the solution (37:3), (37:4) may seem the less normal 
one. Both in (37:2) and in (37:3), (37:4) the character of the solution was 

determined by those imputations which described a complete decision, a ' 
> t ^ 

and a "' respectively. To these the extra " stabilizing" imputations, a " 
> t > 

and a /v , had to be added. Now in the first solution this extra a " had an 

1 This is, of course, a well known occurrence in mathematical-physical theories, even 
if they originate in heuristic considerations. 

* An easy count of the imputations given and of their different permutations shows 
that the solution (37:2) consists of 13 elements, and the solution (37:3), (37:4) of 10. 



THE CENTER AND ITS ENVIRONS 319 

obvious heuristic interpretation as a tie, while in the second solution the 

nature of the extra a IV appeared to be more complex. 

A more thorough analysis discloses, however, that the first solution 
is surrounded by some peculiar phenomena which can neither be explained 
nor foreseen by the heuristic procedure which provided easy access to this 
solution. 

These phenomena are quite instructive from a general point of view too, 
because they illustrate in a rather striking way some possibilities and 
interpretations of our theory. We shall therefore analyze them in some 
detail in what follows. We add that a similar expansion of the second 
solution has not been found up to now. 

37.6. Unsymmetrical Central Solutions 

37.6.1. To begin with, there exist some finite but asymmetrical solutions 
which are closely related to (37:2) in 37.3.2. because they contain some of the 
imputations {i, i, 0, 1 J. 1 One of these solutions is the one which obtains 
when we approach the center along the diagonal /-Center- V7// from either 
side, and use there the solutions referred to in 36.3. I.e.: it obtains by 
continuous fit to the domains (36 :B) and (36 :C) there mentioned. (It 
will be remembered that the point Xi = 0, i.e. the center, belongs to both 
these domains, cf. 36.3.2.) Since this solution can be taken also to express 
a sui generis principle of social organization, we shall describe it briefly. 

This solution possesses the same symmetry as those which belong to the 
games on the diagonal /-Center- VIII, as it is actually one of them : symmetric 
with respect to players 1,2,3, while player 4 occupies a special position. 2 
We shall therefore describe it in the same way we did the solutions on 
the diagonal, e.g. in (36:3) in 36.2.1. Here only permutations of the 
players 1,2,3 are suppressed, while in the descriptions of (37:3) and (37:4) we 
suppressed all permutations of the players 1,2,3,4. 

37.6.2. For the sake of a better comparison, we restate with this notation 
(i.e. allowing for permutations of 1,2,3 only) the definition of our first fully- 
symmetric solution (37:2) in 37.3.2. It consists of these imputations: 8 

7' = (i,i,o, -i} 

. ft" = {i, i, 1,0} and the imputations which originate from 

"?/// (in 1 \\ these by permuting the players 1,2,3. 
P = tii U, l, i> 

7 /v = {0,0,0,0} 

1 I.e. some but not all of the 12 permutations of this imputation. 

* That the position of player 4 in the solution is really different from that of the others, 
is what distinguishes this solution from the two symmetric ones mentioned before. 

Our 7', 7", 7"' exhaust the a' of (37:2) in 37.3.2., while ^ is a ", id. 

_ _ * . 

a ' had to be represented by the three imputations ', ", ft '" because this 
system of representation makes it necessary to state in which one of the three possible 
positions of that imputation (i.e. the values }, 0, 1) the player 4 is found. 



320 ZERO-SUM FOUR-PERSON GAMES 

Now the (asymmetric) solution to which we refer consists of these 
imputations: 

?' "a*" "?" QQintt7'9*^ and the imputations which origi- 
(37:5) V P ' P asm^/.z ; nate from these by permuting the 

F = (4,0, -*, Op players 1,2,3. 

Once more we omit giving the proof that (37:5) is a solution. Instead 
we shall suggest an interpretation of the difference between this solution 
and that of (37:2) i.e. of the first (symmetric) solution in 37.3.2. 

37.6.3. This difference consists in replacing 

7'" = (4,0, -i,i) 
by 

7 F = (4,0, -4,0}. 

That is: the imputation ft '" in which the player 4 would belong to the 
"first" coalition (cf. 37.3.1.), i.e. to the group which wins the maximum 

amount is removed, and replaced by another imputation ft y . Player 4 
now gets somewhat less and the losing player among 1,2,3 (in this arrange- 
ment player 3) gets somewhat more than in ft '". This difference is pre- 
cisely 4, so that player 4 is reduced to the tie position 0, and player 3 moves 
from the completely defeated position 1 to an intermediate position 4 

Thus players 1,2,3 form a " privileged " group and no one from the out- 
side will be admitted to the "first" coalition. But even among the three 
members of the privileged group the wrangle for coalition goes on, since 
the "first" coalition has room for two participants only. It is worth noting 
that a member of the privileged group may even be completely defeated, as 

in ft ", but only by a majority of his " class " who form the " first " coalition 
and who may admit the "unprivileged" player 4 to the third membership 
of the "final" coalition, to which he is eligible. 

37.6.4. The reader will note that this describes a perfectly possible form 
of social organization. This form is discriminatory to be sure, although 
not in the simple way of the "discriminatory" solutions of the three-person 
game. It describes a more complex and a more delicate type of social 
inter-relation, due to the solution rather than to the game itself. 2 One 
may think it somewhat arbitrary, but since we are considering a "society" 
of very small size, all possible standards of behavior must be ad justed rather 
precisely and delicately to the narrowness of its possibilities. 

We scarcely need to elaborate the fact that similar discrimination 
against any other player (1,2,3 instead of 4) could be expressed by suitable 

> 

1 This imputation ft v is reminiscent in its arrangement of a /F in (37:4) of 37.4.2., 
but it has not been possible to make anything of that analogy. 
1 As to this feature, cf. the discussion of. 35.2.4. 



NEIGHBORHOOD OF THE CENTER 321 

solutions, which could then be associated with the three other diagonals 
of the cube Q. 

38. A Family of Solutions for a Neighborhood of the Center 
38.1. Transformation of the Solution Belonging to the First Alternative at the Center 

38.1.1. We continue the analysis of the ramifications of solution (37:2) 
in 37.3.2. It will appear that it can be subjected to a peculiar transforma- 
tion without losing its character as a solution. 

This transformation consists in multiplying the imputations (37:2) of 
37.3.2. by a common (positive) numerical factor z. In this way the follow- 
ing set of imputations obtains: 

f^K-n ^ ' = |2' 2* ^ ~ Z | anc ^ ^ e i m Putations which originate from 
__ these by permuting the players 1,2,3,4. 

7" = {0,0,0,0} 

In order that these be imputations, all their components must be ^ 1 
(i.e. the common value of the v((i)). As z > this means only that 
z ^ 1, i.e. we must have 

(38:2) < z ^ 1. 

For z = 1 our (38:1) coincides with (37:2) of 37.3.2. It would not seem 
likely a priori that (38:1) should be a solution for the same game for any 
other z of (38:2). And yet a simple discussion shows that it is a solution 
if and only if z > $ i.e. when (38*:2) is replaced by 

(38:3) f < z g 1. 

The importance of this family of solutions is further increased by the fact 
that it can be extended to a certain three-dimensional piece surrounding 
the center of the cube Q. We shall give the necessary discussion in full, 
because it offers an opportunity to demonstrate a technique that may be of 
wider applicability in these investigations. 

The interpretation of these results will be attempted afterwards. 

38.1.2. We begin by observing that consideration of the set V defined 
by the above (38:1) for the game described by (37:1) in 37.1.2. (i.e. the 
center of Q), could be replaced by consideration of the original set V of 
(37:2) in 37.3.2. in another game. Indeed, our (38:1) was obtained from 
(37:2) by multiplying by z. Instead of this we could keep (37:2) and 
multiply the characteristic function (37:1) by l/z; this would destroy the 
normalization 7 = 1 which was necessary for the geometrical representation 
by Q (cf. 34.2.2.) but we propose to accept that. 

What we are now undertaking can be formulated therefore as follows: 
So far we have started with a given game, and have looked for solutions. 
Now we propose to reverse this process, starting with a solution and looking 



322 ZERO-SUM FOUR-PERSON GAMES 

for the game. Precisely: we start with a given set of imputations Vi and 
ask for which characteristic function v(S) (i.e. games) this V is a solution. 1 
Multiplication of the v(S) of (37:1) in 37.1.2. by a common factor means 
that we still demand 

(38:4) v(/S) = when S is a two-element set, 

but beyond this only the reduced character of the game (cf. 27.1.4.), i.e. 

(38:5) v((l)) = v((2)) - v((3)) - v((4)). 

Indeed, this joint value of (38:5) is l/z and therefore (38:4), (38:5) and 
(25:3:a) (25:3:b) in 25.3.1. yield that this v(S) is just (37:1) multiplied by 
l/z. Our assertion (38:3) above means that the V of (37:2) in 37.3.2. is a 
solution for (38:4), (38:5) if and only if the joint value of (38:5) (i.e. - l/z) 
is ^ 1 and > f. 

38.1.3. Now we shall go one step further and drop the requirement of 
reduction, i.e. (38:5). So we demand of v(S) only (38:4), restricting its 
values for two-element sets S. We restate the final form of our question: 

(38: A) Consider all zero-sum four-person games where 
(38:6) v(S) =0 for all two-element sets S. 

For which among these is the set V of (37:2) in 37.3.2. a solution? 

It will be noted that since we have dropped the requirements of normal- 
ization and reduction of v(S) all connections with the geometrical represen- 
tation in Q are severed. A special manipulation will be necessary therefore 
at the end, in order to put the results which we shall obtain back into the 
framework of Q. 

38.2. Exact Discussion 
38.2.1. The unknowns of the problem (38: A) are clearly the values 

(38:7) v((l = -2/1, v((2)) = -2/2, v((3)) = -2/3, v((4)) = -y 4 . 

We propose to determine what restrictions the condition in (38 :A) actually 
places on these numbers 2/1, 2/*> 2/a, 2/4. 

1 This reversed procedure is quite characteristic of the elasticity of the mathematical 
method for the kind and degree of freedom which exists there. Although initially it 
deflects the inquiry into a direction which must be considered unnatural from any but 
the strictest mathematical point of view, it is nevertheless effective; by an appropriate 
technical manipulation it finally discloses solutions which have not been found in any 
other way. 

After our previous examples where the guidance came from heuristic considerations, 
it is quite instructive to study this case where no heuristic help is relied on and solutions 
are found by a purely mathematical trick, the reversal referred to above. 

For the reader who might be dissatisfied with the use of such devices (i.e. exclusively 
technical and non-conceptual ones), we submit that they are freely and legitimately used 
in mathematical analysis. 

We have repeatedly found the heuristic procedure easier to handle than the rigorous 
one. The present case offers an example of the oooosite. 



NEIGHBORHOOD OF THE CENTER 323 

This game is no longer symmetric. 1 Hence the permutations of the 
players 1,2,3,4 are now legitimate only if accompanied by the corresponding 
permutations of yi, y^ y&, y^ 

To begin with, the smallest component with which a given player k is 
ever associated in the vectors of (37:2) in 37.3.2., is 1. Hence the vectors 
will be imputations if and only if 1 *z v((fc)) i.e. 

(38:8) y k *l for k = 1,2,3,4. 

The character of V as a set of imputations is thus established; let us 
now see whether it is a solution. This investigation is similar to the proof 
given in 36.2.3-5. 

38.2.2. The observations (36:5), (36:6), of 36.2.3., apply again. A two- 
element set S = (i, j) is effective for a = {i, #2, s, ouj when a + ay ^ 

(cf. (38:A)). Hence we have for the a ', a" of (37:2): In a " every two- 



element set S is effective. In a ' : No two-element set S which does not con- 
tain the player 4 is effective, while those which do contain him, S = (1,4), 
(2,4), (3,4) clearly are. However, if we consider S = (1,4), we may discard 
the two others; S = (2,4) arises from it by interchanging 1 and 2, which 

does not affect a '; 3 S = (3,4) is actually inferior to it after 1 and 3 are 
interchanged, since i ^ O. 4 
Summing up: 

(38 :B) Among the two-element sets S, those given below are cer- 

tainly necessary, and all others are certainly unnecessary: 

(1,4) for 7', 6 all for 7". 

Concerning three-element sets: Owing to the above we may exclude by 
(36:6) all three-element sets for a ", and for a ' those which contain (1,4) or 

(2,4). 6 This leaves only S = (1,2,3) for a '. 
Summing up: 

(38 :C) Among the three-element sets S, the one given below is 

certainly necessary, and all others are certainly unnecessary: 

(1,2,3) for 7'. 

1 Unless y\ y* y\ y<. 

2 But there is nothing objectionable in such uses of the permutations of 1,2,3,4 as we 
made in the formulation of (37:2) in 37.3.2. 

8 This permutation and similar ones later are clearly legitimate devices in spite of 
footnote 1 above. Observe footnote 1 on p. 309 and footnote 2 above. 

4 As i 1 we could discard all these sets, including S (1,4), when v((4)) 1; 
i.e. when 2/4 1, which is a possibility. But we are under no obligation to do this. We 
prefer not to do it, in order to be able to treat 3/4 1 and j/ 4 > 1 together. 

6 And all permutations of 1,2,3,4; these modify a ' too. 

6 The latter obtains from the former by interchanging 1 and 2, which does not affect a '. 



324 ZERO-SUM FOUR-PERSON GAMES 

We leave to the reader the verification of (30:5 :a) in 30.1.1., i.e. that no 
> 

a 'of V dominates any ft of V. (Cf . the corresponding part of the proof in 

36.2.4. Actually the proof of (30:5:b), which follows, also contains the 
necessary steps.) 

38.2.3. We next verify (30:5:b) in 30.1.1., i.e. that an imputation ft 

which is undominated by the elements of V must belong to V. 

> 
Consider a ft undominated by the elements of V. If any two of fa, 182, 

0s, ft 4 were < 0, we could make these (by permuting 1,2,3,4) fa, 2 < 0. 

> 

This gives a " H ft with S = (1,2) of (38:B). Hence at most one of fa, 2 , 


03, 4 is < 0. If none is < 0, then all are ^ 0. So each component of ft 

is < the corresponding component of a", and since both are imputations 

(cf. footnote 2 on p. 311), it follows that they coincide, ft = a"; and so 
it is in V. 

Hence precisely one of 0i, 2 , 0s, ft 4 is < 0. By permuting 1,2,3,4 we 
can make it 4 . 

If any two of fa, ft*, 3 were < i, we could make these (by permuting 
1,2,3) ft i, 02 < i. Besides, 4 < 0. So the interchange of 3 and 4 gives 

a ' H ft with S = (1,2,3) of (38:C). Hence at most one of fa, fa, 3 is < i. 
Ifnoneis<, then0i,0 2 , 3 ^i. Hence 4 ^ f. But0 4 ^ v((4)) = -y 4 , 
so this necessitates 1/ 4 ^ $, i.e. $/ 4 ^ f . Thus we need i/ 4 < f to 
exclude this possibility, and as we are permuting freely 1,2,3,4, we even need 

(38:9) y k < } for k = 1,2,3,4. 

If this condition is satisfied, then we can conclude that precisely one of 
fa, 02, 0a is < i. By permuting 1,2,3, we can make it 3 . 

So 0i, 02 ^ i, 03 ^ 0. If 4 ^ - 1, 1 then each component of is ^ the 

> 

corresponding component of a ', and since both are imputations (cf . foot- 
note 2 on p. 311) it follows that they coincide: = a' and so it is in V. 

Hence 4 < 1. Also 3 < i. So interchange of 1 and 3 gives 

~^' H 7 with S = (1,4) of (38 :B). 

This, at last, is a contradiction, and thereby completes the verification 
of (30:5 :b) in 30.1. 1. 

The condition (38:9), which we needed for this proof, is really necessary: 
it is easy to verify that 

7' = i*,*,*, -i} 

1 If v((4)) 1, i.e. if y 4 1, then this is certainly the case; but we do not wish 
to assume it. (Cf. footnote 4 on p. 323.) 



NEIGHBORHOOD OF THE CENTER 325 

is undominated by our V, and the only way to prevent it from being an 
imputation is to have | < v((4)) = y 4 , i.e. 2/4 < f. 1 Permuting 1,2,3,4 
then gives (38:9). 

Thus we need precisely (38:8) and (38:9). Summing up: 

(38 :D) The V of (37:2) in 37.3.2. is a solution for a game of (38 :A) 

(with (38:6), (38:7) there) if and only if 

(38:10) 1 ^ y k < | for h = 1,2,3,4. 

38.2.4. Let us now reintroduce the normalization and reduction which 
we abandoned temporarily, but which are necessary in order to refer these 
results to Q, as pointed out immediately after (38: A). 

The reduction formulae of 27.1.4. show that the share of the player fc 
must be altered by the amount ajj where 



= yk - i(2/i + 2/2 + 2/3 + 2/4) 
and 



7 = - 

= i(2/i + 2/2 + 2/3 + 2/0- 

For a two-element set S = (i, j), v(S) is increased from its original value to 

<*? + a = 2A + 2/7 - i(2/i + 2/2 + 2/3 + 2/4) 
= i(2/ + 2/y - yk - yi) 

(fc, I are the two players other than i, j). 

The above y is clearly ^ 1 > (by (38:10)), hence the game is essential. 
The normalization is now carried out by dividing the characteristic function, 
as well as every player's share, by y. Thus for S = (t, j), v(S) is now 
modified further to 



, 

y 2/i + y* + 2/3 + 2/4 

This then is the normalized and reduced form of the characteristic 
function, as used in 34.2.1. for the representation by Q. (34:2) id. gives, 
together with the above expression, the formulae 

1 Observe that the failure of V to dominate this ' could not be corrected by adding 

ft ' to V (when j/ 4 ^ !). Indeed, ft ' dominates a " - (0,0,0,0) with S (1,2,3), so 



it would be necessary to remove a " from V, thereby creating new undominated 
imputations, etc. 

If t/j t/j 2/ t y 4 ss | t then a change of unit by f brings our game back to the 

form (37:1) of 37.1.2., and it carries the above ft ' into the o IV - { J, i, i, -1| of (37:3) 
in 37.4.1. Thus further attempts to make our V over into a solution would probably 
transform it gradually into (37:3), (37:4) in 37.4.1-2. This is noteworthy, since we 
started with (37:2) in 37.3.2. 

These connections between the two solutions (37:2) and (37:3), (37:4) should be 
investigated further. 



326 



ZERO-SUM FOUR-PERSON GAMES 



(38:11) 



x _ yi ~ 2/2 - 2/8 + 2/4^ 

1 2/1 + 2/2 + 2/3 + 2/4' 

= -2/i + 2/2 2/8 + 2/4 ; 

* 2/1 + #2 + 2/8 + 2/4 

_ -2/i -- 2/2 + ys + 2/4 ; 
8 yi + 2/2 + 2/8 + 2/4 ' 



for the coordinates x\, x*, X* in Q. 

38.2.5. Thus (38:10) and (38:11) together define the part of Q in which 
these solutions i.e. the solution (37:2) in 37.3.2., transformed as indicated 
above can be used. This definition is exhaustive, but implicit. Let us 
make it explicit. I.e., given a point of Q with the coordinates zi, x^ 3, 
let us decide whether (38:10) and (38:11) can then be satisfied together (by 
appropriate 2/1, 2/2, 2/s, 2/4). 

We put for the hypothetical yi, 2/2, 2/8, i/ 4 



2/i + 2/2 + 2/s + 2/4 = - 



(38:12) 

with z indefinite. Then the equations (38:11) become 



(38:12*) 



, xi 

2/i y* ~ 2/3 + 2/4 = > 



, 
-2/i + 2/2 - 2/3 



2/4 = > 
z 



-2/i - 2/2 "h 2/8 + 2/4 = 8> 



(38:12) and (38:12*) can be solved with respect to 2/1, 2/2, 2/s, 

1 + Xi x z x 9 

i/ \ ~~~ 

(38:13) 



I 



z 

-* + 



2/2 = 



2/4 = 



1 + Xi + X 2 



Now (38:11) is satisfied, and we must use our freedom in choosing z to 
satisfy (38:10). 

Let w be the greatest and v the smallest of the four numbers 



(38:14) 



+ 



These are known quantities, since Zi, x 2 , 0:3 are assumed to be given. 

Now (38:10) clearly means that 1 ^ v/z and that w/z < $ , i.e. it means 
that 

(38:15) $w <zgv. 

Obviously this condition can be fulfilled (for z) if and only if 

^38:16) fu; < v. 



NEIGHBORHOOD OF THE CENTER 327 

And if (38:16) is satisfied, then condition (38:15) allows infinitely many 
values an entire interval for z. 

38.2.6. Before we draw any conclusions from (38:15), (38:16), we give 
the explicit formulae which express what has become of the solution (37:2) 
of 37.3.2. owing to our transformations. We must take the imputations 

* * 

a ', a ", loc. cit., add the amount a* to the component k (i.e. to the player fc's 

share), and divide this by y. 

These manipulations transform the possible values of the component k 

which are i, 0, 1 in (37:2) as follows. We consider first k = 1, and 
use the above expressions for a k and y as well as (38:13). Then: 



1 g0 e 8 into *5! = 2 + 4y. - (y. + y. + y, + 

2 y i + a + 3 + 4 



Ogoesinto^ = ** - (if. + If. + If. + *) = Xl - Xt - Xt , 
y yi + yt + yt + yt 

_ ! goes into Jll+Jf = -4 + 4.-(yt + * + * + .) 



2/1 + 2/2 + ^8 + 2/4 

= Z + Xi ~ Zj ~ X|. 

For the other k = 2,3,4 these expressions are changed only in so far that their 
Xi X2 zs is replaced by Xi + x 2 z 8 , Zi 2 + Zs, Zi + 2 + z$, 
respectively. 1 

Summing up (and recalling (38:14)): 

(38 :E) The component fc is transformed as follows: 

i goes into z/2 + w* 1, 
goes into u k 1, 
1 goes into z + uu 1, 
with the Wi, w 2 , MS, u 4 of (38:14). 

We leave it to the reader to restate (37:2) with the modification (38 :E), 
paying due attention to carrying out correctly the permutations 1,2,3,4 
which are required there. 

It will be noted that for the center i.e. x\ = x 8 = X* = (38 :E) 
reproduces the formulae (38:1) of 38.1.1., as it should. 

38.2.7. We now return to the discussion of (38:15), (38:16). 

Condition (38:16) expresses that the four numbers 1*1, W2, u*, M 4 of (38:14) 
are not too far apart that their minimum is more than f of their maximum 
i.e. that on a relative scale their sizes vary by less than 2:3. 

This is certainly true at the center, where x\ = x* = X* = 0; there 
ui, t*2, MS, ^4 are all =1. Hence in this case v = w = 1, and (38:15) 

1 This is immediate, owing to the form of the equations (38:13), and equally by con- 
sidering the influence of the permutations of the players 1,2,3,4 on the coordinates 
Xi, xj, xs as described in 34.3.2. 



328 ZERO-SUM FOUR-PERSON GAMES 

becomes f < z g 1 proving the assertions made earlier in this discussion 
(cf. (38:3) in 38.1.1.). 

Denote the part of Q in which (38:16) is true by Z. Then even a 
sufficiently small neighborhood of the center belongs to Z. 1 So Z is a 
three-dimensional piece in the interior of Q, containing the center in its own 
interior. 

We can also express the relationship of Z to the diagonals of Q, say to 
/-Center- VIIL Z contains the following parts of that diagonal. (Use 
Figure 64) : on one side precisely C, on the other a little less than half of 
J3.* We add that these solutions are different from the family of solu- 
tions valid in (36 :B) and (36 :C) which were referred to in 36.3. 

38.3. Interpretation of The Solutions 

38.3.1. The family of solutions which we have thus determined possesses 
several remarkable features. 

We note first that for every game for which this family is a solution 
at all (i.e. in every point of Z) it gives infinitely many solutions. 1 And all 
we said in 37.5.1. applies again: these solutions are finite sets of imputations* 
and possess the full symmetry of the game. 6 Thus there is no " discrimina- 
tion " in any one of these solutions. Nor can the differences in "organi- 
zational principles," which we discussed loc. cit., be ascribed to them. There 
is nevertheless a simple " organizational principle' 1 that can be stated in a 
qualitative verbal form, to distinguish these solutions. We proceed to 
formulate it. 

38.3.2. Consider (38 :E), which expresses the changes to which (37:2) 
in 37.3.2. is to be subjected. It is clear that the worst possible outcome 
for the player k in this solution is the last expression (since this corresponds 
to 1), i.e. z + Uk 1. This expression is > or = 1, according to 
whether z is < or = u k . Now Wi, w 2 , MS, w 4 are the four numbers of (38:14), 
the smallest of which is v. By (38:15) z v, i.e. always z + w* 1 ^ 1, 
and = occurs only for the greatest possible value of z, z = v, and then 
only for those k for which Uk attains its minimum, v. 

1 If Xi, xs, Xi differ from by < A then each of the four numbers MI, MJ, MI, u 4 of (38:14) 
is < 1 -f A I and > 1 A 1 ; hence on a relative size they vary by < J : t f. 
So we are still in Z. In other words: Z contains a cube with the same center as Q, but 
with A of Q's (linear) size. 

Actually Z is somewhat bigger than this, its .volume is about yAo of the volume of Q. 

* On that diagonal x\ x x t , so the MI, MI, MI, M 4 are: (three times) 1 x\ and 
1 -f 3xi. So for zi 0, v - 1 - x b w - 1 + 3xi, hence (38:16) becomes x\ < J. 
And for si g 0, v - 1 + 3xi, w - 1 - Xi, hence (38:16) becomes > - A. So the 
intersection is this: 

Xi < t (this is precisely C) 
xi > - A (B is xi > - i). 

1 The solution which we found contained four parameters: y\, yi, y t , y* while the games 
for which they are valid had only three parameters: &i, x>, x v . 

4 Each one has 13 elements, like (37:2) in 37.3.2. 

1 In the center xi - x t - x t - we have y\ - y* - y* - y 4 (cf. (38:13)), i.e. sym- 
metry in 1,2,3,4. On the diagonal Xi - x t - x 9 we have j/i - y f - y t (cf. (38:13)), i.e. 
symmetry in 1,2,3. 



NEIGHBORHOOD OF THE CENTER 329 

We restate this: 

(38 :F) In this family of solutions, even as the worst possible outcome, 

a player k faces, in general, something that is definitely better 
than what he could get for himself alone, i.e. v((fc)) = 1. 
This advantage disappears only when z has its greatest possible 
value, z = v, and then only for those k for which the correspond- 
ing number iii, w 2 , w 8 , w 4 in (38:14) attains the minimum in 
(38:14). 

In other words: In these solutions a defeated player is in general not 
11 exploited " completely, not reduced to the lowest possible level the level 
which he could maintain even alone, i.e. v((fc)) = 1. We observed 
before such restraint on the part of a victorious coalition, in the "milder" 
kind of "discriminatory" solutions of the three-person game discussed in 
33.1. (i.e. when c > 1, cf. the end of 33.1.2.). But there only one player 
could be the object of this restraint in any one solution, and this phenomenon 
went with his exclusion from the competition for coalitions. Now there is 
no discrimination or segregation; instead this restraint applies to all players 
in general, and in the center of Q ((38:1) in 38.1.1., with z < 1) the solution 
is even symmetric! 1 

38.3.3. Even when z assumes its maximum value v, in general only one 
player will lose this advantage, since in general the four numbers ui, wj, MS, 
Ui of (38:14) are different from each other and only one is equal to their 
minimum v. All four players will lose it simultaneously only if u\, w, Wt, u\ 
are all equal to their minimum v i.e. to each other and one look at 
(38:14) suffices to show that this happens only when x\ = x\ = x\ = 0, 
i.e. at the center. 

This phenomenon of not "exploiting" a defeated player completely is a 
very important possible (but by no means necessary) feature of our solu- 
tions, i.e. of social organizations. It is likely to play a greater role in the 
general theory also. 

We conclude by stating that some of the solutions which we mentioned, 
but failed to describe in 36.3.2., also possess this feature. These are the 
solutions in C of Figure 64. But nevertheless they differ from the solutions 
which we have considered here. 

1 There is a quantitative difference of some significance as well. Both in our present 
set-up (four-person game, center of Q) and in the one referred to (three-person game in 
the sense of 33.1.), the best a player can do (in the solutions which we found) is J, and 
the worst is 1. 

The upper limit of what he may get in case of defeat, in those of our solutions where 
he is not completely " exploited," is now - J (i.e. -z with \ < z 1) and it was \ then 

(i.e. c with 1 & c < J). So this zone now covers the fraction . __ ( 1) ** 4 "* 9* 
i.e. 22| % of the significant interval, while it then covered 100%. 



CHAPTER VIII 
SOME REMARKS CONCERNING n 5 PARTICIPANTS 

39. The Number of Parameters in Various Classes of Games 
39.1. The Situation for n = 3,4 

39.1. We know that the essential games constitute our real problem 
and that they may always be assumed in the reduced form and with 7 = 1. 
In this representation there exists precisely one zero-sum three-person 
game, while the zero-sum four-person games form a three-dimensional 
manifold. 1 We have seen further that the (unique) zero-sum three-person 
game is automatically symmetric, while the three-dimensional manifold 
of all zero-sum four-person games contains precisely one symmetric game. 

Let us express this by stating, for each one of the above varieties of 
games, how many dimensions it possesses, i.e. how many indefinite param- 
eters must be assigned specific (numerical) values in order to characterize a 
game of that class. This is best done in the form of a table, given in Figure 
65 in a form extended to all n ^ 3. 2 Our statements above reappear in 
the entries n = 3,4 of that table. 

39.2. The Situation for All n 3 

39.2.1. We now complete the table by determining the number of 
parameters of the zero-sum n-person game, both for the class of all these 
games, and for that of the symmetric ones. 

The characteristic function is an aggregate of as many numbers v(S) 
as there are subsets S in / = (1, , n), i.e. of 2 n . These numbers are 
subject to the restrictions (25:3:a)-(25:3:c) of 25.3.1., and to those due to the 
reduced character and the normalization 7 = 1, expressed by (27:5) in 
27.2. Of these (25:3:b) fixes v(-S) whenever v(S) is given, hence it 
halves the number of parameters: 3 so we have 2 n ~ l instead of 2 n . Next 
(25 :3 :a) fixes one of the remaining v (S) : v () ; (27 :5) fixes n of the remaining 
v(S):v((l)), , v((n)); hence they reduce the number of parameters 
by n + I. 4 So we have 2 n ~ l n 1 parameters. Finally (25:3:c) need 
not be considered, since it contains only inequalities. 

39.2.2. If the game is symmetric, then v(S) depends only on the number 
of elements p of S: v(S) = v p , cf. 28.2.1. Thus it is an aggregate of as 
many numbers v p as there are p = 0, 1, , n, i.e. n + 1. These 

1 Concerning the general remarks, cf. 27.1.4. and 27.3.2.; concerning the zero-sum 
three-person game cf. 29.1.2.; concerning the zero-sum four-person game cf. 34.2.1. 
* There are no essential zero-sum games for n 1,2! 
8 S and S are never the same set! 

4 S Q t (1), , (n) differ from each other and from each other's complements. 

330 



NUMBER OF PARAMETERS 



331 



numbers are subject to the restrictions (28:ll:a)-(28:ll:c) of 28.2.1.; the 
reduced character is automatic, and we demand also Vi = y = 1. 
(28:11 :b) fixes v w _ p when v p is given; hence it halves the numbers of those 
parameters for which n-p^p. When n - p = p l i.e. n = 2p, which hap- 
pens only when n is even, and then p = n/2 (28:11 :b) shows that this v p 






must vanish. So we have ^ parameters if n is odd and 5 if n is even, 

instead of the original n + 1. Next (28:ll:a) fixes one of the remaining 
v p : Vo) and Vi = 7 = 1 fixes another one of the remaining v p : Vi; 

hence they reduce the number of parameters by 2: 2 so we have 



- 2 



n 



or ^ ~ 2 parameters. Finally (28:ll:c) need not be considered since it 

contains only inequalities. 

39.2.3. We collect all this information in the table of Figure 65. We also 
state explicitly the values arising by specialization to n = 3,4,5,6,7,8, 
the first two of which were referred to previously. 



Number 
of players 


All games 


Symmetric 


games 


3 


0* 


0* 


4 


3 


0* 


5 


10 


1 


6 


25 


1 


7 


56 


2 


8 


119 


2 




. . . 


. . . 


n 




Of 


or n odd 
n even 


2 
|-2for 



* Denotes the game is unique. 

Figure 65. Essential games. (Reduced and y 1.) 

The rapid increase of the entries in the left-hand column of Figure 65 
may serve as another indication, if one be needed, how the complexity of a 
game increases with the number of its participants. It seems noteworthy 

1 Contrast this with footnote 3 on p. 330! 

1 p - 0, 1 differ from each other and from each other's n - p. (The latter only 
because of n 3.) 



332 REMARKS CONCERNING n 5 PARTICIPANTS 

that there is an increase in the right-hand column too, i.e. for the symmetric 
games, but a much slower one. 

40. The Symmetric Five -person Game 
40.1. Formalism of the Symmetric Five-person Game 

40.1.1. We shall not attempt a direct attack on the zero-sum five-person 
game. The systematic theory is not far enough advanced to allow it; 
and for a descriptive and casuistic approach (as used for the zero-sum, 
four-person game) the number of its parameters, 10, is rather forbidding. 

It is possible however to examine the symmetric zero-sum five-person 
games in the latter sense. The number of parameters, 1, is small but not 
zero, and this is a qualitatively new phenomenon deserving consideration. 
For n = 3,4 there existed only one symmetric game, so it is for n = 5 
that it happens for the first time that the structure of the symmetric game 
shows any variety. 

40.1.2. The symmetric zero-sum five- person game is characterized by the 
v p , p = 0,1,2,3,4,5 of 28.2.1., subject to the restrictions (28:ll:a)-(28:ll:c) 
formulated there. (28:ll:a), (28:ll:b) state (with 7 = 1) 

(40:1) v = 0, vi=-l, v 4 = 1, v 6 = 

and v 2 = v 3 , i.e. 

(40:2) v 2 = -ij, v 3 = 7j 

Now (28:ll:c) states v p + g ^ v p + v q for p + q ^ 5 and we can subject 
PJ q to the further restrictions of (28:12) id. Therefore p = 1, q = 1,2,* 
and so these two inequalities obtain (using (40:1), (40:2)): 

p = 1, q = 1: -2 ^ -17; p = 1, q = 2: 1 i? ^ iy; 
i.e. 

(40:3) - i g rj g 2. 

Summing up: 

(40 :A) The symmetric zero-sum five-person game is characterized 

by one parameter t\ with the help of (40:1), (40:2). The domain 
of variability of y is (40:3). 

40.2. The Two Extreme Cases 

40.2.1. It may be useful to give a direct picture of the symmetric games 
described above. Let us first consider the two extremes of the interval 
(40:3): 

1 = 2, - *. 

1 This is easily verified by inspection of (28:12), or by using the inequalities of foot- 
note 2 on p. 250. These give 1 p f , 1 ^ 4 j 2; hence as p, q are integers, p 1, 

q - 1,2. 



THE SYMMETRIC FIVE-PERSON GAME 333 

Consider first 17 = 2: In this case v(S) = 2 for every two-element 
set S; i.e. every coalition of two players is defeated. 1 Thus a coalition of 
three (being the set complementary to the former) is a winning coalition. 
This tells the whole story: In the gradual crystallization of coalitions, the 
point at which the passage from defeat to victory occurs is when the size 
increases from two to three, and at this point the transition is 100 %. 2 

Summing up: 

(40 :B) 77 = 2 describes a game in which the only objective of all 

players is to form coalitions of three players. 

40.2.2. Consider next 17 = i. In this case we argue as follows: 



1 



when S has 



4 



elements. 



A coalition of four always wins. 3 

Now the above formula shows that a coalition of two is doing just as 
well, pro ratdj as a coalition of four; hence it is reasonable to consider the 
former just as much winning coalitions as the latter. If we take this 
broader view of what constitutes winning, we may again affirm that the 
whole story of the game has been told: In the formation of coalitions, the 
point at which the passage from defeat to victory occurs is when the size 
increases from one to two; at this point the transition is 100 %. 4 

Summing up: 

(40 :C) rj = i describes a game in which the only objective of all 

players is to form coalitions of two players. 

40.2.3. On the basis of (40 :B) and (40 :C) it would be quite easy to guess 
heuristically solutions for their respective games. This, as well as the 
exact proof that those sets of imputations are really solutions, is easy ; but 
we shall not consider this matter further. 

Before we pass to the consideration of the other rj of (40:3) let us remark 
that (40 :B) and (40 :C) are obviously the simplest instances of a general 

1 Cf. the discussion in 35.1.1., particularly footnote 4 on p. 296. 

2 One player is just as much defeated as two, four are no more victorious than three. 
Of course a coalition of three has no motive to take in a fourth partner ; it seems (heuristi- 
cally) plausible that if they do they will accept him only on the worst possible terms. But 
nevertheless such a coalition of four wins if viewed as a unit, since the remaining isolated 
player is defeated. 

8 In any zero-sum n-person game any coalition of n 1 wins, since an isolated player 
is always defeated. Cf. loc. cit. above. 

4 One player is defeated, two or four players are victorious. A coalition of three 
players is a composite case deserving some attention : v (S) is J for a three-element set 
S t i.e. it obtains from the i of a two-element set by addition of 1. Thus a Coalition of 
three is no better than a winning coalition of two (which it contains) plus the remaining 
isolated and defeated player separately. This coalition is just a combination of a. win- 
ning and a defeated group whose situation is entirely unaltered by this operation. 



334 REMARKS CONCERNING n 5 PARTICIPANTS 

method of defining games. This procedure (which is more general than that 
of Chapter X, referred to in footnote 4 on p. 296) will be considered exhaus- 
tively elsewhere (for asymmetric games also). It is subject to some restric- 
tions of an arithmetical nature ; thus it is clear that there can be no (essential 
symmetric zero-sum) n-person game in which every coalition of p is winning 
if p is a divisor of n, since then n/p such coalitions could be formed and every- 
body would win with no loser left. On the other hand the same requirement 
with p = n 1 does not restrict the game at all (cf. footnote 3, p. 333). 

40.3. Connection between the Symmetric Five-person Game and the 1,2,3-symmetric 

Four-person Game 

40.3.1. Consider now the rj in the interior of (40:3). The situation is 
somewhat similar to that discussed at the end of 35.3. We have some 
heuristic insight into the conditions at the two ends of (40:3) (cf. above). 
Any point ry of (40:3) is somehow " surrounded " by these end-points. More 
precisely, it is their center of gravity if appropriate weights are used. 1 
The remarks made loc. cit. apply again: while this construction represents 
all games of (40:3) as combinations of the extreme cases (40 :B), (40 :C), it 
is nevertheless not justified to expect that the strategies of the former can 
be obtained by any direct process from those of the latter. Our experiences 
in the case of the zero-sum four-person game speak for themselves. 

There is, however, another analogy with the four-person game which 
gives some heuristic guidance. The number of parameters in our case is the 
same as for those zero-sum four-person games which are symmetric with 
respect to the players 1,2,3; we have now the parameter 77 which runs over 

(40:3) - i ^ T? g 2, 

while the games referred to had the parameter x\ which varies over 

(40:4) -1 ^ xi I. 2 

This analogy between the (totally) symmetric five-person game and the 
1,2,3-symmetric four-person game is so far entirely formal. There is, 
however, a deeper significance behind it. To see this we proceed as follows : 

40.3.2. Consider a symmetric five-person game F with its 77 in (40:3). 
Let us now modify this game by combining the players 4 and 5 into one 
person, i.e. one player 4'. Denote the new game by F'. It is important to 
realize that F' is an entirely new game: we have not asserted that in F 
players 4 and 5 will necessarily act together, form a coalition, etc., or that 
there are any generally valid strategical considerations which would moti- 
vate just this coalition. 8 We have forced 4 and 5 to combine; we did this 
by modifying the rules of the game and thereby replacing F by F'. 

1 The reader can easily carry out this composition in the sense of footnote 1 on p. 304, 
relying on our equations (40:1), (40:2) in 40.1.2. 

* Cf . 35.3.2. In the representation in Q used there, x\ = xt x t . 

9 This ought to be contrasted with the discussion in 36.1.2., where a similar combina- 
tion of two players was formed under such conditions that this merger seemed strategi- 
cally justified. 



THE SYMMETRIC FIVE-PERSON GAME 335 

Now T is a symmetric five-person game, while r' is a 1,2,3-symmetric 
four-person game. 1 Given the > of T we shall want to determine the 
xi of I" in order to see what correspondence of (40:3) and (40:4) this defines. 
Afterwards we shall investigate whether there are not, in spite of what was 
said above, some connections between the strategies i.e. the solutions of 
T and T'. 

The characteristic function v'(S) of r' is immediately expressible in 
terms of the characteristic function v(S) of T. Indeed: 

v'((l)) = v((l)) = -1, v'((2)) = v((2)) = -1, 

v'((3)) = v((3)) = -1, v'((4')) = v((4,5)) = -i,; 

v'((l,2)) = v((l,2)) = -,, v'((l,3)) = v((l,3)) = -n, 

v'((2,3)) = v((2,3)) . -,, v'((l,4')) = v((l,4,5)) - ,, 

v'((2,4')) = v((2,4,5)) = , v'((3,4')) = v((3,4,5)) = ,; 

v'((l,2,3)) = v((l,2,3)) = n, v'((l,2,4')) = v((l,2,4,5)) = 1, 

v'((l,3,4')) = v((l,3,4,5)) = 1, v'((2,3,4')) = v((2,3,4 > 5)) = 1; 

and of course 

v'(0) = v'((l,2,3,4')) = 0. 

While F was normalized and reduced, r" is neither; and we must bring 
T' into that form since we want to compute its x\, 2, 3, i-e. refer it to the 
Q of 34.2.2. 

Let us therefore apply first the normalization formulae of 27.1.4. They 
show that the share of the player k = 1,2,3,4' must be altered by the 
amount ajj where 

al =, - 
and 

7 = - 
Hence 



_ 

3 l 5 
This 7 is clearly ^ ^~ = ^ > (by (40:3)); hence the game is 

essential. The normalization is now carried out by dividing every player's 
share by 7. 

Thus for a two-element set S = (i, j), v'(S) is replaced by 



7 
Consequently a simple computation yields 



o -t- i? 
v"((l,4')) = v"((2,4')) = v"((3,4')) = 2(3 " ~ 1} - 

1 The participants in r are players 1,2,3,4,5, who all have the same role in the original 
T. The participants in r' are players 1,2,3 and the composite player (4,5) : 4'. Clearly 
1,2,3 have still the same role, but 4' is different. 



336 REMARKS CONCERNING n 5 PARTICIPANTS 

This then is the normalized and reduced form of the characteristic 
function, as used in 34.2. for the representation by Q. (34:2) in 34.2.1 
gives, together with the above expression, the formula 



Taking x\ = x* = x* for granted, this relation can also be written as follows: 
(40:5) (3 - xO(3 + n) = 10. 

Now it is easy to verify that (40:5) maps the Tj-domain (40:3) on the 
Xi-domain (40:4). The mapping is obviously monotone. Its details are 
shown in Figure 66 and in the adjoining table of corresponding values of 
xi and 17. The curve in this figure represents the relation (40:5) in the x\ 9 
ly-plane. This curve is clearly (an arc of) a hyperbola. 

40.3.3. Our analysis of the 1,2,3-symmetric four-person game has 
culminated in the result stated in 36.3.2.: The game, i.e. the diagonal 
7-Center-V7/7 in Q which represents them, is divided into five classes 
A-E, each of whrch is characterized by a certain qualitative type of 
solutions. The positions of the zones A-E on the diagonal 7-Center- 
VIII, i.e. the interval 1 g x\ ^ 1, are shown in Figure 64. 

The present results suggest therefore the consideration of the cor- 
responding classes of symmetric five-person games F in the hope that some 
heuristic lead for the detection of their solutions may emerge from their 
comparison with the 1,2,3-symmetric four-person games F, class by class. 

Using the table in Figure 66 we obtain the zones A-E in ^ 17 g 2, 
which are the images of the zones A-E in 1 x\ ^ 1. The details 
appear in Figure 67. 

A detailed analysis of the symmetric five-person games can be carried 
out on this basis. It discloses that the zones A, B do indeed play the role 
which we expect, but that the zones C, D, E must be replaced by others, 
<?', D'. These zones A-D' in ^ t\ z* 2 and their inverse images A-D' 
in 1 ^ Xi ^ 1 (again obtained with the help of the table of Figure 66) 
are shown in Figure 68. 

It is remarkable that the Zi-diagram of Figure 68 shows more symmetry 
than that of Figure 67, although it is the latter which is significant for the 
1,2,3-symmetric four-person games. 

40.3.4. The analysis of symmetric five-person games has also some 
heuristic value beyond the immediate information it gives. Indeed, by 
comparing the symmetric five-person game F and the 1,2,3-symmetric 
four-person game F' which corresponds to it, and by studying the differences 
between their solutions, one observes the strategic effects of the merger 
of players 4 and 5 in one (composite) player 4'. To the extent to which the 
solutions present no essential differences (which is the case in the zones A, 
B, as indicated above) one may say that this merger did not affect the really 



THE SYMMETRIC FIVE-PERSON GAME 337 




Figure 66. 
Corresponding values of Xi and 17: 

*i: -1 -I -i } J i J 1 
*:-!- i i A ! 1 2 



1 


A \ I 


< |C| D \ B | 




-I 




t i 1 






1 A 


1 B \C\ D I fi 


1 



o t i A I i 
Figure 67. 



I B | C- 



-t- 



-l 



-i o 

A 1*1*1 



Figure 68. 



338 REMARKS CONCERNING n 5 PARTICIPANTS 

significant strategic considerations. 1 On the other hand, when such differ- 
ences arise (this happens in the remaining zones) we face the interesting 
situation that even when 4 and 5 happen to cooperate in T, their joint 
position is dislocated by the possibility of their separation. 2 

Space forbids a fuller discussion based on the rigorous concept of solutions. 

1 Of course one must expect, in solutions of F, arrangements where the players 4 and 5 
are ultimately found in opposing coalitions. It is clear that this can have no parallel 
in F'. All we mean by the absence of essential differences is that those imputations in a 
solution of T which indicate a coalition of 4 and 5 should correspond to equivalent imputa- 
tions in the solution of r'. 

These ideas require further elaboration, which is possible, but it would lead too far 
to undertake it now. 

1 Already in 22.2., our first discussion of the three-person game disclosed that the 
division of proceeds within a coalition is determined by the possibilities of each partner 
in case of separation. But this situation which we now visualize is different. In our 
present r it can happen that even the total share of player 4 plus player 5 is influenced 
by this "virtual" fact. 

A qualitative idea of such a possibility is best obtained by considering this : When a 
preliminary coalition of 4 and 5 is bargaining with prospective further allies, their bar- 
gaining position will be different if their coalition is known to be indissoluble (in r') 
than when the opposite is known to be a possibility (in r). 



CHAPTER IX 
COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

41. Composition and Decomposition 
41.1. Search for n-person Games for Which All Solutions Can Be Determined 

41.1.1. The last two chapters will have conveyed a specific idea of the 
rapidity with which the complexity of our problem increases as the number 
n of participants goes to 4,5, etc. In spite of their incompleteness, 
those considerations tended to be so voluminous that it must seem com- 
pletely hopeless to push this casuistic approach beyond five participants. 1 
Besides, the fragmentary character of the results gained in this manner very 
seriously limits their usefulness in informing us about the general possibilities 
of the theory. 

On the other hand, it is absolutely vital to get some insight into the 
conditions which prevail for the greater values of n. Quite apart from the 
fact that these are most important for the hoped for economic and socio- 
logical applications, there is also this to consider: With every increase of 
n, qualitatively new phenomena appeared. This was clear for each of 
n = 2,3,4 (cf. 20.1.1., 20.2., 35.1.3., and also the remarks of footnote 2 
on p. 221), and if we did not observe it for n = 5 this may be due to our 
lack of detailed information about this case. It will develop later, (cf. the 
end of 46.12.), that very important qualitative phenomena make their 
first appearance for n = 6. 

41.1.2. For these reasons it is imperative that we find some technique 
for the attack on games with higher n. In the present state of things we 
cannot hope for anything systematic or exhaustive. Consequently the 
natural procedure is to find some special classes of games involving many 
participants 2 that can be decisively dealt with. It is a general experience 
in many parts of the exact and natural sciences that a complete under- 
standing of suitable special cases which are technically manageable, but 
which embody the essential principles has a good chance to be the pace- 
maker for the advance of the systematic and exhaustive theory. 

We will formulate and discuss two such families of special cases. They 
can be viewed as extensive generalizations of two four-person games so 
that each one of these will be the prototype of one of the two families. 
These two four-person games correspond to the 8 corners of the cube Q, 
introduced in 34.2.2.: Indeed, we saw that those corners presented only 

1 As was seen in Chapter VIII, it was already necessary for five participants to 
restrict ourselves to the symmetric case. 

1 And in such a manner that each one plays an essential role! 

339 



340 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

two strategically different types of games the corners /, Vj VI, VII, 
discussed in 35.1. and the corners //, ///, IV, VIII, discussed in 35.2. 
Thus the corners / and VIII of Q are the prototypes of those generaliza- 
tions to which this chapter and the following one will be devoted. 

41.2. The First Type. Composition and Decomposition 

41.2.1. We first consider the corner VIII of Q, discussed in 35.2. As 
was brought out in 35.2.2. this game has the following conspicuous feature: 
The four participants fall into two separate sets (one of three elements and 
the other of one) which have no dealings with each other. I.e. the players 
of each set may be considered as playing a separate game, strictly among 
themselves and entirely unrelated to the other set. 

The natural generalization of this is to a game F of n = A; + I par- 
ticipants, with the following property: The participants fall into two sets of 
k and I elements, respectively, which have no dealings with each other. 
I.e. the players of each set may be considered playing a separate game, say 
A and H respectively, strictly among themselves and entirely unrelated 
to the other set. 1 

We will describe this relationship between the games T, A, H by the 
following nomenclature: Composition of A, H produces F, and conversely 
F can be decomposed into the constituents A, H. 2 

41.2.2. Before we deal with the above verbal definitions in an exact 
way, some qualitative remarks may be appropriate: 

First, it should be noted that our procedure of composition and decompo- 
sition is closely analogous to one which has been successfully applied in 
many parts of modern mathematics. 3 As these matters are of a highly 
technical mathematical nature, we will not say more about them here. 
Suffice it to state that our present procedure was partly motivated by those 
analogies. The exhaustive but not trivial results, which we shall obtain 

1 In the original game of 35.2. the second set consisted of one isolated player, who was 
also termed a " dummy." This suggests an alternative generalization to the above one: 
A game in which the participants fall into two sets such that those of the first set play a 
game strictly among themselves etc., while those of the second set have no influence upon 
the game, neither regarding their own fate, nor that of the others. (These are then the 
"dummies.") 

This is, however, a special case of the generalization in the text. It is subsumed in 
it by taking the game H of the second set as an inessential one, i.e. one which has a definite 
value for each one of its participants that cannot be influenced by anybody. (Cf. 27.3.1. 
and the end of 43.4.2. A player in an inessential game could conceivably deteriorate his 
position by playing inappropriately. We ought to exclude this possibility for a 
"dummy" but this point is of little importance.) 

The general discussion, which we are going to carry out (both games A and H essen- 
tial) will actually disclose a phenomenon which does not arise in the special case to which 
the corner VIII of 35.2. belongs i.e. the case of "dummies" (H inessential). The 
new phenomenon will be discussed in 46.7., 46.8., and the case of "dummies" where 
nothing new happens in 46.9. 

2 It would seem natural to extend the concepts of composition and decomposition to 
more than 2 constituents. This will be carried out in 43.2., 43.3. 

3 Cf. G. Birkhoff & S. MacLane: A Survev of Modern Ahrebra. New York. 1941. 
Chapt. XIII. 



COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION 341 

and also be able to use for further interpretations are a rather encouraging 
symptom from a technical point of view. 

41.2.3. Second, the reader may feel that the operation of composition 
is of an entirely formal and fictitious nature. Why should two games, 
A and H, played by two distinct sets of players and having absolutely no 
influence upon each other, be considered as one game F? 

Our result will disclose that the complete separation of the games A 
and H, as far as the rules are concerned, does not necessarily imply the 
same for their solutions. I.e.: Although the two sets of players cannot 
influence each other directly, nevertheless when they are regarded as one 
set, one society there may be stable standards of behaviour which 
establish correlations between them. 1 The significance of this circumstance 
will be elaborated more fully when we reach it loc. cit. 

41.2.4. Besides, it should be noted that this procedure of composition 
is quite customary in the natural sciences as well as in economic theory. 
Thus it is perfectly legitimate to consider two separate mechanical systems 
situated, to take an extreme case, say one on Jupiter and one on Uranus 
as one. It is equally feasible to consider the internal economies of two 
separate countries the connections between which are disregarded as one. 
This is, of course, the preliminary step before introducing the interacting 
forces between those systems. Thus we could choose in our first example 
as those two systems the two planets Jupiter and Uranus themselves 
(both in the gravitational field of the Sun), and then introduce as interaction 
the gravitational forces which the planets exert on each other. In OUT 
second example, the interaction enters with the consideration of inter- 
national trade, international capital movements, migrations, etc. 

We could equally use the decomposable game F as a stepping stone 
to other games in its neighborhood, which, in their turn, permit no decompo- 
sition. 2 

In our present considerations, however, these latter modifications will 
not be considered. Our interest is in the correlations introduced by the 
solutions referred to at the beginning of this paragraph. 

41.3. Exact Definitions 

41.3.1. Let us now proceed to the strictly mathematical description 
of the composition and decomposition of games. 

Let k players 1', , fc', forming the set J = (!', , k f ) play the 
game A; and I players 1", , I", forjning the set K = (1", , V) 
play the game H. We re-emphasize that A and H are disjoint sets of 
players and 8 that the games A and H are without any influence upon each 

1 There is sortie analogy between this and the phenomenon noted before (cf. 21.3., 
37.2.1.) that a symmetry of the game need not imply the same symmetry in all solutions. 

1 Cf. 35.3.3., applied to the neighborhood of corner /., which according to 35.2. is a 
decomposable game. The remark of footnote 2 on p. 303 on perturbations is also 
pertinent. 

8 If the same players 1, t n are playing simultaneously two games, then an 
entirely different situation prevails. That is the superposition of games referred to in 



342 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

other. Denote the characteristic functions of these two games by v&(S) 
and v H (!T) respectively, where S zJ and T K. 

In forming the composite game F, it is convenient to use the same 
symbols 1', ,*', 1", ,/" for its n = k + I players. 1 They 
form the set / = J u K = (!', -,*', 1", , V). 

Clearly every set R / permits a unique representation 

(41:1) # = SuT, SsJ, TzK; 

the inverse of this formula being 

(41:2) S = #n/, T = R n K* 

Denote the characteristic function of the game F by vr(fi) with R /. 
The intuitive fact that the games A and H combine without influencing 
each other to F has this quantitative expression : The value in F of a coalition 
R I obtains by addition of the value in A of its part S (s J) in J and of 
the value in H of its part T (s K) in K. Expressed by a formula: 

(41:3) vr(fl) = v A (S) + v R (T) where R, S, T are linked by (41:1), 

i.e. (41 :2). 8 

41.3.2. The form (41:3) expressed the composite vr(R) by means of its 
constituents VA(), v H (T). However, it also contains the answer to the 
inverse problem: To express VA(/S), v H (T) by v r (#). 

Indeed v A (0) = v H (0) = O. 4 Hence putting alternately T = 
and S = Q in (41:3) gives: 

(41:4) v A (5)=v r (S) for SsJ, 

(41:5) v H (r) = v r (r) for T <= #. 6 

We are now in a position to express the fact of the decomposdbility of the 
game F with respect to the two sets J and K. I.e.: the given game F 
(among the elements of / = J u K) is such that it can be decomposed into 
two suitable games A (among the elements J) and H (among the elements 
of K). As stated, this is an implicit property of F involving the existence 
of the unknown A, H. But it will be expressed as an explicit property of F. 

Indeed: If two such A, H exist, then they cannot be anything but those 
described by (41 :4), (41 :5). Hence the property of F in question is, that the 

27.6.2. and also in 35.3.4. Its influences on the strategy are much more complex and 
scarcely describable by general rules, as was pointed out at the latter loc. cit. 

1 Instead of the usual 1, , n. 

1 These formulae (41:1), (41 :2) have an immediate verbal meaning. The reader may 
find it profitable to formulate it. 

8 Of course, a rigorous deduction on the basis of 25.1.3. is feasible without difficulty. 
All of 25.3.2. applies in this case. 

4 Note that the empty set is a subset of both / and K\ since J and K are disjoint, 
it is their only common subset. 

6 This is an instance of the technical usefulness of our treating the empty set as a 
coalition. Of. footnote 2 on p. 241. 



COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION 343 

A, H of (41:4), (41:5) fulfill (41:3). Substituting, therefore, (41:4), (41:5) 
into (41 :3), using (41 :1) to express R in terms of /S, T gives this: 

(41 :6) v r (S u T) = v r (S) + v r (T) for S J, T 7 S #. 
Or, if we use (41 :2) (expressing S,,r in terms of R) in place of (41 :1) 
(41 :7) vr(fi) = v r (fi n J) + v r (fl n X) for Bel. 

41.3.3. In order to see the role of the equations (41:6), (41:7) in the 
proper light, a detailed reconsideration of the basic principles upon which 
they rest, is necessary. This will be done in sections 41.4.-42.5.2. which 
follow. However, two remarks concerning the interpretation of these 
equations can be made immediately. 

First: (41:6) expresses that a coalition between a set S s J and a set 
T S K has no attraction that while there may be motives for players 
within J to combine with each other, and similarly for players within K, 
there are no forces acting across the boundaries of J and K. 

Second: To those readers who are familiar with the mathematical theory 
of measure, we make this further observation in continuation of that 
made at the end of 27.4.3.: (41:7) is exactly Carath6odory's definition of 
measurability. This concept is quite fundamental for the theory of additive 
measure and Carath6odory's approach to it appears to be the technically 
superior one to date. l Its emergence in the present context is a remarkable 
fact which seems to deserve further study. 

41.4. Analysis of Decomposability 

41.4.1. We obtained the criteria (41:6), (41:7) of Y's decomposability 
by substituting the v A (/S), v H (T r ) obtained from (41:4), (41:5) into the 
fundamental condition (41 :3). However, this deduction contains a lacuna: 
We did not verify whether it is possible to find two games A, H which pro- 
duce the v A (S), v H (5P) formally defined by (41:4), (41:5). 

There is no difficulty in formalizing these extra requirements. As we 
know from 25.3.1. they mean that v*(S) and v H (T) fulfill the conditions 
(25:3:a)-(25:3:c) eod. It must be understood that we assume the given 
Vr(B) to originate from a game F, i.e. that vp(fi) fulfills these conditions. 
Hence the following question presents itself: 

(41 :A) v r (B) fulfills (25:3:a)-(25:3:c) in 25.3.1. together with the 

above (41:6), i.e. (41:7). Will then the v A (S) and v H (T) of 
(41:4), (41:5) also fulfill (25:3:a)-(25:3:c) in 25.3.1.? Or, if this 
is not the case, which further postulate must be imposed upon 
vr(B)? 
To decide this, we check (25:3:a)-(25:3:c) of 25.3.1. separately for v A (S) 

and v H (7 7 ). It is convenient to take them up in a different order. 

41.4.2. Ad (25:3:a): By virtue of (41:4), (41:5), this is the same state- 
ment for VA(*S) and v H (T) as for v r (#). 

1 Cf. C. Carathtodwy: Vorlesungen liber Reelle Funktionen, Berlin, 1918, Chapt. V. 



344 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

Ad (25:3:c): By virtue of (41:4), (41:5), this carries over to v A (S) and 
Vn(T) from Vr(fi) it amounts only to a restriction from the R c I to 
S J and T s K. 

Before discussing the remaining (25:3:b), we insert a remark concerning 
(25:4) of 25.4.1. Since this is a consequence of (25:3:a)-(25:3:c), it is 
legitimate for us to draw conclusions from it and it will be seen that this 
anticipation simplifies the analysis of (25:3:b). 

From here on we will have to use promiscuously complementary sets in 
7, J, K. It is, therefore, necessary to avoid the notation S, and to write 
instead I S, J S, K S, respectively. 

Ad (25:4) : For v A (S) and v H (T) the role of the set I is taken over by the 
sets J and K, respectively. Hence this condition becomes: 

v A (J) = 0, 
0. 



Owing to (41:4), (41 :5), this means 

(41:8) VrO/) =0, 

(41:9) vp(K) = 0. 

Since K = I /, therefore (25:3:b) (applied to v r OS) for which it was 
assumed to hold) gives 



(41 :10) v r (J) + Vr(K) = 0. 

Thus (41:8) and (41:9) imply each other by virtue of the identity (41:10). 

In (41:8) or (41:9) we have actually a new condition, which does not 
follow from (41:6) or (41:7). 

Ad (25:3:b): We will derive its validity for v A (S) and v H (7) from the 
assumed one for VF(#). By symmetry it suffices to consider v&(S). 

The relation to be proven is 

(41:11) v A (S) + v&(J - S) = 0. 

By (41 :4) this means 

(41:12) vrOS) + v T (J - S) 0. 

Owing to (41:8), which we must require anyhow, this may be written 

(41:13) vrOS) + v r (J - S) = v r (J) 

(Of course, S J.) 

To prove (41:13), apply (25:3:b) for v r (fl) to R = J - S and R = J. 
For these sets / - R = Su K and / - R = K, respectively. So (41:13) 
becomes 

VrOS) - VrOSutf) = -v r (X), 
i.e. 

VrOS u K) = vrOS) + v r (X), 

and this is the special case of (41:6) with T = K. 



MODIFICATION OF THE THEORY 345 

Thus we have filled in the lacuna mentioned at the beginning of this 
paragraph and answered the questions of (41: A). 

(41 :B) The further postulate which must be imposed upon vr(fi) 

is this: (41:8), i.e. (41:9). 

All these put together answer the question of 41.3.2. concerning decom- 
posability: 

(41 :C) The game F is decomposable with respect to the sets J and K 

(cf. 41.3.2.) if and only if it fulfills these conditions: (41:6), i.e. 
(41:7) and (41:8), i.e. (41:9). 

41.5. Desirability of a Modification 

41.5.1. The two conditions which we proved equivalent to decompos- 
ability in (41 :C) are of very different character. (41:6) (i.e. (41:7)) is the 
really essential one, while (41 :8) (i.e. (41 :9)) expresses only a rather inciden- 
tal circumstance. We will justify this rigorously below, but first a quali- 
tative remark will be useful. The prototype of our concept of decomposition 
was the game referred to at the beginning of 41.2.1.: the game represented 
by the corner VIII of 35.2. Now this game fulfilled (41:6), but not 
(41:8). (The former follows from (35:7) in 35.2.1., the latter from v(J) = 
v((l,2,3)) = 1 7* 0.) We nevertheless considered that game as decom- 
posable (with J = (1,2,3), K = (4)) how is it then possible, that it 
violates the condition (41 :8) which we found to be necessary for the decom- 
posability? 

41.5.2. The answer is simple: For the above game the constituents A 
(in J = (1,2,3)) and H (in K = (4)) do not completely satisfy (25:3:a)- 
(25:3:c) in 25.3.1. To be precise, they do not fulfill the consequence 
(25:4) in 25.4.1.: V A (/) = V H (#) = is not true (and it was from this 
condition that we derived (41:8)). In other words: the constituents of F 
are not zero-sum games. This point, of course, was perfectly clear in 
35.2.2., where it received due consideration. 

Consequently we must endeavor to get rid of the condition (41:8), 
recognizing that this may force us to consider other than zero-sum games. 

42. Modification of the Theory 
42.1. No Complete Abandoning of the Zero-sum Condition 

42.1. Complete abandonment of the zero-sum condition for our games 1 
would mean that the functions 3C*(ri, , r n ) which characterized it 
in the sense of 11.2.3. are entirely unrestricted. I.e. that the requirement 

(42:1) 2) JC*(n, , r n ) BE 

Jb-l 

1 We again denote the players by 1, , n. 



346 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

of 11.4. and 25.1.3. is dropped, with nothing else to take its place. This 
would necessitate a revision of considerable significance, since the construc- 
tion of the characteristic function in 25. depended upon (25:1), i.e. (42:1), and 
would therefore have to be taken up de novo. 

Ultimately this revision will become necessary (cf . Chapter XI) but not 
yet at the present stage. 

In order to get a precise idea of just what is necessary now, let us make 
the auxiliary considerations contained in 42.2.1., 42.2.2. below. 

42.2. Strategic Equivalence. Constant-sum Games 

42.2.1. Consider a zero-sum game F which may or may not fulfill 
conditions (41:6) and (41:8). Pass from F to a strategically equivalent 
game r' in the sense of 27.1.1., 27.1.2., with the a?, , aj described 
there. It is evident, that (41 :6) for F is equivalent to the same for F'. 1 

The situation is altogether different for (41:8). Passage from F to 
F' changes the left hand side of (41:8) by ajj, hence the validity of 

kinJ 

(41:8) in one case is by no means implied by that in the other. Indeed 
this is true: 

(42 :A) For every F it is possible to choose a strategically equivalent 

game F' so that the latter fulfills (41:8). 

n 

Proof: The assertion is 1 that we can choose aj, , a with ] aj = 

*i 
(this is (27:1) in 27.1.1.) so that 

v(J) + aj = 

kinJ 

Now this is obviously possible if J 7* or /, since then ] a can be 

*m J 

given any assigned value. For J = Q or J, there is nothing to prove, as 
then v(J) = by (25:3:a) in 25.3.1. and (25:4) in 25.4.1. 

This result can be interpreted as follows: If we refrain from considering 
other than zero-sum games, 2 then condition (41:6) expresses that while 
the game F may not be decomposable itself, it is strategically equivalent 
to some decomposable game F'. 3 

42.2.2. The above rigorous result makes it clear where the weakness 
of our present arrangement lies. Decomposability is an important strategic 
property and it is therefore inconvenient that of two strategically equivalent 
games one may be termed decomposable without the other. It is, therefore, 

1 By (27:2) in 27.1.1. Observe that the v r GS), v r 'OS) of (42:A) are the v(S), v'(S) of 
(27:2) loc. cit. 

* I.e. we require this not only for r, but also for its constituents A, H. 

* The treatment of the constituents in 35.2.2. amounts to exactly this, as an inspec- 
tion of footnote 1 on p. 300 shows explicitly. 



MODIFICATION OF THE THEORY 347 

desirable to widen these concepts so that decomposability becomes an 
invariant under strategic equivalence. 

In other words: We want to modify our concept so that the transforma- 
tion (27:2) of 27.1.1., which defines strategic equivalence, does not interfere 
with the relationship between a decomposable game F and its constituents 
A and H. This relationship is expressed by (41:3): 

(42:2) vr(S u T) = v A (S) + v K (T) for S c J, T c K. 

Now if we use (27:2) with the same cf k for all three games F, A, H then (42:2) 
is manifestly undisturbed. The only trouble is with the preliminary 
condition (27:1). This states for F, A, H that 



2 = 0, a fc - 0, 

* in / k in J k in K 

respectively and while we now assume the first relation true, the two others 
may fail. 

Hence the natural way out is to discard (27:1) of 27.1.1. altogether. 
I.e. to widen the domain of games, which we consider, by including all 
those games which are strategically equivalent to zero-sum ones by virtue 
of the transformation formula (27:2) alone without demanding (27:1). 

As was seen in 27.1.1. this amounts to replacing the functions 



* " " > T n) 

of the latter by new functions 

3Ci(n, ' ' , r n ) - JC*(n, - , r n ) + al 

(The a?, , aj are no longer subject to (27:1)). The systems of 
functions 3C(ri, , r n ) which are obtained in this way from the system 
of functions 3Cfc(ri, , r n ) which fulfill (42:1) in 42.1. are easy to char- 
acterize. The characteristic is (in place of (42:1) loc. cit.) the property 

(42:3) 3C;(n, - , r n ) EE .i 

*i 

Summing up: 

(42 :B) We are widening the domain of games which we consider, by 

passing from the zero-sum games to the constant-sum games.* 
At the same time, we widen the concept of strategic equivalence, 

> 

1 8 is an arbitrary constant = 0. In the transformation (27:2) which produces this 

< 
game from a zero-sum one, there is obviously 



1 This gives a precise meaning to the statement at the beginning of 42.1. according to 
which we are not yet prepared to consider all games unrestrictedly. 



348 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

introduced in 27.1.1., by defining it again by transformation 
(27:2) loc. cit., but dropping the condition (27:1) eod. 

42.2.3. It is essential to recognize that our above generalizations do not 
alter our main ideas on strategic equivalence. This is best done by con- 
sidering the following two points. 

First, we stated in 25.2.2. that we proposed to understand all quanti- 
tative properties of a game by means of its characteristic function alone. 
One must realize that the reasons for this are just as good in our present 
domain of constant-sum games as in the original (and narrower) one of 
zero-sum games. The reason is this: 

(42 :C) Every constant-sum game is strategically equivalent to a 

zero-sum game. 

Proof: The transformation (27:2) obviously replaces the a of (42:3) 

n 

above by s + aj. Now it is possible to choose the aj, , aj so 

*-i 

n 

as to make this s + J) = 0, i.e. to carry the given constant-sum game 

Jb-i 
into a (strategically equivalent) zero-sum game. 

Second, our new concept of strategic equivalence was only necessary 
for the sake cf the new (non-zero-sum) games that we introduced. For the 
old (zero-sum) games it is equivalent to the old concept. In other words : 
If two zero-sum games obtain from each other by means of the transforma- 
tion (27:2) in 27.1.1., then (27:1) is automatically fulfilled. Indeed, this 
was already observed in footnote 2 on p. 246. 

42.3. The Characteristic Function in the New Theory 

42.3.1. Given a constant-sum game F" (with the 3C(ri, , r n ) 
fulfilling (42:3)), we could introduce its characteristic function v'(S) by 
repeating the definitions of 25.1.3. 1 On the other hand, we may follow 
the procedure suggested by the argumentation of 42.2.2., 42.2.3.: We can 
obtain F' with the functions 3Cl(ri, , r n ) from a zero-sum game F 
with the functions JCjb(ri, , r w ) as in 42.2.2., i.e. by 



(42:4) jei(n, , r n ) s 3C*(r,, - , r n ) + <tf 

with appropriate otj, , aj (cf. footnote 1 on p. 246), and then define the 
characteristic function v'(S) of T f by means of (27:2) in 27.1.1., i.e. by 

(42:5) v'(S) ^ V (5) + aj. 

kinS 

1 The whole arrangement of 25.1.3. can be repeated literally, although T is no longer 
zero-sum, with two exceptions. In (25:1) and (25:2) of 25.1.3. we must add A to the 
extreme right hand term. (This is so, because we now have (42:3) in place of (42.1).) 
This difference is entirely immaterial. 



MODIFICATION OF THE THEORY 349 

Now the two procedures are equivalent, i.e. the v'(/S) of (42:4), (42:5) 
coincides with the one obtained by the reapplication of 26.1.3. Indeed, an 
inspection of the formulae of 25.1.3. shows immediately, that the substitu- 
tion of (42:4) there produces the result (42:5). l * f 

42.3.2. v(S) is a characteristic function of a zero-sum game, if and only 
if it fulfills the conditions (25:3:a)-(25:3:c) of 25.3.1., as was pointed out 
there and in 26.2. (The proof was given in 25.3.3. and 26.1.) What do 
these conditions become in the case of a constant-sum game? 

In order to answer this question, let us remember, that (25:3:a)-(25:3:c) 
loc. cit. imply (25:4) in 25.4.1. Hence, we can add (25:4) to them, and 
modify (25:3:b) by adding v(7) to its right hand side (this is no change 
owing to (25:4)). Thus the characterization of the v(S) of all zero-sum 
games becomes this: 

(42:6:a) v() = 0, 

(42:6:b) v(S) + v(-S) = v(7), 

(42:6:c) v(5) + v(T) g v(S u T) if S n T = 0, 

and 

(42:6:d) v(7) = 0. 

Now the v'(S) of all constant-sum games obtain from these v(/S) by subject- 
ing them to the transformation (42:5) of 42.3.1. How does this transforma- 
tion affect (42:6:a)-(42:6:d)? 

One verifies immediately, that (42:6:a)-(42:6:c) are entirely unaffected, 
while (42:6:d) is completely obliterated. 3 So we see: 

(42 :D) v(S) is the characteristic function of a constant-sum game 

if and only if it satisfies the conditions (42:6:a)-(42:6:c). 

(We write from now on v(S) for v'GS)). 

As mentioned above, (42:6:d) is no longer valid. However, we have 

(42:6:d*) v(7) = s. 

Indeed, this is clear from (42:3), considering the procedure of 25.1.3. It 
can also be deduced by comparing footnote 1 on p. 347 and footnote 3 
above (our v(S) is the v'(S) there). Besides (42:6:d*) is intuitively clear: 
A coalition of all players obtains the fixed sum s of the game. 

1 The verbal equivalent of this consideration is easily found. 

1 Had we decided to define v'(*S>) by means of (42:2), (42:5) only, a question of ambi- 
guity would have arisen. Indeed: A given constant-sum game r' can obviously be 
obtained from many different zero-sum games r by (42:4), will then (42:5) always yield 
the same v ; (5)? 

It would be easy to prove directly that this is the case. This is unnecessary, how- 
ever, because we have shown that the v'(S) of (42:5) is always equal to that one of 
25.1.3. and that v'(S) is defined unambiguously, with the help of F' alone. 

n 

1 According to (42:5), the right hand side of (42:6:d) goes over into ?> i- e ^ ? 

t in / t - 1 

and this sum is completely arbitrary. 



350 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

42.4. Imputations, Domination, Solutions in the New Theory 

42.4*1. From now on, we are considering characteristic functions of any 
constant-sum game, i.e. functions v(S) subject to (42:6:a)-(42:6:c) only. 

Our first task in this wider domain, is naturally that of extending to it 
the concepts of imputations, dominations, and solutions as defined in 30.1.1. 

Let us begin with the distributions or imputations. We can take over 
from 30.1.1. their interpretation as vectors 

> 

a = {ai, -,). 

Of the conditions (30:1), (30:2) eod. we may conserve (30:1): 
(42:7) a, v((t)) 

unchanged the reasons referred to there 1 are just as valid now as then. 
(30:2) eod., however, must be modified. The constant-sum of the game 
being s (cf. (42:3) and (42:6:d*) above), each imputation should distribute 
this amount i.e. it is natural to postulate 

(42:8) 

By (42:6:d*) this is equivalent to 

(42:8*) a, = v(/). 

-i 

The definitions of effectivity, domination, solution we take over unchanged 
from 30.1. 1. 3 the supporting arguments brought forward in the discussions 
which led up to those definitions, appear to lose no strength by our present 
generalization. 

42.4.2. These considerations receive their final corroborations by observ- 
ing this: 

(42 :E) For our new concept of strategic equivalence of constant-sum 

games F, F', 4 there exists an isomorphism of their imputations, 
i.e. a one-to-one mapping of those of F on those of F', which 
leaves the concepts of 30.1. 1. 5 invariant. 

This is an analogue of (31 :Q) in 31.3.3. and it can be demonstrated in 
the same way. As there, we define the correspondence 

(42:9) 7^7' 

1 a < v((t)) would be unacceptable, cf. e.g. the beginning of 29.2.1. 

2 For the special case of a zero-sum game v(7) = so (42:8), (42:8*) coincide as 
they must with (30:2) loc. cit. 

'I.e. (30:3); (30:4:a)-(30:4:c); (30:5:a), (30:5:b), or (30:5:c) loc. cit., respectively. 
4 As defined at the end of 42.2.2., i.e. by (27:2) in 27. 1.1., without (27:1) eod. 
As redefined in 42.4.1. 



MODIFICATION OF THE THEORY 351 

between the imputations a = \a h , a n j of F and the imputations 

"?' = K - , a' n ] of I" by 

(42:10) a' k = a k + J 

where the a?, - , a are those of (27:2) in 27.1.1. 

Now the proof of (31 :Q) in 31.3.3. carries over almost literally. The one 
difference is that (30:2) of 30.1.1. is replaced by our (42:8) but since (27:2) 



n 



in 27.1.1. gives v'(/) = v(7) + <*?, this too takes care of itself. 1 The 

t-i 

reader who goes over 31.3. again, will see that everything else said there 
applies equally to the present case. 

42.5. Essentiality, Inessentiality, and Decomposability in the New Theory 

42.6.1. We know from (42 :C) in 42.2.3. that every constant-sum game is 
strategically equivalent to a zero-sum game. Hence (42 :E) allows us to 
carry over the general results of 31. from the zero-sum games to the constant- 
sum ones always passing from the latter class to the former one by strategic 
equivalence. 

This forces us to define inessentiality for a constant-sum game by 
strategic equivalence to an inessential zero-sum game. We may state 
therefore: 

(42 :F) A zero-sum game is inessential if and only if it is strategically 

equivalent to the game with v(S) = 0. (Cf. 23.1.3. or (27 :C) 
in 27.4.2.) By the above, the same is true for a constant-sum 
game. (But we must use our new definitions of inessentiality 
and of strategic equivalence.) 

Essentiality is, of course, defined as negation of inessentiality. 
Application of the transformation formula (42:5) of 42.3.1. to the 
criteria of 27.4. shows, that there are only minor changes. 
(27:8) in 27.4.1. must be replaced by 



(42:11) 



since the right hand side of this formula is invariant under (42:5) and it 
goes over into (27:8) loc. cit. for v(I) = (i.e. the zero-sum case). 

The substitution of (42:11) for (27:8) necessitates replacement of the 
on the right hand side of both formulae in the criterion (27 :B) of 27.4.1. by 

n 

1 And this was the only point in the proof referred to, at which 2, S - (i.e. (27:1) 

t-i 
in 27.1.1., which we no longer require) is used. 



352 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

v(7). The criteria (27:C), (27:D) of 27.4.2. are invariant under (42:5), 
and hence unaffected. 

42.5.2. We can now return to the discussion of composition and decom- 
position in 41.3.-41.4., in the wider domain of all constant-sum games. 

All of 41.3. can be repeated literally. 

When we come to 41.4.,, the question (41 :A) formulated there again 
presents itself. In order to determine whether any postulates beyond 
(41:6), i.e. (41:7) of 41.3.2. are now needed, we must investigate (42:6:a)- 
(42:6:c) in 42.3.2., instead of (25:3:a)-(25:3:c) in 25.3.1. (for all three of 
v r (/Z), v A (S), v,(I*)). 

(42:6:a), (42:6:c) are immediately disposed of, exactly as (25:3:a), 
(25:3:c) in 41.4. As to (42:6:b), the proof of (25:3:b) in 41.4. is essentially 
applicable, but this time no extra condition arises (like (41:8) or (41:9) 
loc. cit.). To simplify matters, we give this proof in full. 

Ad (42:6:b): We will derive its validity for v A (S) and v H (T) from the 
assumed one for vrCR). By symmetry it suffices to consider 

The relation to be proven is 



(42:12) v A (S) + v A (J - S) = 

By (41:4) this means 

(42:12*) VrOS) + v r (J - S) = v r (J). 

To prove (42:12*) apply (42:6:b) for v r (fl) to R = / - S and R = J. 
For these I - R = SuK and I - R = K, respectively. So (42:12*) 
becomes 

Vr(S) + v r (J) - Vr(S u K) = v r (7) - v r (X), 

i.e. 

v r (S u K) = Vr(S) + v r (X), 

and this is the special case of (41:6) with T = K. 

Thus we have improved upon the result (41 :C) of 41.4. as follows: 

(42 :G) In the domain of all constant-sum games the game F is 

decomposable with respect to the sets J and K (cf. 41.3.2.) if 
and only if it fulfills the condition (41:6), i.e. (41:7). 

42.5.3. Comparison of (41 :C) in 41.4. and of (42 :G) in 42.5.2. shows that 
the passage from zero-sum to constant-sum games rids us of the unwanted 
condition (41:8), i.e. (41:9) for decomposability. 

Decomposability is now defined by (41:6), i.e. (41:7) alone, and it is 
invariant under strategic equivalence as it should be. 

We also know that when a game F is decomposed into two (constituent) 
games A and H (all of them constant-sum only!), we can make all these 
games zero-sum by strategic equivalence. (Cf. (42 :C) in 42.2.3. for F, 
and then (42 :A) in 42.2.1. et sequ. for A, H.) 



THE DECOMPOSITION PARTITION 363 

Thus we can always use one of the two domains of games zero-sum 
or constant-sum whichever is more convenient for the problem just under 
consideration. 

In the remainder of this chapter we will continue to con- 
sider constant-sum games, unless the opposite is explicitly stated. 

43. The Decomposition Partition 
43.1. Splitting Sets. Constituents 

43.1. We defined the decomposability of a game F not per se, but with 
respect to a decomposition of the set / of all players into two complementary 
sets, J, K. 

Therefore it is feasible to take this attitude: Consider the game F 
as given, and the sets J ', K as variable. Since J determines K (indeed 
K = 7 J), it suffices to treat J as the variable. Then we have this 
question: 

Given a game F (with the set of players /) for which sets J s / (and the 
corresponding K = / J) is F decomposable? 

We call those J(Q I) for which this is the case the splitting sets of T. 
The constituent game A which obtains in this decomposition (cf. 41.2.1. 
and (41:4) of 41.3.2.) is the J -constituent of F. 1 

A splitting set J is thus defined by (41:6), i.e. (41:7) in 41.3.2., where 
K = 7 J must be substituted. 

The reader will note that this concept has a very simple intuitive mean- 
ing: A splitting set is a self contained group of players, who neither influence, 
nor are influenced by, the others as far as the rules of the game are concerned. 

43.2. Properties of the System of All Splitting Sets 

43.2.1. The totality of all splitting sets of a given game is characterized 
by an aggregate of simple properties. Most of these have an intuitive 
immediate meaning, which may make mathematical proof seem unnecessary. 
We will nevertheless proceed systematically and give proofs, stating the 
intuitive interpretations in footnotes. Throughout what follows we write 
v(S) for v r (S) (the characteristic function of F). 

(43: A) J is a splitting set if and only if its complement K = / J 

is one. 2 

Proof: The decomposability of F involves J and K symmetrically. 
(43 :B) and / are splitting sets. 8 

Proof: (41:6) or (41:7) with J = , K = / are obviously true, as 
v(0) = 0. 

1 By the same definition the game H (cf. 41.2.1. and (41:5) in 41.3.2.) is then the 
K-constituent (K - / - J) of T. 

1 That a set of players is self-contained in the sense of 43.1., is clearly the same state- 
ment, as that the complement is self-contained. 

1 That these are self-contained is tautological. 



354 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

43.2.2. 

(43 :C) /' n J" and J' u J" are splitting sets if J', J" are. 1 

Proof: Ad J' u J": As J', J" are splitting sets, we have (41:6) for J, K 
equal to J', 7 - J' and J", / - J". We wish to prove it for J f u J", 
I - (J'u J"). Consider therefore two S J 1 u J", T 7 - (J 9 u /") 
Let S' be the part of S in J', then S" = S S' lies in the complement of 
J', and as S J' u J", S" also lies in J". So S = S' + S", S' c J', 
S" S /". Now S' j', S" c / - J' and (41 :6) for J', I - J' give 

(43:1) v(5) = v(S') + v(S"). 

Next S" 7 - J' and T s I - (J' u J") s 7 - J' so S"uTsI-J'. 
Also S' c j'. Clearly S' u (S" u T) = S u T. Hence (41 :6) for J', 7 - J' 
also gives 

(43:2) v(S u T) = v(S') + v(S" u 7 1 ). 

Finally S"<=J" and Ts 7 - (J' u J") 7 - J". Hence (41:6) for 
J", 7 - J" gives 

(43:3) v(S" u T 7 ) = v(S") + v(T). 

Now substitute (43 :3) into (43 :2) and then contract the right hand side 
by (43:1). This gives 

v(S u T) = v(5) + v(T), 

which is (41:6), as desired. 

Ad J' n J": Use (43 :A) and the above result. As J', J" are splitting 
sets, the same obtains successively for 7 J', I J", (I J') u (7 /") 
which is clearly 7 (/' n 7") 2 , and J' n /" the last one being the desired 
expression. 

43.3. Characterization of the System of All Splitting Sets. The Decomposition Partition 

43.3.1. It may be that there exist no other splitting sets than the trivial 
ones , 7 (cf. (43 :B) above). In that case, we call the game F indecompos- 
able* Without studying this question any further, 4 we continue to 
investigate the splitting sets of F. 

1 The intersection J' n J": It may strike the reader as odd, that two self-contained 
sets J', J" should have a non-empty intersection at all. This is possible, however, as the 
example /' J" shows. The deeper reason is that a self-contained set may well be the 
sum of smaller self-contained sets (proper subsets). (Cf. (43 :H) in 43.3.) Our present 
assertion is that if two self-contained sets J', /" have a non-empty intersection /' n /", 
then this intersection is such a self-contained subset. In this form it will probably appear 
plausible. 

The sum /' U J": That the sum of two self-contained sets will again be self-contained 
stands to reason. This may be somewhat obscured when a non-empty intersection 
/' n J" exists, but this case is really harmless as discussed above. The proof which 
follows is actually primarily an exact account of the ramifications of just this case. 

1 The complement of the intersection is the sum of the complements. 

1 Actually most games are indecomposable; otherwise the criterion (42 :G) in 42.5.2. 
requires the restrictive equations (41 :6), (41 :7) in 41.3.2. 

4 Yetl Cf. footnote 3 and its references. 



THE DECOMPOSITION PARTITION 355 

(43 :D) Consider a splitting set J of F and the /-constituent A of F. 

Then a J' J is a splitting set of A if and only if it is one of F. 1 

Proof: Considering (41:4), J' is a splitting set of A by virtue of (41:6) 
when 

(43:4) v(S u T) = v(S) + v(7) for 8 J', T fi J - J'. 

(We write v(S) for v r (/S)). Again by (41 :6) J' is a splitting set of F when 

(43:5) v(S u T) = v(S) + v(T) for S J', J 1 c / - J'. 

We must prove the equivalence of (43:4) and (43:5). As J J, so 
(43:4) is clearly a special case of (43:5) hence we need only prove that 
(43:4) implies (43:5). 

Assume, therefore, (43:4). We may use (41 :6) for F with J, K = / J. 

Consider two S J', T s 7 - J'. Let T f be the part of T in J, then 
T' ' = T - T' lies in 7 - J. So T = T' u T", T f c J, T" c / - J and 
(41:6) for F with J, I - J give 

(43:6) v(r) = v(2") + v(T"). 

Next SzJ'zJ and T 7 ' c J so SuT'sJ. Also T" / - J. Clearly 
(S u T ; ) u T 77 ' = S u T. Hence (41 :6) for F with J, 7 - J also gives 

(43:7) v(S u T) = v(5 u T') + v(T"). 

Finally Scj' and T'&I-J' and T'cJ, so T'sJ-J'. Hence 
(43:4) gives 

(43:8) v(S u T') = v(S) + v(2"). 

Now substitute (43 :8) into (43 :7) and then contract the right hand side 
by (43:6). This gives precisely the desired (43:5). 

43.3.2. (43 :D) makes it worth while to consider those splitting sets J, 
for which J ^ 0, but no proper subset J 1 Q of J is a splitting set. We 
call such a set J, for obvious reasons, a minimal splitting set. 

Consider our definitions of indecomposability and of minimality. 
(43 :D) implies immediately: 

(43 :E) The J-component A (of F) is indecomposable if and only if 

J is a minimal splitting set. 

The minimal splitting sets form an arrangement with very simple 
properties, and they determine the totality of all splitting sets. The 
statement follows: 

(43 :F) Any two different minimal splitting sets are disjunct. 

(43 :G) The sum of all minimal splitting sets is 7. 

1 To be self-contained within a self-contained set, is the same thing as to be such in 
the original (total) set. The statement may seem obvious; that it is not so, will appear 
from the proof. 



356 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

(43 :H) By forming all sums of all possible aggregates of minimal 

splitting sets, we obtain precisely the totality of all splitting 
sets. 1 

Proof: Ad (43 :F) : Let /', J" be two minimal splitting sets which are 
not disjunct. Then J' n J" 7* Q is splitting by (43 :C), as it is J' and 
S J". So the minimality of J' and J" implies that J r n J" is equal to 
both J 1 and J 11 . Hence /' = J". 

Ad (43 :G) : It suffices to show that every k in / belongs to some minimal 
splitting set. 

There exist splitting sets which contain the player k (i.e. /) ; let J be the 
intersection of all of them. J is splitting by (43 :C). If J were not minimal, 
then there would exist a splitting set J' ?* , J, which is J. Now 
J" = J - J' = J n (/ - J') is also a splitting set by (43 :A), (43 :C), and 
clearly also J" j* , J. Either J' or J" = / J 1 must contain k say 
that J 1 does. Then J' is among the sets of which J is the intersection. 
Hence J 1 a J. But as J' J and J' 7* J, this is impossible. 

Ad (43 :H): Every sum of minimal splitting sets is splitting by (43 :C), 
so we need only prove the converse. 

Let K be a splitting set. If J is minimal splitting, then J n K is splitting 
by (43 :C), also J n K J hence either JnK = QoTjnK = J. In 
the first case /, K are disjunct, in the second J K. So we see: 

(43:1) Every minimal splitting set J is either disjunct with K or 



Let K' be the sum of the former J, and K" the sum of the latter. K' u K 11 
is the sum of all minimal splitting sets, hence by (43 :G) 

(43:9) K'uK" = 7. 

By their origin K ' is disjunct with K , and K" is K. I.e. 

(43:10) #'/-#, X"K 

Now (43:9), (43:10) together necessitate K" = K\ hence If is a sum of a 
suitable aggregate of minimal sets, as desired. 

43.3.3. (43 :F), (43 :G) make it clear that the minimal splitting sets 
form a partition in the sense of 8.3.1., with the sum 7. We call this the 
decomposition partition of T, and denote it by H r . Now (43 :H) can be 
expressed as follows: 

(43 :H*) A splitting set Ksl is characterized by the following 

property: The points of each element of II r go together as 
far as K is concerned i.e. each element of II r lies completely 
inside or completely outside of K. 

1 The intuitive meaning of these assertions should be quite clear. They characterize 
the structure of the maximum possibilities of decomposition of F in a plausible way. 



THE DECOMPOSITION PARTITION 357 

Thus n r expresses how far the decomposition of T in / can be pushed, 
without destroying those ties which the rules of T establish between players. 1 
By virtue of (43 :E) the elements of II r are also characterized by the fact 
that they decompose F into indecomposable constituents. 

43.4. Properties of the Decomposition Partition 

43.4.1. The nature of the decomposition partition Ilr being established, 
it is natural to study the effect of the fineness of this partition. We wish to 
analyze only the two extreme possibilities: When II r is as fine as possible, 
i.e. when it dissects / down to the one-element sets and when Er is as coarse 
as possible, i.e. when it does not dissect I at all. In other words: In the first 
case Hr is the system of all one-element sets (in 7) in the second case Ilr 
consists of / alone. 

The meaning of these two extreme cases is easily established: 

(43 :J) n r is the system of all one-element sets (in 7) if and only if 

the game is inessential. 

Proof: It is clear from (43 :H) or (43 :H*) that the stated property of 
H r is equivalent of saying that all sets J(s. 7) are splitting. I.e. (by 43.1.) 
that for any two complementary sets J and K(= I J) the game F is 
decomposable. This means that (41:6) holds in all those cases. This 
implies, however, that the condition imposed by (41 :6) on S, T (i.e. S Si J, 
T K) means merely that S, T are disjunct. Thus our statement becomes 

v(S u T) = v(S) + v(!T) for S n T = 

Now this is precisely the condition of inessentiality by (27 :D) in 27.4.2. 
(43 :K) n r consists of 7 if and only if the game F is indecomposable. 

Proof: It is clear from (43:H) (or (43:H*)), that the stated property of 
Ilr is equivalent to saying that 0, 7 are the only splitting sets. But this 
is exactly the definition of indecomposability at the beginning of 43.3. 

These result^ show that indecomposability and inessentiality are two 
opposite extremes for a game. In particular, inessentiality means that the 
decomposition of F, described at the end of 43.3., can be pushed thrdugh 
to the individual players, without ever severing any tie that the rules of the 
game F establish. 2 The reader should compare this statement with our 
original definition of inessentiality in 27.3.1. 

43.4.2. The connection between inessentiality, decomposability, and 
the number n of players is as follows: 

n = 1: This case is scarcely of practical importance. Such a game is 
clearly indecomposable, 8 and it is at the same time inessential by the first 
remark in 27.5.2. 

1 I.e. without impairing the self-containedness of the resulting sets. 

2 I.e. that every player is self-contained in this game. 

3 As / is a one-element set , / are its only subsets. 



358 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

It should then be noted that indecomposability and inessentiality are 
by (43 :J), (43 :K) incompatible when n ^ 2, but not when n = 1. 

n = 2: Such a game, too, is necessarily inessential by the first remark oi 
27.5.2. Hence it is decomposable. 

n ^ 3: For these games decomposability is an exceptional occurrence, 
Indeed, decomposability implies (41:6) with some J ^ Q, I] hence K = 
/ - J T* 0, /. So we can choose j in J, k in K. Then (41 :6) with S = (j), 
T = (k) gives 

(43:11) v((j, A;)) = v((j)) + v((fc)). 

Now the only equations which the values of v(S) must satisfy, are (25:3:a), 
(25:3:b) of 25.3.1. (if zero-sum games are considered) or (42:6:a), (42:6:bj 
of 42.3.2. (43:11) is neither of these, since only the sets (j), (fc), (j, k] 
occur in (43:11) and these are none of the sets occurring in those equations 
i.e. or 7 or complements as n ^ 3. 1 Thus (43:11) is an extra condition 
which is not fulfilled in general. 

By the above an indecomposable game cannot have n = 2 hence it has 
n = 1 or n ^ 3. Combining this with (43 :E), we obtain the following 
peculiar result: 

(43 :L) Every element of the decomposition partition Tlr is either a 

one-element set, or else it has n ^ 3 elements. 

Note that the one-element sets in II r are the one-element splitting sets' 
i.e. they correspond to those players who are self-contained, separatee 
from the remainder of the game (from the point of view of the strategy oi 
coalitions). They are the " dummies " in the sense of 35.2.3. and footnote 1 
on p. 340. Consequently, our result (43 :L) expresses this fact : Those playen 
who are not "duYnmies," are grouped in indecomposable constituent game* 
of n ^ 3 players each. 

This appears to be a general principle of social organization. 

44. Decomposable Games. Further Extension of the Theory 
44.1. Solutions of a (Decomposable) Game and Solutions of Its Constituents 

44.1. We have completed the descriptive part of our study of composi 
tion and decomposition. Let us now pass to the central part of the problem 
The investigation of the solutions in a decomposable game. 

Consider a game T which is decomposable for J and / J = K, wit! 
the J- and /^-constituents A and H. We use strategic equivalence, as 
explained at the beginning of 42.5.3., to make all three games zero-sum. 

Assume that the solutions for A as well as those for H are known; doei 
this then determine the solution for T? In other words: How do th< 
solutions for a decomposable game obtain from those for its constituents? 

Now there exists a surmise in this respect which appears to be the prime 
facie plausible one, and we proceed to formulate it. 

1 For n = 2 it is otherwise; (j, k) /, (j) and (A;) are complements. 
1 Such a splitting set is, of course, automatically minimal. 



DECOMPOSABLE GAMES 359 

44.2. Composition and Decomposition of Imputations and of Sets of Imputations 

44.2.1. Let us use the notations of 41.3.1. But as we write v(S) for 
Vr(S) this also replaces by (41:4), (41:5), v A (S), v H (5). 

On the other hand, we must distinguish between imputations for 
F, A, H. 1 In expressing this distinction, it is better to indicate the set of 
players to whom an imputation refers, instead of the game in which they are 
engaged. I.e. we will affix to them the symbols /, /, K rather than F, A, H. 
In this sense we denote the imputations for I (i.e. T) by 

(44:1) a j = {i>, , *>, ai, * , r}, 

and those for J, K (i.e. A, H) by 

(44:2) 7/= {0i', ,0*}, 

(44:3) 7* = {7i", ' ,7r). 

If three such imputations are linked by the relationship 

(44.4^ *' = &' for *' = r > ' ' ' > k '> 

( ** A) a,. = 7," for j" = 1", ' , I", 

> > + 

then we say that a / obtains by composition for /, 7 *, that /, 7 * obtain 

by decomposition from a / (for J, If), and that /, 7 K are the (/-, K-) 

constituents of a /. 

Since we are now dealing with zero-sum games, all these imputations 
must fulfill the conditions (30:1), (30:2) of 30.1.1. Now one verifies 

immediately for a/, ft j, y K linked by (44:4). 

Ad (30:1) of 30.1.1. : The validity of this for /, y K is clearly equivalent 
to its validity for a /. 

Ad (30:2) of 30.1.1.: For "/?/, ~y K this states (using (44:4)) 

*' 

(44:5) X ** = > 

t'-r 
i" 

(44:6) a, = 0. 

y-i" 

For a / it amounts to 

*' i" 

(44:7) J) <*' + ,- = 0. 

'!' ;_!/, 

1 It is now convenient to re-introduce the notations of 41.3.1. for the players. 



360 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

Thus its validity for /3 j, y K implies the same for a /, while its validity 

for a i does not imply the same for /, y K indeed (44:7) does imply the 
equivalence of (44:5) and (44:6), but it fails to imply the validity of either 
one. 

So we have: 

(44: A) Any two imputations ft /, y K can be composed to an a/, 

while an imputation a / can be decomposed of two /, y K if and 
only if it fulfills (44:5), i.e. (44:6). 


We call such an a / decomposable (for J, K). 

44.2.2. This situation is similar to that, which prevails for the games 
themselves: Composition is always possible, while decomposition is not. 
Decomposability is again an exceptional occurrence. 1 

It ought to be noted, finally, that the concept of composition of imputa- 
tions has a simple intuitive meaning. It corresponds to the same operation 
of " vie wing as one" two separate occurrences, which played the correspond- 
ing role for games in 41.2.1., 41.2.3., 41.2.4. Decomposition of an a / 
(into ft /, y K) is possible if and only if the two self-contained sets of players 

J, K are given by the sets of imputations a / precisely their " just dues" 
which are zero. This is the meaning of the condition (44 :A) (i.e. of (44:5), 
(44:6)). 

44.2.3. Consider a set V/ of imputations / and a set W/c of imputations 
> > 

y K. Let U/ be the set of those imputations a / which obtain by composition 

> 

of all ft j in V/ with all 7 K in Wx. We then say that U/ obtains by compo- 
sition from V/, Wxi that V/, W* obtain by decomposition from U/ (for 
JT, K\ and that V/, W* are the (J-, K-) constituents of U/. 

Clearly the operation of composition can always be carried out, what- 
ever V/t WK whereas a given U/ need not allow decomposition (for J, K). 
If U/ can be decomposed, we call it decomposable (for J, K). 

Note that this decomposability of U/ restricts it very strongly; it implies, 

among other things that all elements a / of U/ must be decomposable (cf . 
the interpretation at the end of 44.2.2.). 

In order to interpret these concepts for the sets of imputations U/ f V/, 
Wx more thoroughly, it is convenient to restrict ourselves to solutions 
of the games r, A, H. 

1 There are great technical differences between the concepts of decomposability etc., 
for games and for imputations. Observe, however, the analogy between (41:4), (41:5) 
in 41.3.2.; (41:8), (41:9), (41 :1(V) in 41. 4.2.; and our (44:4), (44:5), (44:6), (44:7). 



DECOMPOSABLE GAMES 361 

44.3. Composition and Decomposition of Solutions. 
The Main Possibilities and Surmises 

44.3.1. Let V/f W* be two solutions for the games A, H respectively. 
Their composition yields an imputation set U/ which one might expect 
to be a solution for the game F. Indeed, U/ is the expression of a standard 
of behavior which can be formulated as follows. We give the verbal formula- 
tion in the text under (44:B:a)-(44:B:c), stating the mathematical equiva- 
lents in footnotes, which, as the reader will verify, add up precisely to our 
definition of composition. 

(44:B:a) The players of J always obtain together exactly their 

"just dues" (zero), and the same is true for the players of K. 1 

(44:B:b) There is no connection whatever between the fate of play- 

ers in the set / and in the set K. 2 

(44:B:c) The fate of the players in J is governed by the standard of 

behavior Vj> 3 the fate of the players in K is governed by the 
standard of behavior W*. 4 

If the two constituent games are imagined to occur absolutely separate 
from each other, then this is the plausible way of viewing their separate 
solutions Vy, W/c as one solution U/ of the composite game F. 

However, since a solution is an exact concept, this assertion needs a 
proof. I.e. we must demonstrate this: 

(44 :C) If V/, W* are solutions of A, H, then their composition U/ is 

a solution of F. 

44.3.2. This, by the way, is another instance of the characteristic 
relationship between common sense and mathematical rigour. Although 
an assertion (in the present case that U/ is a solution whenever V/, W* are) 
is required by common sense, it has no validity within the theory (in this 
case based on the definitions of 30.1.1.) unless proved mathematically. To 
this extent it might seem that rigour is more important than common sense. 
This, however, is limited by the further consideration that if the mathe- 
matical proof fails to establish the common sense result, then there is a 
strong case for rejecting the theory altogether. Thus the primate of the 
mathematical procedure extends only to establish checks on the theories 
in a way which would not be open to common sense alone. 

1 Every element a / of U/ is decomposable. 

* Any / which is used in forming U/ and any 7 *, which is used in forming U/, give 

> 
by composition an element a / of U/. 

* The above mentioned / are precisely the elements of V/. 

4 The above mentioned y K are precisely the elements of W/c. 



362 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

It will be seen that (44 :C) is true, although not trivial. 

One might be tempted to expect that the converse of (44 :C) is also 
true, i.e. to demand a proof of this: 

(44 :D) If U/ is a solution of F, then it can be decomposed into solu- 

tions V,, W* of A, H. 

This is prima facie quite plausible: Since F is the composition of what 
are for all intents and purposes two entirely separate -games, how could any 
solution of F fail to exhibit tjiis composite structure? 

The surprising fact is, however, that (44 :D) is not true in general. 
The reader might think that this should induce us to abandon or at least 
to modify materially our theory (i.e. 30.1.1.) if we take the above method- 
ological statement seriously. Yet we will show, that the " common sense " 
basis for (44 :D) is quite questionable. Indeed, our result, contradicting 
(44 :D) will provide a very plausible interpretation which connects it 
successfully with well known phenomena in social organizations. 

44.3.3. The proper understanding of the failure of (44 :D) and of the 
validity of the theory which replaces it, necessitates rather detailed con- 
siderations. Before we enter upon these, it might be useful to make, in 
anticipation, some indications as to how the failure of (44 :D) occurs. 

It is natural, to split (44 :D) into two assertions: 

(44:D:a) If U/ is a solution of F, then it is decomposable (for J, K). 

(44:D:b) If a solution U/ of F is decomposable (for /, K), then its 

constituents V/, W/c are solutions for A, H. 

Now it will appear that (44:D:b) is true, and (44:D:a) is false. I.e. 
it can happen that a decomposable game F possesses an indecomposable 
solution. 1 

However, the decomposability of a solution (or of any set of imputations) 
is expressed by (44:B:a)-(44:B:c) in 44.3.1. So one or more of these condi- 
tions must fail for the indecomposable solution referred to above. Now 
it will be seen (cf. 46.11.) that the condition which is not satisfied is (44:B:a). 
This may seem to be very grave, because (44:B:a) is the primary condition 
in the sense that when it fails, the conditions (44:B:b), (44:B:c) cannot 
even be formulated. 

The concept of decomposition possesses a certain elasticity. This 
appeared_jn 42.2.1., 42.2.2. and 42.5.2., where we succeeded in ridding 
ourselves of an inconvenient auxiliary condition connected with the decom- 
posability of a game by modifying that concept. It will be seen that our 
difficulties will again be met by this procedure so that (44 :D) will be 
replaced by a correct and satisfactory theorem. Hence we must aim at 
modifying our arrangements, so that the condition (44 :B :a) can be discarded. 

We will succeed in doing this, and then it will appear that conditions 
(44:B:b), (44:B:c) make no difficulties and that a complete result can be 
obtained. 

1 This is similar to the phenomenon that a symmetric game may possess an asym- 
metric solution. Cf. 37.2.1. 



DECOMPOSABLE GAMES 383 

44.4. Extension of the Theory. Outside Sources 
44.4.1. It is now time to discard the normalization which we introduced 

(temporarily) in 44.1.: That the games under consideration are zero-sum. 

We return to the standpoint of 42.2.2. according to which the games are 

constant-sum. 

These being understood, consider a game F which is decomposable 

(for J, K) with J-, -K-constituents A, H. 

The theory of composability and decomposability of imputations, as 

given in 44.2.1., 44.2.2. could now be repeated with insignificant changes. 

(44:l)-(44:4) may be taken over literally, while (44:5)-(44:7) are only 

modified in their right hand sides. Since (30:2) of 30.1.1. has been replaced 

by (42:8*) of 42.4.1. those formulae (44:5)-(44:7) now become: 

k' 

(44:5*) a,- = v(J), 

i'-r 

(44:6*) rv(K) f 

/'!" 

and 

(44:7*) | , + or = v(7) = v(J) + v(K). 

i'-i' /'-i" 

(The last equation on the right hand side by (42:6:b) in 42.3.2., or equally 
by (41:6) in 41.3.2. with S = /, T = K.) The situation is exactly as in 
44.2.1., indeed, it really arises from that one by the isomorphism of 42.4.2. 

Thus a i fulfills (44:7*), but for its decomposability (44:5*), (44:6*) are 
needed and (44:7*) does imply the equivalence of (44:5*) and (44:6*), 
but it fails to imply the validity of either. 

So the criterion of decomposability (44 :A) in 44.2.1. is again true, only 
with our (44:5*), (44:6*) in place of its (44:5), (44:6). And the final con- 

clusion of 44.2.2. may be repeated: Decomposition of an a / (into ft /, y K ) 
is possible if and only if the two self contained sets of players J, K are 

given by this imputation a / precisely their just dues which are now v(J), 



Since we know that this limitation of the decomposability of imputa- 
tions the reason for (44:B:a) in 44.3.1. is a source of difficulties, we have 
to remove it. This means removal of the conditions (44:5*), (44:6*), i.e. 
of the condition (42:8*) in 42.4.1. from which they originate. 

44.4.2. According to the above, we will attempt to work the theory of a 
constant-sum game F with a new concept of imputations, which is based on 
(42:7) of 42.4.1. (i.e. on (30:1) of 30.1.1.) alone, without (42:8*) in 42.4.1. 
In other words 2 

1 Instead of zero, as loc. cit. 

* We again denote the players by 1, , n. 



364 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

An extended imputation is a system of numbers ai, , a n with this 
property: 

(44:8) <* ^ v((t)) for i = I, , n. 

n 

We impose no conditions upon -. We view these extended imputa- 
tions, too, as vectors 



44.4.3. It will now be necessary to reconsider all our definitions which are 
rooted in the concepts of imputation i.e. those of 30.1.1. and 44.2.1. But, 
before we do this, it is well to interpret this notion of extended imputations. 

The essence of this concept is that it represents a distribution of certain 
amounts between the players, without demanding that they should total 
up to the constant sum of the game F. 

Such an arrangement would be extraneous to the picture that the players 
are only dealing with each other. However, we have always conceived of 
imputations as a distributive scheme proposed to the totality of all players. 
(This idea pervades, e.g. all of 4.4., 4.5.; it is quite explicit in 4.4.1.) Such 
a proposal may come from one of the players, 1 but this is immaterial. We 
can equally imagine, that outside sources submit varying imputations to 
the consideration of the players of F. All this harmonizes with our past 
considerations, but in all this, those "outside sources" manifested them- 
selves only by making suggestions without contributing to, or withdrawing 
from, the proceeds of the game. 

44.5. The Excess 

44.5.1. Now our present concept of extended imputations may be taken 
to express that the " outside sources " can make suggestions which actually 
involve contributions or withdrawals, i.e. transfers. For the extended 

imputation a = {i, ,} the amount of this transfer is 

n 

(44:9) e = % a, - v(/) 

-i 


and will be called the excess of a . Thus 

e > for a contribution, 

(44:10) e = if no transfer takes place, 

e < for a withdrawal. 

1 Who tries to form a coalition. Since we consider the entire imputation as his 
proposal, this necessitates our assuming that he is even making propositions to those 
players, who will not be included in the coalition. To these he may offer their respective 
minima v((t)) (possibly more, cf. 38.3.2. and 38.3.3.). There may also be players in 
intermediate positions "between included and excluded" (cf. the second alternative in 
37.1.3.). Of course, those less favored players may make their dissatisfaction effective, 
this leads to the concept of domination, etc. 



DECOMPOSABLE GAMES 365 

It will be necessary to subject this to certain suitable limitations, in 
order to obtain realistic problems; and we will take due account of this. 

It is important to realize how these transfers interact with the game. 
The transfers are part of the suggestions made from outside, which are 
accepted or rejected by the players, weighed against each other, according 
to the principles of domination, etc. 1 In the course of this process, any 
dissatisfied set of players may fall back upon the game F, which is the 
sole criterion of the effectivity of their preference of their situation in one 
(extended) imputation against another. 2 Thus the game, the physical 
background of the social process under consideration, determines the 
stability of all details of the organization but the initiative comes through 
the outside suggestions, circumscribed by the limitations of the excess 
referred to above. 

44.5.2. The simplest form that this "limitation" of the excess can take, 
consists in prescribing its value e explicitly. In interpreting this prescrip- 
tion, (44:10) should be remembered. 

The situation which exists when e . may at first seem paradoxical. 

This is particularly true when e < 0, i.e. when a withdrawal from outside 
is attempted. Why should the players, who could fall back on a game of 
constant sum v(/) accept an inferior total? I.e. how can a "standard of 
behavior/' a "social order," based on such a principle be stable? There is, 
nevertheless an answer: The game is only worth v(l) if all players form a 
coalition, act in concert. If they are split into hostile groups, then each 
group may have to estimate its chances more pessimistically and such a 
division may stabilize totals that are inferior to v(/). 3 

The alternative e > 0, i.e. when the outside interference consists of a 
free gift, may seem less difficult to accept. But in this case too, it will be 

1 This is, of course, a narrow and possibly even somewhat arbitrary description of the 
social process. It should be remembered, however, that we use it only for a definite and 
limited purpose: To determine stable equilibria, i.e. solutions. The concluding remarks 
of 4.6.3. should make this amply clear. 

2 We are, of course, alluding to the definitions of effectivity and domination, cf. 4.4.1. 
and the beginning of 4.4.3. given in exact form in 30.1.1. We will extend the exact 
definitions to our present concepts in 44.7.1. 

3 For a first quantitative orientation, in the heuristic manner: If the players are 
grouped into disjunct sets (coalitions) S\, , S p , then the total of their own valua- 
tions is v(Si) + + v(S P ). This is v(J) by (42:6:c) in 42.3.2. 

Oddly enough, this sum is actually v(7) when p - 2 by (42:6:b) in 42.3.2. 
i.e. in this model the disagreements between three or more groups are the effective sources 
of damage. 

Clearly by (42:6:c) in 42.3.2. the above sums v(8i) + + v(S p ) are all 

n 

g> V v ((*')). On the other hand, this latter expression is one of them (put p n, 

t-i 
S K (t)). So the damage is greatest when each player is isolated from all others. 

n 

The whole phenomenon disappears, therefore, when ^ v((i)) v(7) , i.e. when the 

t-i 
game is inessential. (Cf. (42:11) in 42.5.1.) 



366 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

necessary to study the game in order to see how the distribution of this 
gift among the players can be governed by stable arrangements. It has to 
be expected, that the optimistic appraisal of their own chances, derived 
from the possibilities of the various coalitions in which they might par- 
ticipate will determine the players in making their claims. The theory 
must then provide their adjustment to the available total. 

44.6. Limitations of the Excess. 
The Non-isolated Character of a Game in the New Setup 

44.6.1. These considerations indicate that the excess e must be neither 
too small (when e < 0), nor too large (when e > 0). In the former case a 
situation would arise where each player would prefer to fall back on the 
game, even if the worst should happen, i.e. if he has to play it isolated. 1 
In the latter case it will happen that the "free gift" is "too large," i.e. that 
no player in any imagined coalition can make such claims as to exhaust the 
available total. Then the very magnitude of the gift will act as a dissolvent 
on the existing mechanisms of organizations. 

We will see in 45. that these qualitative considerations are correct 
and we will get from rigorous deductions the details of their operation and 
the precise value of the excess at which they become effective. 

44.6.2. In all these considerations the game F can no longer be con- 
sidered as an isolated occurrence, since the excess is a contribution or a 
withdrawal by an outside source. This makes it intelligible that this 
whole train of ideas should come up in connection with the decomposition 
theory of the game F. The constituent games A, H are indeed no longer 
entirely isolated, but coexistent with each other. 2 Thus, there is a good 
reason to look at A, H in this way whether the composite game F should 
be treated in the old manner (i.e. as isolated), or in the new one, may be 
debatable. We shall see, however, that this ambiguity for F does not 
influence the result essentially, whereas the broader attitude concerning A, 
H proves to be absolutely necessary (cf. 46.8.3. and also 46.10.). 

When a game F is considered in the above sense, as a non-isolated 
occurrence, with contributions or withdrawals by an outside source, one 
might be tempted to do this: Treat this outside source also as a player, 
including him together with the other players into a larger game F'. The 
rules of F' (which includes F) must then be devised in such a manner as to 
provide a mechanism for the desired transfers. We shall be able to meet 
this demand with the help of our final results, but the problem has some 
intricacies that are better considered only at that stage. 

n 

1 This happens when the proposed total v(/) + e is < v((i)). As the last expres- 

-i 
sion is equal to v(7) ny (by (42:11) in 42.5.1.) this means e < ny. 

We will see in 45.1. that this is precisely the criterion for e being "too small/' 
' This in spite of the absence of "interactions," as far as the rules of the game are 
concerned; cf. 41.2.3., 41.2.4. 



DECOMPOSABLE GAMES 367 



44.7. Discussion of the New Setup (i ), 

44.7.1. The reconsideration of our old definitions mentioned at the 
beginning of 44.4.3. is a very simple matter. 

For the extended imputations we have the new definitions of 44.4.2. 
The definitions of effectivity and domination we take over unchanged from 
30.1. 1. 1 the supporting arguments brought forward in the discussion which 
led up to those definitions appear to lose no strength by our present general- 
izations. The same applies to our definition of solutions eod. 2 with one 
caution: The definition of a solution referred to makes the concept of a 
solution dependent upon the set of all imputations in which it is formed. 
Now in our present setup of extended imputations we shall have to consider 
limitations concerning them notably concerning their excesses as indi- 
cated in 44.5.1. These restrictions will determine the set of all extended 
imputations to be considered and thereby the concept of a solution. 

44.7.2. Specifically we shall consider two types of limitations. 

First, we shall consider the case where the value of the excess is pre- 
scribed. Then we have an equation 

(44:11) e = eo 

with a given e . The meaning of this restriction is that the transfer from 
outside is prescribed, in the sense of the discussion of 44.5.2. 

Second, we shall consider the case where only an upper limit of the excess 
is prescribed. Then we have an inequality 

(44:12) e g e 

with a given e . The meaning of this restriction is that the transfer from 
outside is assigned a maximum (from the point of view of the players who 
receive it). 

The case in which we are really interested is the first one, i.e. that one 
of 44.5.2. The second case will prove technically useful for the clarification 
of the first one although its introduction may at first seem artificial. 
We refrain from considering further alternatives because we will be able to 
complete the indicated discussion with these two cases alone. 

Denote the set of all extended imputations fulfilling (44:11) (first case) 
by E(eo). Considering (44:9) in 44.5.1., we can write (44:11) as 

n 

(44:11*) = v(7) + e . 

-i 

Denote the set of all extended imputations fulfilling (44:12) (second case) 
by F(e Q ). Considering (44:9) in 44.5.1., we can write (44:12) as 

n 
(44:12*) g v(7) + e,. 

i-l 

1 I.e. (30:3); (30:4:a)-(30:4:c) loc. cit., respectively. 
8 I.e. (30:5:a), (30:5:b) or (30:5:c) eod. 



368 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

For the sake of completeness, we repeat the characterization of an extended 
imputation which must be added to (44:11*), as well as to (44:12*): 

(44:13) a, v((0), for i = 1, - , n. 

Note that the definitions of (44:9) as well as (44:11*), (44:12*) and (44:13) 
are invariant under the isomorphism of 42.4.2. 

44.7.3. Now the definition of a solution can be taken over from 30.1.1. 
Because of the central role of this concept we restate that definition, adjusted 
to the present conditions. Throughout the definition which follows, E(e^) 
can be replaced by F(e<>), as indicated by [ ]. 

A set V E(eo) [F(ed)] is a solution for E(e Q ) [F(eo)] if it possesses the follow- 
ing properties: 



(44:E:a) No in V is dominated by an a in V. 

(44:E:b) Every /} of E(e*)[F(e 9 )] not in V is dominated by some a 

inV. 

(44:E:a) and (44:E:b) can be stated as a single condition: 

(44:E:c) The elements of V are those elements of E(e<>) [F(eo)] which 

are undominated by any element of V. 

It will be noted that E(0) takes us back to the original 30.1.1. (zero-sum 
game) and 42.4.1. (constant-sum game). 

44.7.4. The concepts of composition, decomposition and constituents 
of extended imputations can again be defined by (44:l)-(44:4) of 44.2.1. 
As pointed out in 44.4.2. the technical purpose of our extending the concept 
of imputation is now fulfilled. Decomposition as well as composition can 
now always be carried out. 

The connection of these concepts with the sets E(e ) and F(eo) is not so 
simple; we will deal with it as the necessity arises. 

For the composition, decomposition and constituents of sets of extended 
imputations the definitions of 44.2.3. can now be repeated literally. 

45. Limitations of the Excess. Structure of the Extended Theory 
45.1. The Lower Limit of the Excess 

45.1. In the setups of 30.1.1. and of 42.4.1. imputations always existed. 
It is now different: Either set E(e ), F(e Q ) may be empty for certain e . 
Obviously this happens when (44:11*) or (44:12*) of 44.7.2. conflict with 
(44:13) eodem and this is clearly the case for 

v(7) + eo < v((i)) 
-i 

in both alternatives. As the right hand side is equal to v(7) ny by 
(42:11) in 42.5.1., this means 

(45:1) e < -ny 



STRUCTURE OF THE EXTENDED THEORY 369 

If J(e ) [F(e<>)] is empty, then the empty set is clearly a solution for it 
and since it is its only subset, it is also its only solution. 1 If, on the other 
hand, E(e ) [F(e )] is not empty, then none of its solutions can be empty. 
This follows by literal repetition of the proof of (31 :J) in 31.2.1. 

The right hand side of the inequality (45:1) is determined by the game 
T; we introduce this notation for it (with the opposite sign, and using (42:11) 
in 42.5.1.): 

(45:2) |rK = ny = v(/) - v((t)). 

-i 

Now we can sum up our observations as follows: 

(45: A) If 

o <- |r|,, 

then E(e Q ), F(e ) are empty and the empty set is their only 
solution. Otherwise neither E(e<j) nor F(e ) nor any solution of 
either can be empty. 

This result gives the first indication, that "too small" values of e 
(i.e. e) in the sense of 44.6.1. exist. Actually, it corroborates the quanti- 
tative estimate of footnote 1 on p. 366. 

45.2. The Upper Limit of the Excess. Detached and Fully Detached Imputations 

45.2.1. Let us now turn to those values of e (i.e. e), which are "too 
large " in the sense of 44.6.1. When does the disorganizing influence of 
the magnitude of e, which we there foresaw, manifest itself? 

As indicated in 44.6.1., the critical phenomenon is this: The excess 
may be too large to be exhausted by the claims which any player in any 
imagined coalition can possibly make. We proceed to formulate this idea 
in a quantitative way. 

It is best to consider the extended imputations a themselves, instead 

of their excesses e. Such an a is past any claims which may be made in 
any coalition, if it assigns to the players of each (non-empty) set S I 
more than those players could get by forming a coalition in F, i.e. if 

(45:3) 2v cti > v(S) for every non-empty set S & I. 

in S 

Comparing this with (30:3) in 30.1.1. shows that our criterion amounts to 


demanding that every non-empty set S be ineffective for a . 

In our actual deductions it will prove advantageous to widen (45:3) 
somewhat by including the limiting case of equality. The condition then 
becomes 

1 In spite of its triviality, this circumstance should not be overlooked. The text 
actually repeats footnote 2 on p. 278. 



370 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 
(45:4) <xi v(S) for every SsL 1 

iinS 

* 

It is convenient to give these a a name. We call the a of (45:3) fully 
detached, and those of (45:4) detached. As indicated, the latter concept 
will be really needed in our proofs both termini are meant to express that 
the extended imputation is detached from the game, i.e. that it cannot be 
effectively supported within the game by any coalition. 

45.2.2. One more remark is useful: 

The only restriction imposed upon extended imputations is (44:13) of 
44.7.2.: 

(45:5) a t ^ v((i)) for i = 1, , n. 

Now if the requirement (45:4) of detachedness is fulfilled and hence 
a fortiori if the requirement (45:3) of full detachedness is fulfilled then it is 
unnecessary to postulate the condition (45:5) as well. Indeed, (45:5) 
is the special case of (45:4) for S = (i). 

This remark will be made use of implicitly in the proofs which follow. 

45.2.3. Now we can revert to the excesses, i.e. characterize those which 
belong to detached (or fully detached) imputations. This is the formal 
characterization : 

(45 :B) The game F determines a number |r| 2 with the following 

properties: 
(45:B:a) A fully detached extended imputation with the excess e 

exists if and only if 

e > |r| 2 . 

(45:B:b) A detached extended imputation with the excess e exists 

if and only if 

e ^ |r|,. 

Proof: Existence of a detached a 3 : Let a be the maximum of all v(S), 

S Si (so a ^ v(0) = 0). Put ^ = {aj, , aj} = (a, , a }. 
Then for every non-empty S S I we have a? ^ a ;> v(5). This is 

inS 

(45:4), so a is detached. 

1 It is no longer necessary to exclude S - , since (45:4) unlike (45:3) is true when 
8 . Indeed, then both sides vanish. 

J The intuitive meaning of these statements is quite simple: It is plausible that in 
order to produce a detached or a fully detached imputation, a certain (positive) minimum 
excess is required. |r| t is this minimum, or rather lower limit. Since the notions 
"detached" and "fully detached" differ only in a limiting case (the - sign in (45:4)), 
it stands to reason that their lower limits be the same. These things find an exact 
expression in (45 :B). 

8 Note that it is necessary to prove this! The evaluation which we give here is crude, 
for more precise ones cf. (45 :F) below. 



STRUCTURE OF THE EXTENDED THEORY 371 

Properties of the detached a : According to the above, detached 



a = {!, , a n ] 

n 

exist, and with them their excesses e = a< v(7). By (45:4) (with 

t-i 
8 = 1) all these e are 2> 0. Hence it follows by continuity, that these e have 

a minimum e*. Choose a detached a * = {af, , a*} with this excess 
e*. 1 

We now put 

(45:6) |r|, = e*. 

Proof ot (45:B:a), (45:B:b): If V = {ai, , a n } is detached, then by 

n . 

definition e = on v(7) ^ e*. If a = {i, , a n ) is fully detached, 

i- 1 

then (45:3) remains true if we subtract a sufficiently small 6 > from 
each oti. So a' = {on 5, , a n 8} is detached. Hence by defini- 

n 

tion e - nb = (a< - ) - v(7) ^ e*, e > e*. 
i-i 

Consider now the detached a * = {af, , a*) with 

a* - v(7) = e*. 
-i 

Then (45:4) holds for a*; hence (45:3) holds if we increase each a* by a 
$ > 0. So a" = (a* + 5, , a* + 6j is fully detached. Its excess is 

n 

= (a* + 5) - v(7) = e* + n5. So every e = e* + n, 6 > 0, i.e. 

i-l 

every e > e*, is the excess of a fully detached imputation hence a fortiori 

of a detached one; and e* is, of course, the excess of a detached imputation 

a*. 

Thus all parts of (45:B:a), (45:B:b) hold for (45:6). 

46.2.4. The fully detached and the detached extended imputations are 
also closely connected with the concept of domination. The properties 
involved are given in (45 :C) and (45 :D) below. They form a peculiar anti- 
thesis to each other. This is remarkable, since our two concepts are strongly 
analogous to each other indeed, the second one arises from the first one by 
the inclusion of its limiting cases. 

1 This continuity argument is valid because the = sign is included in (45:4). 



372 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 



(45 :C) A fully detached extended imputation a dominates no other 


extended imputation ft . 

Proof: If a H 0, then a must possess a non-empty effective set. 

(45 :D) An extended imputation a is detached if and only if it is 

dominated by no other extended imputation ft . 

Proof: Sufficiency of being detached: Let a = {ai, ,a n } be detached. 

Assume a contrario ft H a , with the effective set S. Then S is not empty; 
< fti for i in S. So 2} < 2} ft ^ v(5) contradicting (45:4). 

t in 8 f in 8 

Necessity of being detached: Assume that a = {i, , a n } is not 
detached. Let S be a (necessarily non-empty) set for which (45:4) fails, 
i.e. oti < v(S). Then for a sufficiently small 6 > 0, even 

(<* + *) v(S). 

tin S 


Put = {0i, , ft n \ = {ai + 6, , a n + $}, then always a< < ft 
and 5 is effective for ft : ft g v(5). Thus H a . 

45.3. Discussion of the Two Limits |r|i, |r t |. Their Ratio 

45.3.1. The two numbers |r|i and |F| 2 , as defined in (45:2) of 45.1. 
and in (45 :B) of 45.2.3. are both in a way quantitative measures of the 
essentiality of F. More precisely: 

(45 :E) If F is inessential, then JF^ = 0, |F| 2 = 0. 

If F is essential, then |F|i > 0, |F| 2 > 0. 

Proof: The statements concerning |F|i, which is = ny by (45:2) of 45.1., 
coincide with the definitions of inessentiality and essentiality of 27.3., as 
reasserted in 42.5.1. 

The statements concerning |F| 2 follow from those concerning |F|i, by 
means of the inequalities of (45 :F), which we can use here. 

45.3.2. The quantitative relationship of |F|i and |F| 2 is charactenzed as 
follows: 

Always 



(45:F) 



-^rirai 



STRUCTURE OF THE EXTENDED THEORY 373 

Proof: As we know, |F|i and |r| 8 are invariant under strategic equivalence, 
hence we may assume the game T to be zero-sum, and even reduced in the 
sense of 27.1.4. We can now use the notations and relations of 27.2. 

Since |T|i = ny, we want to prove that 

(45:7) jJLj y g |r|, * Sfef^ y. 

Proof of the first inequality of (45:7): Let a = {ai, , a w ) be 
detached. Then (45:4) gives for the (n - l)-element set 8 = I - (fc), 

n 

5) ai ctk = 5) on ^ v(S) = 7, i.e. 

-1 



r 



(45:8) , - * r 

n r. 

Summing (45:8) over k = 1, . n, gives n ] a a* 

i-l *-l 

n n n 

i.e. (n 1) ^ a ^ 717, ^ a : - y 7. Now v(7) = 0, so e = ^ a*. 

Thus e ^ r 7 for all detached imputations; hence |F|t ; r 7. 

n 1 w 1 

Proof of the second inequality of (45:7): 

Put a 00 = ^-y^7, and ^ = {a?, - , aj } = {a 00 , , a 00 }. 

This a is detached, i.e. it fulfills (45:4) for all S fi I. Indeed: Let p be 
the number of elements of S. Now we have: 

p = Q: 5 = , (45:4) is trivial. 

p = 1: S = (t), (45:4) becomes a 00 ^ v((i)), 

n 2 . i - i i 

i.e. s y ^ ~~~7 which is obvious. 

p ^ 2: (45:4) becomes pa 00 ^ v(S), but by (27:7) in 27.2. 

vGS) ^ (n - p)7, 

n 2 
so it suffices to prove pa 00 2> (n p)7 i.e. p ^ 7 ^ (w p)7. This 

amounts to p 7 ^ ^7> which follows from p ^ 2. 

Thus a is indeed detached. As v(/) = 0, the excess is 
e oo na oo = n(n ^" 2) 7 . 

Hence |r|i ^ 7- 



374 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

46.3.3. It is worth while to consider the inequalities of (45 :F) for 
n = 1,2,3,4, successively: 

n = 1,2: In these cases the coefficient j of the lower bound of the 

n 

inequality is greater than the coefficient 5 of the upper bound., 1 This 

z 

may seem absurd. But since F is necessarily inessential for n = 1,2 (cf. 
the first remark in 27.5.2.), we have in these cases |r|i = 0, |r|i = 0, and 

so the contradictions disappear. 

1 ^ o 

n = 3: In this case the two coefficients T and s coincide: 

n I 2 

Both are equal to i. So the inequalities merge to an equation: 
(45:9) |r|, = ilrK. 

n ^ 4: In these cases the coefficient ^ of the lower bound is definitely 

^ o 

smaller than the coefficient = of the upper bound. 2 So now the inequal- 

JL 

ities leave a non- vanishing interval open for |F 2 |. 

The lower bound |F| 2 = ^r |F|i is precise, i.e. there exists for each 

ft L. 

n ^ 4 an essential game for which it is assumed. There also exist for each 
n ^ 4 essential games with |F| 2 > r |F|i, but it is probably not pos- 

n 2 
sible to reach the upper bound of our inequality, |F| 2 = ~ l r li- The 

i 

precise value of the upper bound has not yet been determined. We do not 
need to discuss these things here any further. 8 

45.3.4. In a more qualitative way, we may therefore say that |F|i,|F|j 
are both quantitative measures of the essentiality of the game F. They 
measure it in two different, and to a certain extent, independent ways. 
Indeed, the ratio |F| 2 /|F|i, which never occurs for n = 1,2 (no essential 
games!), and is a constant for n = 3 (its value is ^), is variable with F for 
each n ^ 4. 

We saw in 45.1., 45.2., that these two quantities actually measure the 
limits, within which a dictated excess will not " disorganize " the players, 
in the sense of 44.6.1. Judging from our results, an excess e < |F|i is 
"too small" antl an excess e > |F| 2 is "too great" in that sense. This 
view will be corroborated in a much more precise sense in 46.8. 

1 They are , - } for n - 1 ; 1, for n 2. Note also the paradoxical values <* and 
-i! 

1 ti 2 

s __ < .- means 2 < (n l)(n 2) which is clearly the case for all n 4. 

1 For n 4 our inequality is J |r|i ^ |r|i |r|i. As mentioned above, we know an 
itial game with |r| 8 - J |r|i and also one with |r| - i |r|i. 



STRUCTURE OF THE EXTENDED THEORY 375 

46.4. Detached Imputations and Various Solutions. 
The Theorem Connecting (e ), F(e ) 

45.4.1. (44:E:c) in the definition of a solution in 44.7.3. and our result 
(45 :D) in 45.2.4. give immediately: 

(45 :G) A solution V for E(e^ [F(e )] must contain every detached 

extended imputation of E(e<>) [F(e )]. 

The importance of this result is due to its role in the following considera- 
tion. 

After what was said at the beginning of 44.7.2. about the roles of E(e^) 
and F(e ), the importance of establishing the complete inter-relationship 
between these two cases will be obvious. I.e. we must determine the 
connection between the solutions for E(e ) and F(e ). 

Now the whole difference between E(e Q ) and F(e Q ) and their solutions 
is not easy to appraise in an intuitive way. It is difficult to see a priori 
why there should be any difference at all: In the first case the "gift," made 
to the players from the outside, has the prescribed value e , in the second 
case it has the prescribed maximum value e . It is difficult to see how the 
"outside source/' which is willing to contribute up to e can ever be allowed 
to contribute less than e in a " stable " standard of behavior (i.e. solution). 
However, our past experience will caution us against rash conclusions in this 
respect. Thus we saw in 33.1. and 38.3. that already three and four-person 
games possess solutions in which an isolated and defeated player is not 
" exploited " up to the limit of the physical possibilities and the present 
case bears some analogy to that. 

45.4.2. (45 :G) permits us to make a more specific statement: 

A detached extended imputation a belongs by (45 :G) to every solution for 

F(e ), if it belongs to F(e ). On the other hand, a clearly cannot belong to 
any solution for E(e Q ) if it does not belong to E(e Q ). We now define: 

(45:10) D*(e<>) is the set of all detached extended imputations a in 

F(e ), but not in E(e ). 

So we see: Any solution of F(e ) contains all elements of D*(eo); any solu- 
tion of E(e<>) contains no element of D*(e ). Consequently F(e ) and E(e Q ) 
have certainly no solution in common if D*(e ) is not empty. 

Now the detached a of D*(e ) are characterized by having an excess 
e 6 , but not e = e i.e. by 

(45:11) e < e . 

From this we conclude: 

(45 :H) D*(e<>) is empty if and only if 

e, |r| t . 



376 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

Proof: Owing to (45 :B) and to (45:11) above, the non-emptiness of 
Z>*(e ) is equivalent to the existence of an e with |r|j g e < e i.e. to 
o > |r|j. Hence the emptiness of D*(e Q ) amounts to e Q ^ |r|a. 

Thus the solutions for F(e ) and for E(e$) are sure to differ, when eo> |F|i. 
This is further evidence that e<> is "too large " for normal behavior when it is 

> |r|. 

45.4.3. Now we can prove that the difference indicated above is the only 
one between the solutions for E(e*) and for F(e ). More precisely: 

(45:1) The relationship 

(45:12) V^W = VuD*(e ) 

establishes a one-to-one relationship between all solutions V 
for E(e Q ) and all solutions W for F(e ). 

This will be demonstrated in the next section. 

46.5. Proof of the Theorem 

45.5.1. We begin by proving some auxiliary lemmas. 

The first one consists of a perfectly obvious observation, but of wide 
applicability : 

(45 :J) Let the two extended imputations y = {71, , y n \ and 


5 == {81, , d n ] bear the relationship 

(45:13) 7, ^ 5, for all i = 1, , n\ 

then for every a , a H y implies a H 5 . 

The meaning of this result is, of course, that (45:13) expresses some 

> 
kind of inferiority of 6 to y in spite of the intransitivity of domination. 

This inferiority is, however, not as complete as one might expect. Thus 

one cannot make the plausible inference of y ** ft from 5 H ft , because the 



effectivity of a set S for & may not imply the same for y . (The reader 

should recall the basic definitions of 30.1.1.) 

It should also be observed, that (45 :J) emerges only because we have 
extended the concept of imputations. For our older definitions (cf. 42.4.1.) 

n n 

we would have had 2) 7 = ^ i<; hence y< ^ fl for all i = 1, , n 

t-i i-i 

necessitates % = 5, for all i == 1, , n, i.e. y = & . 

45.5.2. Now four lemmas leading directly to the desired proof of (45:1). 

y >, y ^ 

(45 :K) If a H ft with a detached and in F(e ) and ft in/?(e ), then 

there exists an a ' H ft with a ' detached and in E(e Q ). 



STRUCTURE OF THE EXTENDED THEORY 377 

Proof: Let S be the set of (30:4:a)-(30:4:c) in 30.1.1. for the domination 

a H ft . S = / would imply a { > ft for all i = 1, , n so 

, - v(J) > ft - v(/). 



n n 



But as o is in F(e ) and ft in U(e ), so % o - v(7) g e = ft v(7), 

contradicting the above. 

So S T* 7. Choose, therefore, an t' = 1, , n, not in S. Define 

a' = {a'j, , a' n } with 

A ~* 

choosing e ^ so that 2) < ~~ V CO = g o. Thus all o{ ^ ; hence a ' 

is detached and it is clearly in (e ). Again, as a( = on for i 5^ t'o hence 
for all i in S, so our a H /3 implies a ' H /3 . 

(45 :L) Every solution W for F(e ) has the form (45:12) of (45:1) 

for a unique V s E(eo). 1 

Proof: Obviously the V in question if it exists at all is the intersection 
W n E(ev), so it is unique. In order that (45:12) should hold for 



we need only that the remainder of W be equal to Z)*(eo), i.e. 
(45:14) W - E(e<>) = D*(e ). 

Let us therefore prove (45:14). 

Every element of D*(e<>) is detached and in F(e ) so it is in W by (45 :G). 
Again, it is not in E(e*\ so it is in W - E(e<>). Thus 



(45:15) W - E(e) 

If also 
(45:16) W-(eo)D*(eo), 

then (45:15), (45:16) together give (45:14), as desired. Assume therefore, 
that (45:16) is not true. 

Accordingly, consider an a = {i, , a n | in W E(eJ) and not 

n 

in D*(e ). Then a is in F(e ), but not in E(e<>), so a< - v(J) < e . As 

-i 

1 We do not yet assert that this V is a solution for f( t ) that will come in (45:M). 



378 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

a is not in >*(e ), this excludes its being detached. Hence there exists a 
non-empty set 8 with a < v(S). 

tin S 

Now form a ' = {&(, - , a' n } with 

a'i = cti + c for i in S, 
a< = a< for i not in S, 

n 

choosing > so that still <*( - v(7) g e and ; ^ v(S). So a ' 

\ I in S 

is in F(e ). If it is not in W, then (as W is a solution for F(e Q )) there exists 

>>> > > 

a ft in W with ft H a'. As all ^ , this implies ft H a by (45 :J). 

This is impossible, since both ft , a belong to (the solution) W. Hence a ' 
must be in W. Now ; > a t for all i in S, and <*< ^ v ( 5 )- So 

tin S 

a ' H a . But as both a ', a belong to (the solution) W, this is a contra- 
diction. 

(45 :M) The V of (45 :L) is a solution for E(e ). 

Proof: V c E(e ) is clear, and V fulfills (44:E:a) of 44.7.3. along with W 
(which is a solution for F(e Q )), since V W. So we need only verify 
(44:E:b) of 44.7.3. 

Consider a in #(<)), but not in V. Then /3 is also in F(e Q ) but not in 

W| hence there exists an a in W with a. H ft (W is a solution forF(e )!). 

> 
If this a belongs to E(e ), then it belongs to W n E(e Q ) = V, i.e. we have 

an a in E(e Q ) with a H ft . 

If a does not belong to E(e$), then it belongs to W #(e ) = D*(e ), 
and so it is detached. Thus a H ft , a detached and in f(eo). Hence there 

exists by (45 :K) an a ' H , a ' detached and in E(e<>). By (45 :G) this a ' 
belongs to W, (E(eo) sF(e ), W is a solution for F(e Q )\); hence it belongs 

to W n E(e Q ) = V. So we have an a ' in E(e Q ) with a ' *- .] 
Thus (44:E:b) of 44.7.3. holds at any rate. 

(45:N) If V is a solution for JZ(<* ), then the W of (45:12) in (45:1) 

is a solution for F(e ). 

Proof: WsF^o) is clear, so we must prove (44:E:a), (44:E:b) of 44.7.3. 
Ad (44 :E:a): Assume a H ft for two a , ft in W. a 8- ^3* and (45 :D) 
exclude that ft be detached. So is not in D*(e ), hence it is in 

W - D*(6 ) = V. 



STRUCTURE OF THE EXTENDED THEORY 379 

Hence a H ft excludes that a too be in (the solution) V. So a is in 

W - V = D*(o). 
Consequently a is detached. 

Now (45 :K) produces an a ' H ft which is detached and in E(e Q ). Being 

> - ^ 

detached, a' belongs by (45 :G) to (the solution for E(e Q )) V. As a ', ft 

both belong to (the solution) V and a ' H ft , this is a contradiction. 

Ad (44:E:b): Consider a T = {0i, , ftn] in F(c ), but not in W. 

Now form ft (c) = {^(e), , n (e)} = {fr + t, , n + } for every 
6^0. Let increase from until one of these two things occurs for the 
first time: 



(45:17) (0 is in 

(45:18) "/?() is detached. 2 

We distinguish these two possibilities: 

(45:17) happens first, say for c = ei ^ 0: ft (ci) is in E(e Q ), but it is not 
detached. 

If 1 = 0, then ft = ft (0) is in E(e Q ). As ft is not in V W, there 

> 

exists an a H in (the solution for E(e<>)) V. A fortiori a in W. 

Assume next *i > 0, and (ci) in V. As ft (ei) is not detached, there 
exists a (non-empty) S c / with ^ ft(ei) < v(S). Besides, always 

tin S 

fti(ci) > fti. So ft (ci) H . And ft (1) is in V, hence a fortiori in W. 

Assume, finally, *i > and ft (*0 not in V. As ft (i) is in E(e<>) t there 
exists an a ^ ( l ) in (the solution for E(e*)) V. Since always ft i(i) > ft, 

a H (ei) implies a ^ ft by (45 :J). And a is in V, hence a fortiori in W. 
(45:18) happens first, or simultaneously with (45:17), say for = ej ^ 0: 

ft (j) is still in F(e ), and it is detached. 

If 7(s) is in J(e ), then it is by (45 :G) in (the solution for ()) V. 
If 6 (e 2 ) is not in #(e ), then it is in D*(e ). So ft (* 2 ) is at any rate in W. 




1 I.e. the excess of ft () is - c . For (0) - is in F(c ), i.e. its excess b e , 

* 
and the excess of (e) increases with , 

I.e. 5) 0,(e) vOS)forallS7. Each ft (t) increases with c. 



% in S in S 



380 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

This excludes c s == 0, since ft = ft (0) is not in W. So 61 > 0. 
For < < i, ft (e) is not detached, so there exists a non-empty 8 / 
with 2 0*W < V OS)- Hence there exists by continuity a non-empty 



S / even with &() v(S). Besides, always ftfo) > ft, hence 



(i) H - And () belongs to W. 

Summing up: In every case there exists an a H ft in W. (This a was 
* * 
a , ft (ci), a , (ej) above, respectively.) So (44:E:b) is fulfilled. 

We can now give the promised proof: 

Proof of (45:1): Immediate, by combining (45 :L), (45:M), (45:N). 

45.6. Summary and Conclusions 
46.6.1. Our main results, obtained so far, can be summarized as follows: 

(45:0) If 

(45:O:a) e < -|r|i, 

then U(e ), F(e Q ) are empty and the empty set is their only 
solution. 
If 

(45:0:b) -|r|i e ^ |r|, f 



then J5(e ), ^(^o) are not empty, both have the same solutions, 
which are all not empty. 
If 

(45:0:c) e Q > |r|,, 

then E(eo), F(e ) are not empty, they have no solution in common, 
all their solutions are not empty. 

Proof: Immediate by combining (45: A), (45:1) and (45 :H). 

This result makes the critical character of the points e<> = |F|i, |r|* 
quite clear and it further strengthens the views expressed at the end of 
45.1. and following (45 :H) in 45.4.2. concerning these points: That it is here 
where 60 becomes "too small" or "too large " in the sense of 44.6.1. 

46.6.2. We are also able now to prove some relations which will be useful 
later (in 46.5.). 

(45 :P) Let W be a non-empty solution for F(e ), i.e. assume that 

eo -|r|i. Then 

(45:P:a) Max-. e( O = e 

*" iii iff 



DETERMINATION OF ALL SOLUTIONS 381 

(45:P:b) Min- ^ w e (7) - Min (., |r|,). 

Also 
(45:P:c) Max-* . e(~a) - Min- . e(a) = Max (0, e - |r|,). 

** in TT ot in iff 

Proof: (45:Prc) follows from (45:P:a), (45:P:b) since 
e - Min (e , |T| 2 ) = Max (e - e , e - |r| 2 ) = Max (0, e - |r| 2 ). 
We now prove (45:P:a), (45:P:b). 

Write W = VuD*(e ), V a solution for J0(e ), following (45:1). As 

e Q ^ |r|i, so Vis not empty (by (45: A) or (45:0)). As we know e( a) = e 

throughout V and e( a) < e throughout D*(e ). 

Now for e ^ |T| 2 , D*(6 ) is empty (by (45 :H)), so 

(45:19) Max-* . e(a) = Max-* . w e(a) = , 

in W a m V 

(45:20) Min- . e(T) = Min- . w e("^) = . 

in w a m V 

And for e Q > |T| 2 , D*(e ) is not empty (again by (45:H)), it is the set of all 

> 

detached a with e( a ) < e . Hence by (45:B:b) in 45.2.3. these e( a ) have 

a minimum, |T| 2 . So we have in this case: 

(45:19*) Max-. w/ e(2 ) = Max-. w e(2) = , 

in W in V 



(45:20*) Min 7 ^ w e() = Min-. fa ^^ e() = |r|,. 

(45:19), (45:19*) together give our (45:P:a), and (45:20), (45:20*) give 
together our (45:P:b). 

46. Determination of All Solutions in a Decomposable Game 
46.1. Elementary Properties of Decompositions 

46.1.1. Let us now return to the decomposition of a game T. 
Let F be decomposable for J, K( I J) with A, H as its J-, IC-con- 
stituents. 

Given any extended imputation a = (ai, , <x} for 7, we form its 

J-, ^-constituents ft , 7 (ft = a, for i in J, 7^ = a for i in K), and their 
excesses 

1 Our assertion includes the claim that these Max %w , and Min . exist. 

in W in W 

1 Verbally: The maximum excess in the solution W is the maximum excess allowed in 
FMi o. The minimum excess in the solution W is again c , unless e > |r|t, in which 
case it is only |r|t. I.e. the minimum is as nearly e as possible, considering that it must 
never exceed |r| t . 

The "width" of the interval of excesses in W ia the excess of e over IrU, if any. 



382 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 



(46:1) 



Excess of a. in /: e = e( a ) = ] a 

t-i 



Excess of ft in J: / = /( a ) = J/ a ~~ v (^)> 

tin/ 

Excess of 7 in JRC: g = g( a) = ]? a v(X). 1 

tin X 

Since 

(46:2) v(J) + v(K) = v(7) 

(by (42:6 :b) in 42.3.2., or equally by (41:6) in 41.3.2. with S = J, T = K) 

therefore 

(46:3) e=f + g 

(46 :A) We have 

(46:A:a) |r|i = |A|i + |H|i, 

(46:A:b) |r| 2 = |A|, + JHJ 2 . 

(46 :A :c) F is inessential if and only if A, H are both inessential. 

Proof: Ad (46:A:a): Apply the definition (45:2) in 45.1. to T, A, H ir 
turn. 

(46:4) |r|i = v(7) - v((t)), 

tin / 

(46:5) |A|i = v(J) - v((i)), 

t in J 

(46:6) |H|, = v(K) - % v((i)). 

Comparing (46:4) with the sum of (46:5) and (46:6) gives (46:A:a), owing t< 
(46:2). 

Ad (46:A:b): Let ~2, ~P , y be as above (before (46:1)). Then a i: 
detached (in /) if 

2) a, S v(R) for all R S 7. 

tin R 

Recalling (4t:6) in 41.3.2. we may write for this 

/ A G. f 7\ \^ \ \^ "^ /C\ I ,~/fTi\ **.-* 11 C r~ T H^ r V 

(4o:7; 2/ a i 2/ a * v w) + v \^ ) * or a " o /, 1 IK. 

t in S t in r 

Again , 7 are detached (in J, X) if 

(46:8) % a, ^ v(S) for all SsJ, 

iin S 

(46:9) J) a, ^ v(T) for all TsX. 

tinT 

1 Up to this point it was not necessary to give explicit expression to the dependenc 
of a 's excess e upon a . We do this now.for e as well as for/, g. 



DETERMINATION OF ALL SOLUTIONS 383 

Now (46 :7) is equivalent to (46 :8) , (46 :9) . Indeed : (46 :7) obtains by adding 
(46:8) and (46:9); and (46:7) specializes for T = to (46:8) and for S = 9 
to (46:9). 

Thus a is detached, if and only if its (/-, K-) constituents ft , 7 are both 
detached. As their excesses e and /, g are correlated by (46:3), this gives 
for their minima (cf. (45:B:b)) 

|r|, = |A| 2 + |H| 2 , 

i.e. our formula (46:A:b). 

Ad (46:A:c): Immediate by combining (46:A:a) or (46:A:b) with (45 :E) 
as applied to F, A, H. 

The quantities |r|i, |F| 2 are both quantitative measures of the essentiality 
of the game F, in the sense of 45.3.1. Our above result states that both are 
additive for the composition of games. 

46.1.2. Another lemma which will be useful in our further discussions: 

> > 
(46 :B) If a H ft (for F), then the set S of 30.1.1. for this domination 

can be chosen with S J or S K without any loss of generality. l 

Proof: Consider the set S of 30.1.1. for the domination a H ft. If 
accidentally S Si J or S K, then there is nothing to prove, so we may 
assume that neither S J nor S K. Consequently S = Si u Ti, where 
Si /, Ti S K, and neither Si nor T\ is empty. 

We have a > ft for all i in S, i.e. for all i in Si, as well as for all i in T\. 

Finally 

2 at ^ v(S). 

tin 8 

The left hand side is clearly equal to ^ a + ^ a, while the right hand 

* in Si t in TI 

side is equal to v(Si) + v(Ti) by (41:6) in 41.3.2. Thus 



i in Si 

hence at least one of 



in S l t in 2*, 

must be true. 

> 
Thus of the three conditions of domination in 30.1.1. (for a ^ ft ) 

(30:4:a), (30:4:c) holds for both of Si, TI and (30:4:b) for at least one of 
them. Hence, we may replace our original S by either Si (s J) or Ti(fi -K"). 
This completes the proof. 

1 I.e. this extra restriction on S does not (in this case!) modify the concept of 
domination. 



384 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

46.2. Decomposition and Its Relation to the Solutions: First Results Concerning F(e ) 

46.2.1. We now direct our course towards the main objective of this 
part of the theory: The determination of all solutions U/ of the decomposable 
game T. This will be achieved in 46.6., concluding a chain of seven lemmas. 

We begin with some purely descriptive observations. 

Consider a solution U/ for F(e ) of T. If U/ is empty, there is nothing 
more to say. Let us assume, therefore, that U/ is not empty owing to 
(45: A) (or equally to (45:0)) this is equivalent to 



Using the notations of (46:1) in 46.1.1. we form: 

Max-. ./() = *>, 

a m U/ 

Min-* . , , /( a ) = p, 

in U/ 
(46:10) 

'Max-. flf() = ft 
m U/ 

inU,^ )= *-' 

1 That all these quantities can be formed, i.e. that the maxima and the minima in 
question exist and are assumed, can be ascertained by a simple continuity consideration. 

Indeed /( a ) 2/ a ~~ v (^) and 0r( a ) = 2^ a v(K) are both continuous 

' in J i in X 

functions of a , i.e. of its components 01, , . The existence of their maxima and 
minima is therefore a well known consequence of the continuity properties of the domain 


of a the set U/. 

For the reader who is acquainted with the necessary mathematical background 
topology we give the precise statement and its proof. (The underlying mathematical 
facts are discussed e.g. by C. Carathtodory, loc. cit., footnote 1 on p. 343. Cf. there 
pp. 136-140, particularly theorem 5). 

U/ is a set in the n-dimensional linear space L n (Cf. 30.1.1.). In order to be sure 
that every continuous function has a maximum and a minimum in U/, we must know that 
U/ is bounded and closed. 

Now we prove: 
(*) Any solution U for F(e ) [E(e Q )] of an n-person game r is a bounded and closed 

set in L n . 

Proof: Boundedness: If a {on, , <x) belongs to U, then every a, 2> v((i)) 

n 

and 2/ ~ v(7) =s o, hence a, ^ v(7) + e Q 2} / ^ V CO + *o ^ v((t)). 
So each is restricted to the fixed interval 

and so these a form a bounded set. 

Closedness: This is equivalent to the openness of the complement of U. That set is, 

> > 

by (30:5:c) in 30.1.1., the set of all which are dominated by any a of U* (Observe 



DETERMINATION OF ALL SOLUTIONS 385 

Given two a = {!, - , a n j, ft = {ft, , n } there exists a 

> > 

unique 7 = {71, , -y n } which has the same J-component as a , and 

the same JC-component as ft : 

(4Q.H) 7. = for tin/, 

7 = ft for i in K. 

46.2.2. We now prove: 

(46 :C) If ^T, V belong to U/, then the V of (46:11) belongs to U/ 

if and only if 

(46:C:a) /(*)+ 0(7) S o. 

Incidentally 

(46:C:b) 6(7) =/U)+0(7). 

Proo/: Formula (46:C:b): By (46:3) in 46.1.1. e(V) = /(V) + 0(V), 

and clearly /( 7 )=/(), j( 7 ) = fif(7)- 

* 
Necessity of (46:C:a): Since U/fif^o), therefore e(y) ^ e is neces- 

sary and by (46:C:b) this coincides with (46:C:a). 

Sufficiency of (46:C:a): y is clearly an extended imputation, along 
with a , ft , and (46:C:a), (46:C:b) guarantee that y belongs to F(e ). 1 

Now assume that y is not in U/. Then there exists a 8 H 7 in U/. 

The set /S of 30.1.1. for this domination may be chosen by (46 :B) with 

> 

Now clearly 5 H 7 implies, when S J that 6 H a , 



that we are introducing the solution character of U at this point!) 

For any a denote the set of all H a by D-+. Then the complement of U is 

> <* 

the sum of all -, a of U. 

a 

Since the sum of any number (even of infinitely many) open sets is again open, it 
suffices to prove the openness of each D-+, i.e. this: If ft ^ a , then for every ft ' 

a 

which is sufficiently near to ft , we have also ft ' H a . Now in the definition of dom- 

* > -> 

ination, ft ^ a by (30:4:a)-(30:4:c)in30.1.1., appears in the condition (30:4 :c) only. 
And the validity of (30:4:c) is clearly not impaired by a sufficiently small change of 0<, 
since (30:4 :c) is a < relation. 

(Note that the same is not true for a , because a appears in (30:4:b) also, and 
(30:4:b) might be destroyed by arbitrary small changes, since (30:4:b) is a ^ relation. 

But we needed this property for ft , and not for a !) 
1 This is the only use of (46:C:a). 



386 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

and when S K that d ^ ft . As 5 , a , ft belong to U/, both alterna- 
tives are impossible. 

Hence 7 must belong to U/> as asserted. 

We restate (46 :C) in an obviously equivalent form: 

(46 :D) Let V/ be the set of all /-constituents and Wx the set of all 

If -constituents of U/. 

Then U/ obtains from these V/ and Wx as follows: 

U/ is the set of all those y , which have a /-constituent a ' 
in V/ and a /^-constituent ft ' in W* such that 

(46:12) e( O + e(7') ^ e Q . 1 

46.3. Continuation 

46.3. Recalling the definition of U/'s decomposability (for/, /) in (44 :B) 
in 44.3.1., one sees with little difficulty, that it is equivalent to this: 

U/ obtains from the V/, Wx of (46 :D) as outlined there, but without 
the condition (46:12). 

Thus (46:12) may be interpreted as expressing just to what extent U/ 
is not decomposable. This is of some interest in the light of what was said 
in 44.3.3. about (44:D:a) there. 

One may even go a step further: The necessity of (46:12) in (46 :D) is 
easy to establish. (It corresponds to (46:C:a), i.e. to the very simple first 
two steps in the proof of (46 :C)). Hence (46 :D) expresses that U/ is no 
further from decomposability, than unavoidable. 

All this, in conjunction with (44:D:b) in 44.3.3., suggests strongly that 
V/, WK ought to be solutions of A, H. With our present extensions of all 
concepts it is necessary, however, to decide which F(/o), F(go) to take; 
/o being the excess we propose to use in /, and go the one in K. 2 It will 
appear that the p, # of 46.2.1. are these /o, g<>. 

Indeed, we can prove: 

(46 :E) 

(46:E:a) V/ is a solution of A for 

(46:E:b) W/c is a solution of H for 

It is convenient, however, to derive first another result: 

1 Note that these a ', ' are not the a , ft of (46 :C) they are their /-, K-constit- 
uents as well as those of y . e( a ; ), e( ft ') are the excesses of a ', ft ' formed in /, 

K. But they are equal to /( a ), g( ft ) as well as to /( 7 ), g( y ). (All of this is related 
to (46:C)). 

* The reader will note that this is something like a question of distributing the given 
excess e in / between / and K. 



DETERMINATION OF ALL SOLUTIONS 387 

(46:F) 

(46:F:a) p + = e , 

(46:F:b) $ + } = e . 

Note that in (46 :E), as well as in (46 :F), the parts (a), (b) obtain from 
each other by interchanging J, A, p, f with K t H, #, $ . Hence it suffices to 
prove in each case only one of (a), (b) we chose (a). 

> 

Proof of (46:F:a): Choose an a in U/ for which /( a ) assumes its maxi- 

* . * 

mum p . Since necessarily e( a ) ^ e > and since by definition g( a. ) ^ , 

therefore (46:3) in 46.1.1. gives 

(46:13) $ + $ e . 

Assume now that (46:F:a) is not true. Then (46:13) would imply 
further 

(46:14) 9 + < 6 . 

Use the above a in U/ with /( a ) = p, and chose also a in U/ for which 
0( ) assumes its minimum . Then /( a ) + 0( ) = 9 + ^^00 (by 

(46:13) or (46:14)). Thus the V of (46 :C) belongs to U/, too, Again 
(46 :C) together with (46:14) gives 

e(y) - /(") + |/(7) = 9 + * < o, 

n 

i.e. ^ 7i < v(7) + e . Now define 
t-i 


5 = {i, ,} = {71 + >'> 7 + c), 

n ^ 

choosing > so that 5< = v(/) + e . Thus 6 belongs to F(e ). 
-i 

If 6 did not belong to U/, then an TJ H. 5 would exist in U/. By 

> ^ > 

(45 :J) t? H 7 , which is impossible, since y , 7 are both in U/. Hence 

7 belongs to U/. Now 8 - v(J) > ^ 7 ~ v(J) = ^ a, - v(J), 

t in J iinJ i in / 

i.e. /( d ) > /( a ) = ?, contradicting the definition of p. 

Consequently (46:F:a) must be true and the proof is completed. 

Proof of (46:E:a) : If a ' belongs to V/j> then it is the J-constituent of an 

7 of U/. Hence (cf. footnote 1 on p. 386) e( a ') =* /( a ) g ?, so that a ' 
belongs to F($). Thus V/ 



388 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

So our task is to prove (44:E:a), (44:E:b) of 44.7.3. 

> 

Ad (44:E:a): Assume, that a ' H ft ' happened for two a ', ' in V/. 

> > > > > 

Then a ', ' are the J-constituents of two 7 , 5 in U/. But a ' H ' 

> 
clearly implies 7 *< 6 , which is impossible. 

Ad (44:E:b) : Consider an a ' in F(<p) but not in V/. Then by definition 
> 

e( a ') g . Use the in U/ mentioned in the above proof of (46:F:a), 



for which g( ) = . Let ' be the jfiC-constituent of this ft , so that 

~ft' is in W* and e(T') = gCft) = f Thus 6(T') + e(7') ^ ^ + i = e 
(use (46:F:a)). Form the y (for /), which has the J-, ^-constituents 
"^', T' Then e( 7 ) = e( a ') + e(]*') e Q i.e. ~y belongs to F(e Q ). 

y does not belong to U/ because its /-constituent a ' does not belong 
to V/. Hence, there exists a d H y in (the solution for F(e )) U/. 

Let S be the set of 30.1.1. for the domination 5 H y . By (46 :B) we 
may assume that S s J or S c K. 

Assume first that S K . As y has the same Jf-constituents ft ' as 

ft , we can conclude from d H 7 that 5 H . Since both 5 , 
belong to U/, this is impossible. 

Consequently SsJ. Denote the J-constituent of d by 6'; as 6 
belongs to U/, therefore 6 ' belongs to V/. 7 has the J-constituent a '. 
Hence we can conclude from 6 H 7 that 5 ' H a '. 

Thus we have the desired 6 ' from V/ with 5 ' H a '. 

46.4. Continuation 

46.4.1. (46 :D), (46 :E) expressed the general solution U/ of T in terms 
of appropriate solutions of V/, Wx of A, H. It is natural, therefore, to 
try to reverse this procedure: To start with the V/, W* and to obtain U/. 

It must be remembered, however, that the V/, W* of (46 :D) are not 
entirely arbitrary. If we reconsider the definitions (46:10) of 46.2.1. in 
this light of (46 :D), then we see that they can also be stated in this form: 



(46:15) 



DETERMINATION OF ALL SOLUTIONS 389 

And (46 :F) expresses a relationship of these p, tf>, #, which are determined 
by V/, W/c with each other and with e . 

46.4.2. We will show that this is the only restraint that must be imposed 
upon the V/, W*. To do this, we start with two arbitrary non-empty 
solutions V/i W/c of A, H (which need not have been obtained from any 
solution U/ of T), and assert as follows: 

(46 :G) Let V/ be a non-empty solution of A for F($) and Wx a non- 

empty solution of H for F(#). Assume that p, ^ fulfill (46:15) 
above, and also that with the ^>, ^ of (46:15) 

(46:16) + = ? + = eo . 

> 

For any a ' of V/ and any ft ' of W/c with 

(46:17) (O+e(7') 60, 

form the 7 (for /) which has the 7-, ^-components a ', '. 

> 

Denote the set of all these 7 by U/. 

The U/ which are obtained in this way are precisely all 
solutions of F for F(e ). 

Proof: All U/ of the stated character are obtained in this way: Apply 
(46 :D) to U/ forming its V/, W/c. Then all our assertions are contained in 
(46:D), (46:E), (46:F) together with (46:15). 

All U/ obtained in this way have the stated character: Consider an U/ 
constructed with the help of V/, W/c as described above. We have to 
prove that this U/ is a solution T for F(e Q ). 

For every 7 of U/ our (46:17) gives e( y ) = e( a ') + e( ft ') ^ e , so 



that belongs to F(e<>). Thus U; <= F( 

So our task is to prove (44:E:a), (44:E:b) of 44.7.3. 

Ad (44:E:a): Assume that rj H y happened for two i? , y in U/. 
Let a ', ' be the /-, K-constituents of 7 and 6 ', 6 ' the J-, X-con- 
stituents of 77 from which they obtain as described above. Let S be the 

set of 30.1.1. for the domination y H y . By (46 :B) we may assume that 

> > 

S c J or S Si K. Now S c J would cause T; H 7 to imply 5 ' H a ', 

which is impossible, since 6 ', a ' both belong to V/; and S X would 

cause if H 7 to imply ' H /3 ' which is impossible, since e ', ' both 

belong to W*. 

> 
Ad (44:E:b): Assume per absurdum, the existence of a 7 in F(e ) but 

> 

not in U/, such that there is no 17 of U/ with 17 H 7 . Let a ', ' be the 

/-, It-constituents of 7 



390 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 



Assume first e( a ') ^ <f>. Then a' belongs to F(p). Consequently 
either a ' belongs to V/ or there exists a 6 ' in V/ with 5 ' H a '. In the 
latter case choose an 6 ' in Wx for which e( ') assumes its minimum value . 
Form the 17 with the /-, /^-constituents 5 ', '. As 6 ', e ' belong to 
V/, W*, respectively, and as e( d ') + e(* ') g + = e , therefore i? 
belongs to U/. Besides T; H y owing to 6 ' H a ' (these being their J- 
constituents). Thus 17 contradicts our original assumption concerning y . 

Hence we have demonstrated, for the case under consideration, that a ' 
must belong to V/. 
In other words: 

(46:18) Either ~' belongs to V/, or e(7') > ?. 

Observe that in the first case necessarily e( a ') ^ <f>, and of course 
in the second case e( a ') > ^ <p. Consequently: 

(46:19) At any rate e( a. ') ^ ^>. 

Interchanging J and K carries (46:18), (46:19) into these: 

(46:20) Either ~f$ r belongs to Wx or e( V') > # 

(46:21) At any rate e(~^ f ) ^ ^. 

Now if we had the second alternative of (46:18), then this gives in con- 
junction with (46:21) 

e(7) = e( O + e(7') > ^ + ^ = c , 

which is impossible, as y belongs F(ed). The second alternative of (46:20) 
is equally impossible. 

Thus we have the first alternatives in both (46:18) and (46:20), i.e. 



a ', ft ' belong to V/, W*. As y belongs to F(e ), therefore 

e(~O + e(7 ; ) = e(7) ^ e . 
Consequently 7 must belong to U/ contradicting our original assumption. 

46.5. The Complete Result in F(e Q ) 

46.5.1. The result (46 :G) is, in spite of its completeness, unsatisfactory 
in one respect: The conditions (46:16) and (46:17) on which it depends are 
altogether implicit. We will, therefore, replace them by equivalent, but 
much more transparent conditions. 



DETERMINATION OF ALL SOLUTIONS 391 

To do this, we begin with the numbers <p, $ which we assume to be given 
first. Which solutions V/, W* of A, H for F(p), F(#) can we then use in 
the sense of (46 :G)? 

First of all, V/, W* must be non-empty; application of (45: A) or (45:0) 
to A, H (instead of F) shows that this means 

(46:22) * -|A|i, # -|H|i. 

Consider next (46:15). Apply (45:P) of 45.6.1. to A, H (instead of T). 
Then (45:P:a) secures the two Max-equations of (46:15), while (45:P:b) 
transforms the two Min-equations of (46:15) into 

(46:23) $ = Min (?, |A| 2 ), * = Min (}, |H| 2 ). 

Let us, therefore, define v>, \l/ by (46:23). 
Now we express (46:16), i.e. 

(46:16) + ^ = _<, + = e . 

The first equation of (46:16) may also be written as 

- <P = # - ^, 
i.e. by (46:23) 

(46:24) Max (0, ? - |A| 2 ) = Max (0, # - |H| 2 ). 1 

46.5.2. Now two cases are possible: 

Case (a): Both sides of (46:24) are zero. Then in each Max of (46:24) 
the 0-term is ^ than the other term, i.e. <p |A| 2 ^ 0, # |H| 2 ^ 0, i.e., 

(46:25) ? ^ |A| 2 , ^ |H|,. 

Conversely: If (46:25) holds, then (46:24) becomes = 0, i.e. it is auto- 
matically satisfied. Now the definition (46 :23) becomes 

(46:26) ? = v, ^ = ^, 

and so the full condition (46:16) becomes 2 
(46:27) ? + * = e Q . 

(46:25) and (46:27) give also 
(46:28) e g |A| 2 + |H| 2 = |r| 2 . 

Case (b): Both sides of (46:24) are not zero. Then in each Max of 
(46:24) the 0-term is < than the other term i.e. ? - |A| 2 > 0,# - |H|, > 0, 
i.e. 
(46:29) ? > |A| 2 , # > |H| 2 .' 

1 Cf. (45:P:c) and its proof. 

1 Of which we used only the first part to obtain (46:24), on which this discussion is 
based. 

1 Note that the important point is that (46:25), (46:29) exhaust all possibilities i.e. 
that we cannot have * |A| a , $ > |H| 2 , or * > |A|i, ? |H|j. This is, of course, due to 
the equation (46:24), which forces that both sides vanish or neither. 
The meaning of this will appear in the lemmas which follow. 



392 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

Conversely: If (46:29) holds, then (46:24) becomes $ - |A| 2 = # -|H|, 
i.e. it is not automatically satisfied. We can express (46:24) by writing 

(46:30) ? * |A|i + , # = |H| 2 + o>, 

and then (46:29) becomes simply 

(46:31) co > 0. 

Now the definition (46:23) becomes 

(46:32) ? = |A| 2 , * = |H| 2 , 

and so the full condition (46:16)* becomes 

|A| 2 + |H|t + co = 6 , 
i.e. 

(46:33) e = |r| 2 + w. 

(46:31) and (46:33) give also 
(46:34) 6 > |F| 2 . 

46.6.3. Summing up : 

(46 :H) The conditions (46:16), (46:17) of (46 :G) amount to this: 

One of the two following cases must hold: 
Case (a): (1) -|r|i e |r|, 

together with 

(2) -|A|I*S |A|,, 

[(3) -|H|i**S|H|,, 

and 

(4) 9 + * = .- 

Case (b): (1) e, > |r|,, 

together with 

(2) P > |A|i, 

(3) * > |H| J( 
and 

(4) 6 - |r|, = 9 - |A|t = * ~ |H|,. 

Proo/: Case (a): We knew all along, that 6 ^ |r|i and <f> ^ |A|i, 
^ ^ -|H|i. The other conditions coincide with (46:28), (46:25), (46:27) 
which contain the complete description of this case. 

Case (b): These conditions coincide with (46:34), (46:29), (46:30), 
(46:33) which contain the complete description of the case (after elimination 
of w which subsumes (46:31) under (l)-(3)). 

1 Cf. footnote 2 on p. 391. 

1 The reader will note that while (l)-(3) for (a) and for (b) show a strong analogy, 
the final condition (4) is entirely different for (a) and for (b). Nevertheless, all this was 
obtained by the rigorous discussion of one consistent theory! 
More will be said about this later. 



DETERMINATION OF ALL SOLUTIONS 393 

46.6. The Complete Result in E(e ) 

46.6. (46 :G) and (46 :H) characterize the solutions of T for F(e ) in a 
complete and explicit way. It is now apparent, too, that the cases (a), (b) 
of (46 :H) coincide with (45:0:b), (45:0:c) in 45.6.1.: Indeed (a), (b) of 
(46 :H) are distinguished by their conditions (1), and these are precisely 
(45:O:b), (45:O:c). 

We now combine the results of (46 :G), (46 :H) with those of (45:1), 
(45:0). This will give us a comprehensive picture of the situation, utilizing 
all our information. 

(46:1) If 

(46:I:a) (1) eo < -|r|i, 

then the empty set is the only solution of r, for E(e ) as well as 
for F(e 9 ). 

If 
(46:1 :b) (1) -|r|i ^ e |r|,, 

then T has the same solutions O/ for E(e Q ) and for F(e ). These 
O/ are precisely those sets, which obtain in the following manner: 
Choose any two p, # so that 

(2) -|A|i ^ p |A| 2 , 

(3) -|H|i ^* g |H| 2 , 
and 

(4) ? + # = eo. 

Choose any two solutions V/, W* of A, H for JE(p), E($). 
Then U/ is the composition of V/ and WK in the sense of 
44.7.4. 
If 
(46:I:c) (1) e > |r| 2 , 



then F does not have the same solutions O/ for E(e^) and U/ for 
F(e ). These O/ and U/ are precisely those sets which obtain 
in the following manner: Form the two numbers , # with 

(2) 9 > |A|i, 

(3) f > |H| 2 , 
which are defined by 

(4) eo - |r| 2 = 9 - |A|, = * - |H| 2 . 

Choose any two solutions V/, WK of A, H for E(v), E$). 
Then O/ is the sum of the following sets: The composition of 

V/ and of the set of all detached 7 ' (in K) with e(ft ') = |H| a ; the 



composition of the set of all detached a ' (in J) with e( a ') = |A|* 



394 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

and of WA:; the composition of the set of all detached a ' (in J) 



with e( a ') = <p and of the set of all detached ' (in K) with 

e( ft ') = ^, taking all pairs ^>, ^ with 

(5) |A| 2 < *, < 9, |H|i < * < *, 
and 

(6) ? + ^ = e . 

U/ obtains by the same process, only replacing the condition (6) 
by 

(7) ? + * g 6 . 

Proo/: Ad (46:I:a): This coincides with (45:O:a). 

Ad (46:I:b): This is a restatement of case (a) in (46 :H) except for the 
following modifications: 

First: The identification of the E and F solutions for F, A, H. This is 
justified by applying (45:O:b) to F, A, H which is legitimate by (1), (2), (3) 
of (46:I:b). 

Second: The way in which we formed O/ = U/ from V/ = V/, W/c = Wx 
which differed from the one described in (46 :H) insofar as we omitted 
the condition (46:17). This is justified by observing that (46:17) is 
automatically fulfilled: V/ = Vj #(?), W* = W* E($), hence for 

a ' in V/ and ft ' in W* always e( a. ') = 9, e( ft ') = # and so by (4) 

e( O + (7') = *o. 

Ad (46:I:c): This is a restatement of case (b) in (46 :H), except for this 
modification: 

We consider both E and F solutions for F (not only F solutions as in 
(46:H)), and use only E solutions for A, H (not F solutions as in (46:H)). 
The way in which the former O/, U/ of F are formed from the latter (Vj of 
A, Wx of H) is accordingly different from the one described in (46 :H). 

In order to remove these differences, one has to proceed as follows: 
Apply (45:1) and (45:O:c) to F, A, H which is legitimate by (1), (2), (3) 
of (46:I:c). Then substitute the defining for the defined in (46 :H). If these 
manipulations are carried out on (46 :H) (in the present case (46:I:c)), then 
precisely our above formulation results. l 

46.7. Graphical Representation of a Part of the Result 

46.7. The results of (46:1) may seem complicated, but they are actually 
only the precise expression of several simple qualitative principles. The 
reason for going through the intricacies of the preceding mathematical 
derivation was, of course, that these principles are riot at all obvious, and 
that this is the way to discover and to prove them. On the other hand our 
result can be illustrated by a simple graphical representation. 

1 If the reader carries this out, he will see that this transformation, although somewhat 
cumbersome, presents absolutely no difficulty. 



DETERMINATION OF ALL SOLUTIONS 



395 



We begin with a more formalistic remark. 

A look at the three cases (46:I:a)-(46:I:c) discloses this: While nothing 
more can be said about (46:I:a), the two other cases (46:I:b), (46:I:c) 
have some common features. Indeed, in both instances the desired solu- 
tions O/, U/ of F are obtained with the help of two numbers , # and certain 
corresponding solutions V/, W* of A, H. The quantitative elements of the 
representation of O/, U/ are the numbers , #. As was pointed out in foot- 
note 2 on p. 386, they represent something like a distribution of the given 
excess e in / between J and K. 




Figure 69. 

, # are characterized in the cases (46:I:b) and (46:I:c) by their respec- 
tive conditions (2)-(4). Let us compare these conditions for (46:I:b) and 
for (46:I:c). 

They have this common feature : They force the excesses , # to belong 
to the same case of A, H as the one to which the excess e belongs for r. 

They differ, however, very essentially in this respect: In (46:I:b) they 
impose only one equation upon , # while in (46 :1 :c) they impose two equa- 
tions. 1 Of course, the inequalities too, may degenerate occasionally to 
equations (cf. (46:J) in 46.8.3.), but the general situation is as indicated. 

The connections between e and p, # are represented graphically by 
Fig. 69. 



1 (2), (3) are inequalities in both cases, 
for two equations in (46:I:c). 



(4) stands for one equation in (46:I:b) and 



396 COMPOSITION AND DECOMPOSITION OF GAMES 

This figure shows the p, #-plane and under it the 6o-line. On the latter 
the points -|r|i, |r|i mark the division into the three zones corresponding 
to cases (46:I:a)-(46:I:c). The <?>, ^-domain which belongs to case (46:I:b) 
covers the shaded rectangle marked (b) in the p, #-plane; the , ^-domain, 
which belongs to case (46:I:c) covers the line marked (c) in the p, ^-plane. 

Given any $, #-point, following the line leads to its e value 

thus 6, V yield a, a', respectively. Given any e -value the reverse process 
discloses all its 9, ^-points, thus a produces an entire interval at 6, while 
a' yields the unique point b'. 1 

46.8. Interpretation : The Normal Zone. Heredity of Various Properties 

46.8.1. Figure 69 calls for further comments, which are conducive to a 
fuller understanding of (46:1). 

First: There have been repeated indications (for the last time in the com- 
ment following (45:0)), that the cases (46:I:a) and (46:I:c), i.e. e < -| r k 
and 60 > |F|j, respectively are the "too small" or "too large" values of e 
in the sense of 44.6.1.; i.e., that case (46:I:b), |F|i ^ e g |r| 2 , is in some 
way the normal zone. Now our picture shows that when the excess e 
of F lies in the normal zone, then the corresponding excesses , # of A, 
H lie also within their respective normal zones. 2 In other words: 

The normal behavior (position of the excess in (46:I:b)) is hereditary from 
T to A, H. 

Second: In the case (46:I:b) the normal zone <f>, $ are not completely 
determined by eo, as we repeatedly saw before. In case (46:I:c), on the 
other hand, they are. This is pictured by the fact that the former domain 
is the rectangle (b) in the <p, #-plane, while the latter domain is only a line (c). 

It is worth noting, howe